Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Habit and Mental Illness from an Hegelian Perspective

  • Arena of Health
  • Published:
Human Arenas Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Hegel proposes cultivation of habit as one of the major cures for mental illness. According to him, habit not only involves embodiment and dexterity but also mental activities and ethical elements. The aim of this paper is to evaluate the types of habit Hegel prescribes for curing mental illness in his original works. A three-level framework comprising the intrapersonal, interpersonal, and spiritual levels is adopted, and results show that although Hegel points out that habit is ethical and spiritual in nature, in his discussions on mental illness Hegel makes the majority of references on habits that involves the body such as physical movement and laboring. Habits that belong to the interpersonal and spiritual aspects are relatively neglected. This paper proposes that habits in the interpersonal and family realms, habits that function in the transition from the subjective to objective spirit, and habits in the morality sphere, which are equally important in Hegel’s philosophy, should be taken into consideration in future research and interventions for mental illness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Availability of data and material (data transparency)

Not applicable.

Code availability (software application or custom code)

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. Some examples are madness, insanity, dementia, and mania. See, for example, Doob (1974), Gomory, Cohen, and Kirk (2013).

  2. Hegel provides an account of a few types of mental illness such as idiocy, the distracted mind and the rambling mind in the Zusätz of §408 of his Philosophy of Mind (PhM) (Hegel 1971). However, the descriptions are relatively short and most of them cover about one page only.

  3. For example, “mental disorder,” “psychopathology,” and “mental patient” will also be used wherever suitable.

  4. Following prominent experts on the history of mental illness (e.g., Scull 1979; 2015), this paper uses the term “mental illness” as an umbrella term for mental and psychological disorders in modern usage to replace Hegel’s “madness” and “insanity” which he often used.

  5. For example, Forman (2010), Howard (2013), Lumsden (2012), Testa (2017), Žižek (2009), and Zovko (2018).

  6. For example, Menke (2013); Žižek (2009).

  7. For example, Hegel (1971, p. 123).

  8. Hegel’s conceptualization of dementia is entirely different from contemporary conceptualizations. For example, in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-5) (American Psychiatric Association 2013), dementia is categorized as a Neurocognitive Disorder which is a disease of the brain.

  9. One good example is the influences of his theories on the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual (American Psychological Association 2013).

  10. In his later important work, the Philosophy of Right (1953: 109), Hegel points out habit is a “second nature”.

  11. As stated by Hegel, “at the stage we have now reached in the development of subjective mind, we come to a being-for-self of the soul that has been brought into being by the Notion of soul which has overcome the inner contradiction of mind present in insanity, has put an end to the complete dividedness of the self. This being-at-home-with-oneself we call habit. In this, the soul which is no longer confined to a merely subjective particular idea by which it is displaced from the center of its concrete actuality, has so completely received into its ideality the immediate and particularized content presented to it, has come to feel so at home in it, that it moves about in it in freedom” (Hegel 1971: 144).

  12. Lumsden (2012: 224) explains how habit is related to self-identity, that “(T)he repetition is what allows the subject to habituate that feeling, sensation of action and thereby make it part of its identity, something it could then be indifferent to, precisely because it relates to them as external drives, sensations or impulses. Prior to habit the subject is not able to be at home with itself and is not free because the being of the soul is driven by particulars. It can only be at home with itself when the particulars are idealized, only then has it started to become self-identical.”

  13. In Malabou’s words, “from the beginning to the end of the organism’s life, habit is busy applying its power from the inside, fulfilling the individual development of the organism’s faculties” (Malabou 2005: 58).

  14. As stated by Malabou, “habit becomes a condition of adaptation in a double sense, being a form of contemplation – absorbing the environment, passively lending itself to what is given – and a kind of exercise, informing and transforming the surroundings, appropriating the given conditions for its organic functions” (Malabou 2005: 60).

  15. As suggested earlier on page 4, Hegel treats dementia as a reversion to nature, a flight from the world, and a deficit in world relation (Hegel 2007: 140).

  16. For example, de Sousa, Varese, Sellwood, and Bentall (2014).

  17. See, for example, Hegel (1971: 135) and Hegel (2007: 148).

  18. For example, Jones (2017) and Schirmann (2013).

  19. For example, Hegel (1977).

References

  • American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). Arlington: American Psychiatric Association.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berthold-Bond, D. (1991). Hegel, Nietzsche, and Freud on madness and the unconscious. The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 5(3), 193–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berthold-Bond, D. (1995). Hegel’s theory of madness. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berthold-Bond, D. (2009). Talking cures: A Lacanian reading of Hegel and Kierkegaard on language and madness. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 16, 299–311. https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.0.0264

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boss, M. (1979). Existential foundations of medicine and psychology. New York: Aronson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boss, M. (1982). Psychoanalysis and Daseinsanalysis. New York: Da Capo Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, G. W., & Harris, T. (1978). Social origins of depression: A study of psychiatric disorder in women. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bürgy, M. (2008). The concept of psychosis: Historical and phenomenological aspects. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 34(6), 1200–1210. https://doi.org/10.1093/schbul/sbm136

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • de Sousa, P., Varese, F., Sellwood, W., & Bentall, R. P. (2014). Parental communication and psychosis: A meta-analysis. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 40, 756–768. https://doi.org/10.1093/schbul/sbt088

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Doob, P. B. R. (1974). Nebuchadnezzar’s children: Conventions of madness in Middle English literature. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forman, D. (2010). Second nature and spirit: Hegel on the role of habit in the appearance of perceptual consciousness. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 48, 325–352. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.2041-6962.2010.00037.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1965). New introductory lectures on psychoanalyses. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, J. D. (2006). Hegel’s idea of the good life. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gomory, T., Cohen, D., & Kirk, S. A. (2013). Madness or mental illness? Revisiting historians of psychiatry. Current Psychology, 32, 119–135. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12144-013-9168-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1953). Philosophy of right. (T. M. Knox, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1970). Philosophy of nature: Being part two of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences. (A. V. Miller, Trans.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1971). Hegel’s philosophy of mind: Being part three of the Encyclopaedia of Philosophical Sciences. (W. Wallace, Trans.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1977). Phenomenology of spirit. (A. V. Miller, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (2007). Lectures on the philosophy of spirit 18278. (R. R. Williams, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Howard, J. J. (2013). Hegel on the emotions: Coordinating form and content. In D. S. Stern (Ed.), Essays on Hegel’s philosophy of subjective spirit (pp. 71–86). New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyppolite, J. (1971). Hegel’s phenomenology and psychoanalysis. In W. E. Steinkraus (Ed.), New studies in Hegel’s philosophy (pp. 57–70). New York: Holt, Rinehart, Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ikäheimo, H. (2014). Hegel’s concept of recognition – What is it?” In C. Krijnen (Ed.), Recognition – German Idealism as an ongoing challenge (pp. 11–38). Leiden: Brill. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004262607_003

  • Jaspers, K. (1963). General psychopathology (J. Hoenig & M. W. Hamilton, Trans.). Manchester: Manchester University Press.

  • Jones, D. W. (2017). Moral insanity and psychological disorder: The hybrid roots of psychiatry. History of Psychiatry, 28, 263–279. https://doi.org/10.1177/0957154X17702316

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Legg, C., & Black, J. (2020). What is intelligence for? A Peircean pragmatist response to the knowing-how, knowing-that debate. Erkenntnis. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00301-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, S. (2015). McDowell, Hegel, and habits. Hegel Bulletin, 36, 184–201. https://doi.org/10.1017/hgl.2015.17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, T. A. (2007–8). Speaking of habits: The role of language in moving from habit to freedom. The Owl of Minerva, 39, 25–53. https://doi.org/10.5840/owl2007/2008391/22

  • Lumsden, S. (2012). Habit, Sittlichkeit and second nature. Critical Horizons, 13, 220–243. https://doi.org/10.1558/crit.v13i2.220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie, H. M. (1909). Hegel’s educational theory and practice. London: Swan Sonnenschein.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magrì, E. (2016). The place of habit in Hegel’s psychology. In S. Herrmann-Sinai & L. Ziglioli (Eds.), Hegel’s philosophical psychology (pp. 74–90). London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magrì, E. (2017). The problem of habitual body and memory in Hegel and Merleau-Ponty. Hegel Bulletin, 38(1), 24–44. https://doi.org/10.1017/hgl.2016.65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malabou, C. (2005). The future of Hegel. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massecar, A. (2016). Ethical habits: A Peircean perspective. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCumber, J. (1990). Hegel on habit. The Owl of Minerva, 21, 155–165. https://doi.org/10.5840/owl19902121

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menke, C. (2013). Hegel’s theory of second nature: The ‘lapse’ of spirit. Symposium. Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy, 17, 31–49. https://doi.org/10.5840/symposium20131713

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niarchos, C. G. A. (2014). The concept of soul in Hegel’s anthropology. In Arndt, A., Gerhad, M., Zovko, J., & Beyer, W. R. (Eds.), Hegel-Jahrbuch 2014 (pp. 129–136). Berlin/München/Boston: Walter de Gruyter. https://doi.org/10.1515/hgjb-2014-0122

  • Panova, O. B. (2015). Spirit and language in Hegel’s philosophy of absolute spirit. Procedia – Social and Behavioral Sciences, 200, 502–508. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.sbspro.2015.08.008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J., Bovet, P., & Zahavi, D. (2002). Schizophrenic autism: clinical phenomenology and pathogenetic implications. World Psychiatry, 1(3), 131–136. https://doi.org/10.1590/S1516-80342008000100017

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J., Sass, L. A., & Zahavi, D. (2012). Rediscovering psychopathology: The epistemology and phenomenology of the psychiatric object. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 39(2), 270–277. https://doi.org/10.1093/schbul/sbs153

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1998). The essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings (Vol. 2). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. A., Parnas, J., & Zahavi, D. (2011). Phenomenological psychopathology and schizophrenia: Contemporary approaches and misunderstandings. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 18(1), 1–23. https://doi.org/10.1353/ppp.2011.0008

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schirmann, F. (2013). Badness, madness and the brain – the late 19th-century controversy on immoral persons and their malfunctioning brains. History of the Human Sciences, 26, 33–50. https://doi.org/10.1177/0952695113482317

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, G., Ciarrochi, J., & Deane, F. P. (2004). Disadvantages of being an individualist in an individualistic culture: Idiocentrism, emotional competence, stress, and mental health. Australian Psychologist, 39(2), 143–154. https://doi.org/10.1080/00050060410001701861

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scull, A. (1979). Museums of madness: the social organization of insanity in nineteenth century. London: Allen Lane/Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scull, A. (2015). Madness and civilization: a cultural history of insanity from the Bible to Freud, and from the madhouse to modern medicine. London: Thames and Hudson/Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Testa, I. (2013). Hegel’s naturalism or soul and body in the Encyclopedia. In D. S. Stern (Ed.), Essays on Hegel’s philosophy of subjective spirit (pp. 19–36). New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Testa, I. (2017). Dewey, second nature, social criticism, and the Hegelian heritage. European Journal of Pragmatism and Amercian Philosophy, IX(1), 1–23. https://doi.org/10.4000/ejpap.990

  • Testa, I. (2020). Embodied cognition, habit, and natural agency in Hegel’s anthropology. In M. F. Bykova & K. R. Westphal (Eds.), The Palgrave Hegel handbook (pp. 269–296). Cham, Switzerland: Springer Nature. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-26597-7

  • Winfield, R. D. (2013). The psychology of will and the deduction of right. Rethinking Hegel’s theory of practical intelligence. In D. S. Stern (Ed.), Hegel’s philosophy of subjective spirit (pp. 201–221). Albany: State University of New York.

  • Wu, M. M. (2020). Second language learning as habit formation from a Hegelian perspective. Human Arenas, 3, 391–403. https://doi.org/10.1007/s42087-019-00088-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Žižek, S. (1997/2007). Madness and habit in German Idealism. Retrieved from: https://www.lacan.com/zizdazedandconfused.html

  • Žižek, S. (2009). Discipline between two freedoms – Madness and habit in German Idealism. In M. Gabriel & S. Žižek (Eds.), Mythology, madness, and laughter: Subjectivity in German Idealism (pp. 95–121). London and New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zovko, J. (2018). Hegel’s concept of education from the point of view of his idea of “second nature.” Educational Philosophy and Theory, 50, 652–661. https://doi.org/10.1080/00131857.2017.1374842

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

The author declares that he is the only author and sole contributor of the manuscript.

The research described in this manuscript did not involve human participants and/or animals. Informed consent was not applicable to the research described in this manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Manfred Man-fat Wu.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wu, M.Mf. Habit and Mental Illness from an Hegelian Perspective. Hu Arenas 5, 245–261 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s42087-020-00151-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s42087-020-00151-5

Keywords

Navigation