1 Introduction

Under the headline ‘World’s Top Nationalities Revealed’, Forbes magazine reported that a global index declared France to have the ‘best’ nationality on offer in the world in 2018, in terms of ‘quality of life and opportunity’.Footnote 1 The index is fed by quantitative data that aims to expose what it calls the internal and external quality of a particular nationality—across categories such as economic prosperity, peace and security (internal), and the scope of visa-free travel (external).Footnote 2 This ranking of nationalities, and the citizenship-by-investment schemes is being used to promote and remind us of the pervasiveness of global inequality. Although the contemporary international legal order is based on the principle of the sovereign equality of all states, rendering the world’s nationalities formally equal, in practice there is what Shachar calls an ‘inequality of actual life chances attached to citizenship in specific political communities’.Footnote 3 Even in an era of human rights, which recognise ‘the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family’,Footnote 4 this remains the reality. It matters, not just whether you have a nationality,Footnote 5 but which nationality that is.

While Shachar problematises these ‘global-distributive implications’ of citizenship and its attendant rules in his compelling monograph The Birthright Lottery, this article explores another plane of inequality within modern citizenship regimes that has received little attention to date: the unequal nationality status of different members of the same political community. The concept of nationality—or citizenshipFootnote 6—refers to the legal bond between a person and a state,Footnote 7 that ‘connotes full membership’.Footnote 8 In liberal democracies, citizenship brings with it the often constitutionally guaranteed promise of equality of rights (and duties) within that community.Footnote 9 Nowhere within this understanding of nationality is there anything to suggest that the nature of the legal bond varies among citizens of the same community, i.e. that some citizens are more equal than others. Yet, in the practice of states, not everyone who is admitted as a national enjoys the full package of rights attached, nor the same security of status. Examples of this manifestation include restrictions on the exercise of political rights by particular categories of nationals, such as dual citizensFootnote 10 or the (newly) naturalised,Footnote 11 as well as unequal ability to transmit citizenship and contribute to further shaping the community.Footnote 12

The phenomenon of inequality among citizens is also apparent when examining how protected the legal bond itself is. As this article will expose, when it comes to the power of states to divest a person of his or her nationality, it matters both how that nationality was acquired and whether it is the only one the person in question holds. Citizenship by birth is more secure than citizenship acquired otherwise—such as by naturalisation—and mono citizens are less prone to withdrawal of nationality than persons with dual or multiple nationality. As will be shown in Sect. 2, such inequality is a long-standing feature of the rules on loss and deprivation of nationality across a wide array of countries. Yet, it has drawn increased attention in recent years on account of the growing interest among states to use nationality deprivation as a counter-terrorism measure and become a much-scrutinised topic within related political, public and academic debate. Indeed, as Sect. 3 will discuss, the uptake in legislation on and use of citizenship stripping on the pretext of protecting national security has shone new light on not only the unequal scope of the measure, but also the discriminatory effects of its application. This raises the question of how such law and practice is to be evaluated against contemporary standards of international law. Section 4 explores the apparent contradiction between, on the one hand, norms that inform states’ duty to avoid statelessness and, on the other, the principles of non-discrimination and of equality before the law, discussing how this might be reconciled. Finally, the article reflects on the broader implications of the current trend towards greater inequality of citizenship status as a reaction to the perceived threat that terrorism poses to the integrity of the state, discussing how the creation of different classes of citizen is in fact likely to have a deeper and more lasting impact on the foundations of liberal democracies.

2 Deprivation of Nationality: An Unequal Measure?

Across the world, states provide in their laws for the possibility of involuntary withdrawal of a citizen’s nationality. In some instances, a distinction is drawn between loss and deprivation of nationality.Footnote 13 Loss then refers to a situation in which nationality is withdrawn automatically, by operation of law (i.e. without state interference). For example, in some states nationality can be automatically lost if a person resides abroad for a consecutive period determined by law.Footnote 14 Once the conditions specified in law are fulfilled, the person’s nationality lapses automatically. Deprivation of nationality, in contrast, is non-automatic and requires the state to decide in each individual case whether citizenship should be revoked, in accordance with powers stipulated in national legislation. Often, the assigned state authority (e.g. Minister of Justice or a judge) has some discretion in determining whether a person’s behaviour should lead to denationalisation. Under the 1961 Convention on the Reduction of Statelessness (1961 Convention), different standards apply to specific forms of loss and of deprivation of nationality, however both modalities of withdrawal of citizenship are also subject to the broader human rights norm prohibiting arbitrary deprivation of nationality—i.e. no distinction between loss and deprivation of citizenship is made in human rights law.Footnote 15 In practice, national legislation also does not always clearly distinguish between loss and deprivation of nationality and both lead to a person who was once a citizen being left without that status. In this article, the terms loss and deprivation of nationality will therefore be used interchangeably.

The problematisation of nationality deprivation as an unequal measure has recently emerged as an area of debate in the context of contemporary counter-terrorism efforts which have heralded an increased use of this policy.Footnote 16 Yet, deprivation clauses have been stipulated in most nationality laws since their inception. Historically, denationalisation was invoked against citizens who were disloyal towards the state, posed an imminent threat to national security or no longer had a bond with the state. For example, the 1892 Dutch Citizenship Act, Article 7(4) states: ‘[Nederlanderschap wordt verloren:] door zonder Ons verlof zich te begeven in vreemden krijgs- of staatsdienst’.Footnote 17 In short, Dutch nationality will be lost by any Dutch citizen who joins a foreign military or public service. Being a citizen required having undivided allegiance towards your country, including the duty to support and defend it, and denationalisation was seen as a way to deal with disloyal and undesirable citizens.

That nationality deprivation is a measure of unequal application is apparent already in early comparative studies of domestic legislation. In 1953, the International Law Commission (ILC) published a memorandum that gives an overview of the common nationality deprivation grounds that existed around the world at that time.Footnote 18 While some grounds applied to all citizens, the study also pointed out countries that only apply nationality deprivation grounds to naturalised citizens.Footnote 19 Loss of nationality could, for instance, occur if a naturalised citizen lives abroad for a specified period of time or if a naturalised citizen fraudulently acquired the nationality. Naturalised citizens could also lose their citizenship if they were convicted of a serious crime within a specified number of years after naturalisation. In some states, ‘denaturalisation’ could take place at any time if a citizen was convicted of treason or for a crime against the security of the state or could be invoked if a naturalised citizen ‘indicated oneself to be disloyal, disaffected or of a mentality contrary to the national spirit’.Footnote 20 Denaturalisation was the first form of unequal citizenship stripping, causing a divide between naturalised citizens and native-born citizens.

Another phenomenon of unequal nationality deprivation apparent at that time was the inequality between men and women. In the early to mid-twentieth century it was deemed in the general interest of the international community to ensure that everyone had a nationality, but one nationality only.Footnote 21 The prohibition of dual nationality contributed to gender discrimination in nationality revocation measures.Footnote 22 Women would lose their original nationality upon marriage with a foreign national—a policy justified by states’ desire to prevent dual nationality and avoid mixed nationality marriages that could act as disruptors of social cohesion and blur nationalistic ideals. At the time, the majority of states also provided more generally for nationality revocation in response to the ‘voluntary act of acquiring another nationality’.Footnote 23

Later, views on dual nationality as well as women’s nationality rights changed and this picture changed with it. Many states no longer prohibit dual nationality, nor does international law seek its eradication, and women’s equal and independent nationality rights are now nearly universally recognised. However, another form of unequal nationality deprivation has meanwhile grown in prominence. The duty to avoid statelessness became an international norm with an increasingly strong influence on nationality deprivation rules.Footnote 24 In aid of this goal, states have come to limit the application of many denationalisation measures to citizens with more than one nationality, creating inequality in nationality deprivation measures between mono nationals and dual nationals. For instance, in a number of countries, denationalisation can take place upon long term residence abroad, not fulfilling military duties, or if a person is a threat to national security—unless it leads to statelessness.Footnote 25 This means, in effect, that states can only apply denationalisation measures to dual or multiple citizens: they can be cast out of the political community in response to undesirable behaviour, whereas mono nationals involved in similar acts are not subject to this measure.

By making citizenship for naturalised and dual citizens conditional upon good behaviour, citizenship becomes a less secure status for specific groups of citizens and a less equal status. Citizenship stripping is an instrument that enables states to treat nationality policy as complementary to immigration laws, to continue to control inclusion and exclusion of citizens with a migrant background. As Macklin describes, deprivation of nationality allows states to affect a ‘two-step exile: first, strip citizenship; second, deport the newly minted alien’.Footnote 26 Such deportation can affect people who have lived their entire lives or a large part of their lives in the country, have their family in the country, speak the language and do not know any other country as their home. When revoking someone’s nationality, it not only shows the unequal status of citizenship, it also results in unequal exposure to the risk of deportation and exclusion.Footnote 27

Unequal deprivation measures also affect society as a whole and undermine important democratic values. Citizenship is an enabler of social cohesion as it creates a feeling of belonging and equality. If it is made conditional for only specific groups of citizens, i.e. naturalised and dual citizens, this disrupts (efforts towards) social cohesion. Threatening specific groups with denationalisation measures creates a divide between those who are deemed ‘real’ citizens and ‘others’, underpinning a divide between ‘native citizens’ and those with a migratory background that can have a deep impact on the whole community. As we see in other fields, there is a growing intolerance for making distinctions between sub-groups of citizens. For instance, in the past decade, the Dutch government has formally ceased its use of the terms ‘allochthones’ and ‘autochthones’ in its internal and public communications because they were identified to be highly charged terms that have an exclusionary and degrading effect on groups of citizens.Footnote 28 This confirms the need to also re-assess other distinctions with similar effect that are made between groups of citizens, including through denationalisation measures. The article will return to this matter later.

3 Citizenship Stripping in the Counter-Terrorism Context: A Discriminatory Practice?

Although, as the previous section has shown, ‘citizenship revocation has always been codified as States’ last right to determine their composition, the use of the practice had reached near single digits following World War II’.Footnote 29 Once the legal bond of nationality has been forged, it has therefore generally come to be something to rely on—unless the citizen him or herself takes action to change citizenship and become a member of a different political community.Footnote 30 But this picture has started to change as states have looked to nationality policy as a tool to tackle emerging national security threats.

The evolution of ‘exceptionalist’ counter-terrorism measures has now started to penetrate the realm of citizenship, challenging ‘the prevailing view until the foreign fighter phenomenon came along [that] banishment or exile does not find a place as a matter of modern law and policy’.Footnote 31 In the last decade, over a dozen countries have amended their legislation to give the state greater powers to unilaterally sever the legal bond with its own citizens on grounds that relate to national security or terrorism. These countries include Australia, Austria, Azerbaijan, Bahrain, Belgium, Bosnia and Herzegovina, Egypt, Kazakhstan, Kyrgyzstan, the Netherlands, the Seychelles, South Africa, Turkey and the United Kingdom.Footnote 32

Although nationality deprivation has featured within the so-called ‘legislative fever’Footnote 33 with which many governments have responded to contemporary terrorism threats, its purpose is not clearly articulated. The political rhetoric invokes notions of deterrence, prevention—in particular through blocking return—and punishment. Yet no evidence has been produced for the effectiveness of this instrument and as set out below, the idea that citizenship stripping makes society more secure or helps to protect the democratic values that terrorists have ‘turned their back on’ is deeply questionable.Footnote 34

As was already the case for other rules on deprivation of nationality discussed in Sect. 2, many of these new or expanded powers do not apply equally to all citizens. In the United Kingdom, for instance, a dual national can be stripped of his or her British citizenship if this is deemed to be ‘conducive to the public good’Footnote 35—a low bar that grants significant discretion to the Home Secretary, who wields the power to invoke this measure. On the other hand, a mono citizen may be subject to the withdrawal of his or her British citizenship only if it was acquired by naturalisation and if two additional conditions are met: that ‘it would be conducive to the public good to deprive them of their status because they have engaged in conduct “seriously prejudicial” to the UK’s vital interests’ and that ‘the Home Secretary has reasonable grounds to believe that they could acquire another nationality’.Footnote 36 The nationality of a mono citizen who is British by birth remains secure, regardless of his or her conduct. This legislation alone generates three ‘classes’ of British citizenship in terms of the security of status. Were three British citizens—one a mono citizen by birth, one a naturalised mono citizen and one a dual citizen—to conspire together to commit a terrorist act, the availability to the state of nationality deprivation as a recourse would differ among them, even if they were all equally culpable.

In this age of securitisation of nationality policy, it is dual nationals that are particularly affected. In Britain, there has been a significant upsurge in the deprivation of citizenship. In the 7 years from 2010 to 2016, a total of 47 people were stripped of their citizenship on the basis that to do so was ‘conducive to the public good’, then in 2017 this shot up to 104 people in a single year.Footnote 37 All were dual nationals. In other countries where laws have been reformed in recent years, safeguards have been built into avoid statelessness—protecting the citizenship of mono citizens from interference, while revocation cases were initiated against dual nationals even as the ink was drying on the newly expanded deprivation powers. For instance, the media reported on the use of deprivation of citizenship against four ‘convicted jihadists’ by the Netherlands in 2017, a ‘convicted terrorist’ by Belgium in 2018 and five ‘IS terrorists’ by Australia in 2018.Footnote 38 Again, all were dual nationals.

The upshot of this new trend in law and practice is the creation of ‘a category of individuals who are placed under a special regime because they are considered to be undeserving of the same level of legal protection as other individuals’.Footnote 39 Targeting dual nationals, and in some cases specifically naturalised citizens, opens a pathway to indirect discrimination against minorities. In most countries, people from ethnic and religious minorities are over-represented in the population that holds naturalised citizenship or dual nationality. In the Netherlands, for instance, the majority of dual nationals are Dutch-Moroccans—who also, in fact, experience difficulties renouncing their Moroccan citizenship and so may be unable to become mono Dutch citizens.Footnote 40 If nationality deprivation only applies to dual nationals, this is likely to lead to indirect discrimination against this group.Footnote 41

The consequences of this are not benign, but part of a broader process that Choudhury describes as ‘the production of suspect communities’.Footnote 42 In the run up to the 2017 elections in the Netherlands, Prime Minister Mark Rutte (who succeeded in being re-elected), published an open letter in the country’s newspapers which is telling of the normalisation of rhetoric that treats being part of the ‘in-group’ as contingent on the right kind of behaviour.Footnote 43 In a letter that is addressed to ‘all Dutch citizens’ and which goes on to refer to equal treatment as a shared value that needs to be upheld, he writes:

We feel increasingly uncomfortable when people misuse our freedom to ruin things, when they came to our country precisely for that freedom. People who don’t want to adapt, diss our habits or reject our values […] I fully understand that people think: if you so fundamentally reject our country, I would rather you leave. I actually feel the same way. Act normally or get out.Footnote 44

The instrumentalised use of citizenship stripping against dual nationals on the pretext of national security therefore should not be seen in a vacuum. Rather, it must be understood in a context in which some politicians ‘deliberately stoke and exploit the national security anxieties of national populations [with the result that] they effectively stigmatize entire racial, ethnic, national and religious groups’.Footnote 45 This lends a real urgency to the scrutiny of such measures from the perspective of contemporary international law, which is what this article turns to next.

4 International Law Standards: Mixed Messages?

Starting with the 1930 Hague Convention on certain questions relating to the conflict of nationality laws, international law has progressively developed to constrain states’ freedom to regulate acquisition and withdrawal of nationality. The affirmation of the right of every person to a nationality, in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and later in many universal and regional treaties, has particularly influenced the shape of international norms.Footnote 46 One specific rule that has emerged with a view to protecting the right to a nationality and is codified in both the 1961 Convention and the European Convention on Nationality (ECN) is the prohibition of withdrawal of nationality if it results in statelessness.Footnote 47

This focus on avoiding denationalisation that renders a person stateless implicitly leaves it to states to determine whether and when to denationalise people, as long as they also hold another nationality. Indeed, states appear to have derived justification for targeting dual nationals for denationalisation from the international norms pertaining to statelessness. As the Netherlands explains in its explanatory memorandum on citizenship revocation measures:

Not withdrawing Dutch nationality if it would result into statelessness is one of the Kingdom’s core obligations in countering statelessness. This results in a divide between Dutch citizens that hold one nationality and Dutch citizens with multiple nationalities, whereby the former cannot be denationalised. This is a legitimate divide. Preventing statelessness is the reason to revoke nationality in some cases and to not revoke nationality in other cases.Footnote 48

Furthermore, the 1961 Convention admits a number of exceptions to its general prohibition of loss or deprivation of nationality that result in statelessness and these too appear to support the unequal application of the measure to different categories of citizen. More specifically, the 1961 Convention allows nationality to be revoked from naturalised citizens as a result of long-term residence abroad or if it was acquired by fraud—even if this leaves the person concerned stateless. Here, again, the possibility of citizenship being an unequal status seems to find support in international law: this norm tolerates policies that make naturalised citizens more susceptible to citizenship revocation policies than native-born citizens.

However, there are a number of other important international norms and general principles of law that are also relevant to the question of how unequal denationalisation regimes are to be understood. These include the prohibition of arbitrary deprivation of nationalityFootnote 49 and the principles of non-discrimination and proportionality that form integral elements of that prohibition.Footnote 50 An assessment of current law and practice on withdrawal of nationality leads to a rather different outcome if these standards are taken as the point of departure.

As set out in Sect. 3, where states target only naturalised citizens and/or dual citizens for denationalisation, this unequal treatment grounded on differences in citizenship status can bleed into indirect discrimination on the basis of ethnicity, race or religion—and therefore be considered ‘arbitrary’ under international law. As the UN Special Rapporteur on contemporary forms of racism, racial discrimination, xenophobia and related intolerance wrote:

Rarely do States explicitly discriminate on the basis of race, ethnicity or national origin in their citizenship stripping process. However, overbroad policies ostensibly rooted in national security concerns permit arbitrary enforcement—including arbitrary deprivation of citizenship—which in practice have a disproportionate effect on marginalised racial, national and religious groups. Footnote 51

The statelessness-specific rules contained in the 1961 Convention must be interpreted in light of the broader principle of equality and non-discrimination that has been extensively codified in all core human rights treaties that were adopted after the 1961 Convention.Footnote 52 According to the Human Rights Council (HRC), arbitrary deprivation of nationality, especially on discriminatory grounds such as ‘race, colour, sex, language, religion, political or other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth, or other status, including disability’ is a violation of human rights and fundamental freedoms.Footnote 53

Law, policies and practices that disproportionately exclude or have a negative impact on a particular racial, ethnic or national group should also be considered as a breach of the prohibition of racial discrimination. This is true even in the absence of de jure or intentional discrimination.Footnote 54

In fact, understood in this light, even the 1961 Convention itself can be read differently. Often overlooked in discussions of this topic, Article 9 of the 1961 Convention reads: ‘A Contracting State may not deprive any person or group of persons of their nationality on racial, ethnic, religious or political grounds’. So, while the primary purpose of the 1961 Convention is to reduce the incidence of statelessness, the treaty itself recognises that there is a broader international principle at stake that must be applied as a blanket rule—separate from and regardless of the question of whether the result of denationalisation is statelessness. The ECN is also concerned with ‘avoiding discrimination in matters relating to nationality’Footnote 55 and explicitly provides that ‘Each State Party shall be guided by the principle of non-discrimination between its nationals, whether they are nationals by birth or have acquired its nationality subsequently’.Footnote 56 From this it could be concluded that international law is giving off mixed messages about the legitimacy of rules under which the deprivation of nationality operates unequally.

Looking more closely, the UN Human Rights Committee explains that not every form of differential treatment constitutes discrimination.Footnote 57 Severe national security risks and the fact that dual citizens are not prone to being rendered stateless in the way that mono citizens are could justify differential treatment, if such differential treatment has a legitimate aim and if it is proportionate. Barak clearly sets out the four components of the proportionality test:

(1) It is designed for a proper purpose (2) the measures undertaken to effectuate such a limitation are rationally connected to the fulfilment of that purpose (3) the measures undertaken are necessary in that there are no alternative measures that may similarly achieve that same purpose with a lesser degree of limitation and (4) there needs to be a proper relation (proportionality stricto sensu or ‘balancing’) between the importance of achieving the proper purpose and the social importance of preventing the limitation on the constitutional right.Footnote 58

A way to resolve the question of international law’s apparent ‘mixed messages’ on this issue could then be to explore whether the unequal use of nationality deprivation as it is emerging today in the counter-terrorism context would pass this test.

The purpose of nationality deprivation as a counter-terrorism measure, as outlined in policy debates, is to strengthen national security by acting as a deterrent or preventative instrument and/or to punish those who turn their back on the state. While both the purposes of protecting security and effecting punishment are ‘proper’ aims and functions of the state, the further criteria of the proportionality test may pose a problem to the legitimacy of deprivation of nationality in pursuit of these aims—especially where it is of unequal application among citizens. For instance, will citizenship stripping actually effectuate either purpose if only a small sub-set of citizens is subject to the measure—i.e. what about the mono nationals and native-born citizens that pose a threat to national security? And, if deprivation of nationality is used as an added punishment for some citizens, but not others, how is this to be understood in light of the legal principle of ne bis in idem (to not be punished twice for the same crime)?Footnote 59

What evidence is there, in fact, that citizenship withdrawal has any impact on the threat of terrorist attacks? It imposes barriers to lawful return to the country, but terrorism is a global security threat that reaches beyond national borders. Terrorist attacks can be orchestrated from abroad and carried out by others in terrorist networks. Also, being denationalised does not keep a person out of a country: he or she may travel on false papers and continue to pose a threat to society. By taking away the bond of citizenship, governments may actually have less means at their disposal to track or take action against the person and so by turning citizens suspected of terrorism into foreigners, governments are exporting a security threat to the international community. It is therefore difficult to see how, in Barak’s typology, this measure is ‘rationally connected to the fulfilment’ of the purpose increasing security. Indeed, as Esbrook summarised:

Expansion of citizenship-stripping proposals fractures international cooperation, provides tacit encouragement to States who use citizenship-stripping as a political tool to consolidate power, normatively sets the international community backwards in its evolution towards rights promotion and individual empowerment, and requires implementation of a new and extreme policy where existing law enforcement tools already exist.Footnote 60

Finally, to assess the measure’s proportionality, it is also necessary to ask whether less intrusive measures exist to counter terrorism and to protect national security and/or punish a citizen for his/her wrongdoings. Here, it is important to point out that mono nationals and native-born citizens are subject to a plethora of other measures set out in criminal law such as (preventive) detention, passport revocation, monitoring etc.Footnote 61 In other words, states have found ways to address security threats posed by mono nationals without denationalising them. Why are these measures not simply applied in the same way to all nationals, without the state reaching for the added and far-reaching instrument of citizenship revocation for some? Doing so would prevent the discriminatory application of nationality deprivation measures and its concomitant effect on social cohesion. As Macklin puts it: ‘A man who attacks his mother may be a terrible son who deserves to be prosecuted for his crime, but it is not the job of family law to disclaim him as the son of his mother. Citizenship law is not criminal law. Nor is it national security law. Nor should it be rigged to operate as a trap door that shunts citizens to immigration law’.Footnote 62

On the contrary, taking seriously the protection of the right to a nationality and (re)asserting the equality of citizenship for all citizens is, in fact, a way for states to bolster the security and integrity of their society—one which accords with the ideals of liberal democracies. As Hirsch Ballin explains:

The methods of international terrorism are effectively directed against the foundations of societies based on trust in the rule of law […] Once trust in the law is battered, the door is open for political views that, while vehemently opposing such violent fundamentalists, mirror their culture essentialism: on their turn, populist politicians reject the idea of a free public space for all under the rule of law, and advocate an inward-looking nationalistic ideology. Thus, they undermine the idea of inclusive citizenship for all [and] paradoxically send out a message of confirmation to the terrorists that indeed a ‘clash of civilisations’ unfolds.Footnote 63

It is this reading of the role and value of citizenship that underwrote Justin Trudeau’s memorable speech at a Town Hall meeting during his election campaign in September 2015, where he stated unequivocally: ‘A Canadian, is a Canadian, is a Canadian. You devalue the citizenship of every Canadian when you break down and make it conditional for anyone’.Footnote 64 Following his election into office, Trudeau’s government succeeded in repealing the expanded deprivation powers that had been introduced with the Strengthening Canadian Citizenship Act (SCCA) in 2015. While the trend at the time of writing is towards greater use of nationality deprivation as a security measure, the example of Canada shows that policy can be reversed and the democratic value of equal citizenship can be upheld.

5 Conclusion

Citizenship has been described by Bauböck as having ‘an extremely sticky quality’.Footnote 65 For most people, it indeed accompanies them unchanged and unchallenged throughout their lifetime and may therefore be experienced as a permanent and even immutable element of their identity. Yet, citizenship stripping is a measure that is as old as the existence of nationality law and seems to have always been an unequal measure—with some citizens holding a more precarious citizenship status than others.

The contemporary trend towards the securitisation of nationality policy has, perhaps belatedly, drawn attention to the discriminatory effect of this inequality. It has also helped to make visible the wider context of ‘resurgent xenophobic and racist rhetoric and policies rooted in ethno-nationalism [that] not only harm non-citizens of any given nation [but] also make formal citizens who are ethnic, racial or religious minorities vulnerable to discrimination and intolerance’.Footnote 66 Deprivation policies that target only naturalised or dual nationals have the effect of precluding the acceptance of these citizens as full citizens—undermining the function of naturalisation. The purpose of naturalisation processes is to affirm that a person has fully integrated into the community and is accepted as ‘one of us’. Once admitted, naturalised citizens are equal to birth-right citizens and should be indistinguishable from them, able to participate in the democratic life of the state on the same terms. If their continuing-to-belong is contingent on behaviour, naturalisation serves little purpose and becomes indistinguishable from a form of conditional residence status. Where the naturalised citizen is mistrusted, citizenship stripping is put to work as a weapon which turns badly-behaved citizens into foreigners again, allowing them to be deported, or prevented from re-entering the country and thereby severing the link that has been so painstakingly built up and had received the highest form of legal recognition through the conferral of nationality.Footnote 67

In respect of the distinction between mono and dual nationals, states have staked their case that this form of inequality is not just allowable under international law, it is mandated by international norms. It is true that it is in the interest of both states and individuals that statelessness be avoided and that this is affirmed by the human right to a nationality. But, as this article has discussed, just as nationality deprivation policies must be understood in their wider societal context, so must the duty on states to prevent statelessness be understood as part of a wider web of international standards and principles. The prohibition of arbitrary deprivation of nationality and the principles of non-discrimination and of proportionality must also be satisfied in any case in which a state seeks to strip one of its citizens of his/her citizenship.

How a truly rights-based approach to nationality might prevail where once a more technical approach was taken to the avoidance of nationality ‘problems’ can be illustrated by the evolution of women’s nationality rights under international law (an area of law already referred to in Sect. 2). In 1930, the Convention on certain questions relating to the conflict of nationality laws provided that a woman could only lose her nationality on the basis of marriage with a foreigner if she acquires the nationality of her husband—a measure specifically aimed at preventing statelessness.Footnote 68 By 1957, the norm had evolved and the Convention on the Nationality of Married Women provided that ‘neither the celebration nor the dissolution of a marriage between one of its nationals and an alien, nor the change of nationality by the husband during marriage, shall automatically affect the nationality of the wife’. This marked an early stage in the recognition of women’s independent nationality rights to men. Today, however, both approaches—while not unhelpful in addressing the nationality problems that women have historically faced—are superseded by the human rights standard contained in Article 9(1) of the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women which states: ‘States Parties shall grant women equal rights with men to acquire, change or retain their nationality’. By analogy then, while it remains of utmost importance to take measures to protect people from being rendered stateless, this norm cannot be invoked in a way that excuses from closer scrutiny policies that withdraw nationality from dual nationals only. As this article set out, it is unclear how nationality revocation as a counter-terrorism measure would ever pass the non-discrimination and proportionality tests prescribed by international law and thereby satisfy the norm prohibiting arbitrary deprivation of nationality.

States have an arsenal of counter-terrorism measures that they can apply, equally, to all citizens. As such, a change of perspective on the legitimacy, merits and wisdom of invoking citizenship deprivation—an inherently unequal measure—to ensure national security appears to be overdue. These measures need to be challenged for their discriminatory nature and effects.Footnote 69 Given the wider implications that unequal citizenship has in terms of creating a suspect group within society and eroding one of the key foundations of democratic society, states should in fact be lining up to abolish the outmoded measure of casting citizens out from their own political community.