Skip to main content
Log in

No Justice Without (Relational) Autonomy? Rethinking the Digital Empowerment Rhetoric

  • Commentary
  • Published:
Digital Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The current empowerment rhetoric that is discussed in digital health initiatives is problematic, Nickel et al. argue in a recent article that is published in this journal. They highlight social justice as a crucial value that should be re-engineered in this context. However, they do not take a stand on the relational meaning of autonomy. In this commentary, we instead claim that autonomy could better be conceptualized in relational terms as it brings into focus the importance of developing capabilities that can support self-determination. Such a conception of autonomy places greater emphasis on social justice concerns that mainstream bioethics tends to brush aside. Finally, we introduce the framework of Capability Sensitive Design as a better strategy to try to achieve empowerment through digital health.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. For instance, relational autonomy is also developed in Ubuntu ethics (Mhlambi & Tiribelli, 2023) or more Western-oriented ethical theories such as “care ethics, ethical multiculturalism, phenomenology, personalist ethics, relational ethics, virtue ethics, and different forms of political-philosophical approaches, such as communitarianism, liberalism, etc.” (Gómez-Vírseda et al., 2019, p. 12)

  2. Most applications remain free despite billions in venture capital funding being secured every year for digital health applications. See Somaiya et al. (2023) for an overview of annual venture capital funding. While many in the development team may have the primary aim of developing a quality health product, investors are more likely to be concerned with profits. This focus on profits may incentivize the development of lower quality “general wellness products” that are designed to amass a large subscriber base, whose information is then used to market for-pay products and services to (Simon et al., 2022).

  3. One such solution might come in the form of AI assistants that can assist a clinician in answering messages in online patient portals. ChatGPT, a non-medical AI assistant outperformed clinicians on metrics of both quality and empathy in responding to these message (Abbasi & Hswen, 2023). But it is not immediately obvious that this sort of solution will be utilized to help patients and broaden access. In some cases, clinicians can opt out of helping vulnerable patients (Krishnamurthy, 2023), and may instead use these AI assistants to reduce their own workloads as burnout and a shortfall of providers are pervasive throughout the healthcare industry.

References

  • Abbasi, J., & Hswen, Y. (2023). How AI assistants could help answer patients’ messages-and potentially improve their outcomes. JAMA. Advance online publication. https://doi.org/10.1001/jama.2023.22555.

  • Beauchamp, T. L., & Childress, J. F. (2019). Principles of biomedical ethics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Childress, J. F. (2017). Needed: A more rigorous analysis of models of decision making and a richer account of respect for autonomy. American Journal of Bioethics, 17(11), 52–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Childress, J. F. (2022). Respecting personal autonomy in bioethics: Relational autonomy as a corrective? In J. F. Childress & M. Quante (Eds.), Thick (concepts of) autonomy: Personal autonomy in ethics and bioethics (pp. 135–149). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cortés-Albornoz, M. C., Ramírez-Guerrero, S., García-Guáqueta, D. P., Vélez-Van-Meerbeke, A., & Talero-Gutiérrez, C. (2023). Effects of remote learning during COVID-19 lockdown on children’s learning abilities and school performance: A systematic review. International Journal of Educational Development, 101, 102835.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • De Proost, M., & Segers, S. (2023). Revisiting the ought implies can dictum in light of disruptive medical innovation. Journal of Medical Ethics. Advance online publication. https://doi.org/10.1136/jme-2023-108946.

  • Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gómez-Vírseda, C., De Maeseneer, Y., & Gastmans, C. (2019). Relational autonomy: What does it mean and how is it used in end-of-life care? A systematic review of argument-based ethics literature. BMC Medical Ethics, 20(1), 76.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Ho, A. (2022). Artificial intelligence as a feminist bioethics issue. In W. A. Rogers, J. L. Scully, S. M. Carter, V. A. Entwistle, & C. Mills (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of feminist bioethics (pp. 291–307). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hopster, J., & Löhr, G. (2023). Conceptual engineering and philosophy of technology: Amelioration or adaptation? Philosophy and Technology, 36(4), 70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, N. (2020). Capability sensitive design for health and wellbeing technologies. Science and Engineering Ethics, 26(6), 3363–3391.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, N., & Evers, J. (2023). Ethical perspectives on femtech: Moving from concerns to capability-sensitive designs. Bioethics, 37(5), 430–439.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kapeller, A., & Loosman, I. (2023). Empowerment through health self-testing apps? Revisiting empowerment as a process. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 26, 143–152.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kreitmair, K. V. (2023). Mobile health technology and empowerment. Bioethics. Advance online publication. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.13157.

  • Krishnamurthy, K. B. (2023). Should physicians be able to refuse to care for patients insured by medicare? AMA Journal of Ethics, 25(12), 861–865.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C. (2010). Conceptions of autonomy and conceptions of the body in bioethics. In J. L. Scully, L. Baldwin-Ragaven, & P. Fitzpatrick (Eds.), Feminist bioethics: At the center, on the margins (pp. 71–90). Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C. (2014). The importance of relational autonomy and capabilities for an ethics of vulnerability. In C. Mackenzie, W. Rogers, & S. Dodds (Eds.), Vulnerability: New essays in ethics and feminist philosophy (pp. 33–59). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C. (2019). Feminist innovation in philosophy: Relational autonomy and social justice. Women’s Studies International Forum, 72, 144–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, C., & Stoljar, N. (Eds.). (2000). Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency, and the social self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Mhlambi, S., & Tiribelli, S. (2023). Decolonizing AI ethics: Relational autonomy as a means to counter AI harms. Topoi, 42, 867–880.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morley, J., & Floridi, L. (2019). Enabling digital health companionship is better than empowerment. The Lancet Digital Health, 1(4), e155–e156.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Morley, J., & Floridi, L. (2020). The limits of empowerment: How to reframe the role of mHealth tools in the healthcare ecosystem. Science and Engineering Ethics, 26(3), 1159–1183.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, P. J., Loosman, I., Frank, L., & Vinnikova, A. (2023). Justice and empowerment through digital health: Ethical challenges and opportunities. Digital Society, 2(3), 42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quelly, S. B., Norris, A. E., & DiPietro, J. L. (2016). Impact of mobile apps to combat obesity in children and adolescents: A systematic literature review. Journal for Specialists in Pediatric Nursing, 21(1), 5–17.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robeyns, I. (2006). The capability approach in practice. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 14(3), 351–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saghai, Y. (2018). Theorizing justice in health research. In J. P. Kahn, A. C. Mastroianni, & J. Sugarman (Eds.), Beyond consent: Seeking justice in research (2nd ed., pp. 187–207). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sedhom, R., McShea, M. J., Cohen, A. B., Webster, J. A., & Mathews, S. C. (2021). Mobile app validation: A digital health scorecard approach. NPJ Digital Medicine, 4(1), 111.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Segers, S., & Mertes, H. (2022). The curious case of “trust” in the light of changing doctor–patient relationships. Bioethics, 36(8), 849–857.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2008). The idea of justice. Journal of Human Development, 9(3), 331–342.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sherwin, S. (1998). The politics of women’s health: Exploring agency and autonomy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, D. A., Shachar, C., & Cohen, I. G. (2022). Skating the line between general wellness products and regulated devices: Strategies and implications. Journal of Law and the Biosciences, 9(2), lsac015.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Somaiya, M., Shi, G., & Krasniansky, A. (2023). 2023 Q1 digital health funding: Investing like it’s 2019. Retrieved December 14, 2023, from https://rockhealth.com/insights/2023-q1-digital-health-funding-investing-like-its-2019/

  • Winters, N., Venkatapuram, S., Geniets, A., & Wynne-Bannister, E. (2020). Prioritarian principles for digital health in low resource settings. Journal of Medical Ethics, 46(4), 259–264.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

This research has received funding from the European Research Council (ERC) under the European Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme (grant agreement No. 919841 – DIME).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michiel De Proost.

Ethics declarations

Competing Interests

The authors declare no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

De Proost, M., Gray, J. No Justice Without (Relational) Autonomy? Rethinking the Digital Empowerment Rhetoric. DISO 3, 8 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s44206-024-00093-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s44206-024-00093-3

Keywords

Navigation