Skip to main content
Log in

The presence of the past: Negotiating the politics of collective memory

  • Feature Article: Theory and Practice
  • Published:
Contemporary Political Theory Aims and scope

Abstract

What are the political implications of a complex image of time, where time does not unfold progressively in a neat linear structure, but where the past is always present and the future impinges on the now? If the past is inescapably present, how do societies that live with grievously injured pasts come to terms with them in the present for the sake of the future? How do they try to address the collective memories of their people, when such memories are marked by violence and conflict, without resorting to vengeance? Drawing from the philosophical writings of Friedrich Nietzsche, this article examines the way in which two countries have recently attempted to negotiate the politics of memory – Algeria and Rwanda. It poses such questions as how much should be forgotten and how much should be remembered? It also asks the difficult question of how such pasts can be overcome and transfigured in the present for the sake of the politics of an affirmative politics of the future.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. For Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche's concept of Eternal Return contains within it a vital note of difference. As he writes in Difference and Repetition, for him, ‘the subject of the eternal return is not the same but the different, not the similar but the dissimilar, not the one but the many’ (Deleuze, 1995, 126). For Heidegger, Eternal Return is the return of the same. It re-inscribes being into philosophy, instead of becoming, and betrays Nietzsche's inability to escape Western metaphysics. As one commentator has written, for Heidegger, Eternal Return represents Nietzsche's most ‘telling defeat’ and argues that Heidegger's interpretation of the doctrine might be a consequence of his underplaying of the Dionysian element in Nietzsche's thought, focusing instead on permanence (Gillespie, 1987, 430–431). However, Heidegger's analysis of the creative intervention required at the moment of recurrence highlights a key dimension in the doctrine and supplements Deleuze's affirmative account of Eternal Return, even as they depart from each other in their final assessment.

References

  • Bergson, H. (2002) The selection of images for conscious presentation. What our body means and does. Translated by N.M. Paul and W.S. Palmer. Matter and Memory. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, P. (2005) When the killers go home: Local justice in Rwanda. Dissent Magazine, Summer 2005.

  • Deleuze, G. (1983) Active and reactive. Translated by H. Tomlinson. Nietzsche & Philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1995) Repetition for itself. Translated by P. Patton. Difference & Repetition. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1997) Peaks of present and sheets of past. Translated by H. Tomlinson and R. Galeta Cinema 2: The Time-Image. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dienstag, J.F. (2004) Tragedy, pessimism, Nietzsche. New Literary History 35 (1): 87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faulkner, W. (1975) Requiem for a Nun. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillespie, M.A. (1987) Review: Heidegger's Nietzsche. Political Theory 15 (3): 430–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1979) The convalescent. Translated by D.F. Krell Nietzsche. Vol. II: The Eternal Recurrence of the Same. San Francisco, CA: Harpers & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Human Rights Watch. (2005) Impunity in the Name of Reconciliation. New York: Human Rights Watch, http://hrw.org/backgrounder/mena/algeria0905/index.htm.

  • Ignatieff, M. (1997) The elusive goal of war trials. Harper's Magazine 294 (1762), March 1997.

  • Nietzsche, F. (1968) Discipline and breeding. In: W. Kaufmann (ed.) and translated by W. Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale The Will to Power. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1978) On redemption. Translated by W. Kaufmann Thus Spoke Zarathustra. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1997) On the uses and disadvantages of history for life. Translated by R.J. Hollingdale Untimely Meditations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Slackman, M. (2005a) Top Algerians prefer amnesia to accountability on war. The New York Times 26 September.

  • Slackman, M. (2005b) But bygones can’t be bygones if the pain is raw. The New York Times 5 October.

  • Strain, J. and Keyes, E. (2003) Accountability for Atrocities in the aftermath of Rwanda's genocide. In: J.E. Stromseth (ed.) Accountability for Atrocities: National and International Responses. Ardsley, NY: Transnational Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • The Economist. (2005) A Flawed Charter, Vol. 337 (8447), 8 October.

  • Trouillot, M.-R. (1995) Silencing the past: Power and the production of history. In: The Power in the Story. Boston, MA: Beacon press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rahman, S. The presence of the past: Negotiating the politics of collective memory. Contemp Polit Theory 9, 59–76 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2008.44

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2008.44

Keywords

Navigation