1 Introduction

The extent to which generations of researchers raise a certain issue is an indicator of its importance. One issue that researchers have repeatedly debated is a unified explanation for play of the St. Petersburg game, a paradox that has attracted researchers’ interest for 300 years (Neugebauer 2010; Seidl 2013). In the original version of the St. Petersburg Game, a fair coin is tossed until it comes up heads for the first time. The game pays 2n with n indicating the number of tosses it takes for the first occurrence of heads. While the St. Petersburg game in its original version offers an infinite expected value, people are found to pay no more than $25 for hypothetical offers to participate in the game, which may be regarded as irrational decision-making (Hacking 1980).

The paradox unfolds an immense importance in many diverse fields such as statistical decision analysis (Seidl 2013), econophysics (Takayasu 2010), business ethics (Shrader-Frechette 1985), economics (Rieger and Wang 2006; Samuelson 1960), psychology (Mishra 2014; Chechile and Barch 2013), and even evolutionary theory (Real 1980), in particular animals’ foraging decisions studied in zoology (Real 1996). In the business research context, researchers routinely refer to the paradox when discussing and analyzing, for example, crashes of high-tech stocks (Székely and Richards 2004) and more generally the extent to which speculator psychology has attained an irrational bent at stock markets (Durand 1957), optimal contracting decisions (Mookherjee and Png 1989), optimal portfolio strategies (Rubinstein 2002), newsvendor order decisions (Wang et al. 2009), and loss aversion in consumer behavior (Camerer 2005).

Against this background, modeling play of the St. Petersburg game is essential in many fields. Although several explanations are proposed as solutions to this paradox, there is no general agreement on a unified model valid for different versions of the paradox. This article adds another layer of complexity to the topic, in that we present experimental evidence that shows similar play in finite St. Petersburg games with conventional positive prizes (2n) and negative prizes (− 2n), as monetary payments but also in waiting time. These results are not compatible with loss aversion. Our data suggest that St. Petersburg games elicit similar choices that are invariant to the sign of prizes. As such, we hope our results will contribute to the ongoing discussion of the topic by providing new evidence on decisions about play of St. Petersburg games when prizes are negative, an issue that has been overlooked in the literature.

2 Literature review and experiment overview

Various researchers have provided explanations for the St. Petersburg paradox (e.g., Seidl 2013; Rieger and Wang 2006; Blavatskyy 2005), but with every explanation a new version of the initial game was constructed that brought back the puzzle (Samuelson 1977). Versions of the game have been constructed that challenge all currently popular theories of decision under risk (Cox and Sadiraj 2009).

Historically, the first explanation for the observed behavior was decreasing marginal utility of the outcome (Bernoulli 1954, originally published in 1738). However, for unbounded utilities, games can be constructed with prizes correcting for decreasing marginal utility and the paradox remains.Footnote 1

Therefore, the focus shifted towards the credibility of “infinity” (i.e., no bounds on potential prizes, or on the number of coin flips). Limited time was introduced to bind the value of the St. Petersburg game (Brito 1975; Cowen and High 1988). In contrast, it was argued that the value of the lottery could in principle be unbounded but the offer to play the game is most probably not considered to be credible (Shapley 1977), explaining the decision patterns found in experimental studies. The most favored solution of the paradox, however, is that utility is bound since otherwise one can always create lotteries leading to counterintuitive solutions (Aumann 1977). But bounding utility substitutes one paradox for another: with bounded utility, an agent will exhibit implausible large-stakes risk-aversion (Cox and Sadiraj 2009).

To avoid infinity, the St. Petersburg Game was broken down into a series of finite games, but the paradox does not disappear (Samuelson 1960), questioning infinity as the underlying cause of the paradox. Other work argues that perception of small probabilities of large payoffs is the source of the paradox since sufficiently small probabilities are regarded as zero (Brito 1975) or small chances for large prizes create big risks for the agents (Allais 1952; Weirich 1984) who are willing to buy the game at a large price. In another approach on using probabilities as an explanation for the phenomenon, more recent work introduced a new weighting function for cumulative prospect theory, attempting to solve the problem of infinity (Blavatskyy 2005).

Experimental research has turned to a modified version of the question originally posed by Bernoulli: Is human choice behavior in St. Petersburg lotteries consistent with expected value theory in finite versions of the game that involve few coin tosses, n? Initial experiments followed the general idea that financial incentives provide subjects with an economic motivation for truthfully revealing ranking of available options (Camerer and Hogarth 1999). Thus, experiments based on enhanced designs (Cox et al. 2009; Neugebauer 2010) have used real-money payoffs and finite versions of the St. Petersburg game. Data from these experiments are inconsistent with risk-neutrality but consistent with risk-aversion for moderate n (> 5) providing support for Bernoulli’s general conclusion about risk-aversion (though not about a log specification) as the source of low willingness to pay for playing the game.

The present paper reports on two experiments that implement a modification of the St. Petersburg lotteries used in Cox et al. (2009), replacing positive prizes with negative ones. In Experiment 1, prizes in the St. Petersburg lotteries are − 2n where n is the number of coin tosses it takes to (first) turn up a head, which determines how much subjects get paid to play the game. That means, instead of offering subjects an opportunity to pay money for participating in a St. Petersburg game with positive prizes, this experiment provides subjects with an opportunity to receive money payment for accepting an offer to participate in a St. Petersburg game in which they can only lose money. Because this sign-mirror version of the St. Petersburg game offers stochastic losses, people may make different decisions depending on whether they are risk-loving or risk-averse over losses, a topic on which there is mixed evidence (e.g., Kahneman and Tversky 1979; Holt and Laury 2002, 2005; Åstebro et al. 2015). Previous research suggests that individuals tend to be risk-seeking when it comes to gambling involving the possibility to avert financial losses (e.g., Kahneman and Tversky 1984; Scholer et al. 2010; Rieger et al. 2015). Furthermore, if St. Petersburg play follows from sufficiently small probabilities being regarded as zero (Brito 1975) then we should expect larger willingness to play the game with negative prizes than with positive prizes.

For both the original version of the (finite) St. Petersburg lotteries taken from Cox et al. (2009) and the lotteries developed for this study, participants decide about tradeoffs between possible monetary gains and losses. In the n = 3 version of the game, a subject who decides to participate pays €2.75 for sure and receives €2 (in the case the coin lands Head the first time), €4 in the event T → H (that is the first land is Tail and the second one is Head), €8 in the event T → T → H and €0 otherwise (that is, the event T → T → T). The expected value of participating in the n = 3 version of the finite St. Petersburg game is €0.25.

In total, 80% of the subjects decided to pay €2.75 to participate in the game (Cox et al. 2009). In the n = 3 version of the sign-mirror St. Petersburg game, the game of interest in this paper, a subject who decides to participate gets paid €3 for sure but pays back €2 in the event H, €4 in the event T → H, €8 in the event T → T → H, and €0 in the case of event T → T → T. (see Table 1 for n = 4 and n = 9). The expected value of participating in the n = 3 sign-mirror version of the finite St. Petersburg game is €0. It is not clear how people will play this game in that the game participation is ex ante mixed (total payoff, which is prize plus payment for playing, can be positive or negative depending on the resolution of the risk), whereas the prizes that the game offers are all negative. Risk-aversion, by definition, implies rejection of the St. Petersburg game with negative prizes, Sn for all n as the expected value of participation is zero. Furthermore, with expected utility, risk-aversion implies that the likelihood of rejecting St. Petersburg game increases with n.Footnote 2 This is consistent with the pattern observed in Cox et al. (2009) (but also in data from the new experiments reported in this paper). On the other hand, with loss aversionFootnote 3 acceptance of participation in the conventional St. Petersburg game implies rejection of its sign-mirror St. Petersburg game.

Table 1 St. Petersburg lotteries for monetary losses (for n = 4 and n = 9 games)

Because the (prize plus participation payment) domain of participation in a St. Petersburg game (with positive or negative prizes) is mixed, we conducted another experiment (Experiment 2), reported later in the paper, with same lotteries as in Experiment 1, but with the difference that negative money prizes are replaced by waiting times. Additionally, in another control treatment we elicited subjects’ preferences for waiting times using Holt and Laury’s (2005) procedure. Our subjects’ choices revealed risk-seeking attitudes when choosing waiting times in the control treatment, which implies that our subjects accept the negative St. Petersburg games (as the expected value of participation and nonparticipation is 0). In Experiment 2, we also observe decisions on participation in St. Petersburg lotteries constructed from the domain of waiting times used in the control treatment.

Data from the experiments reported in this paper show that decisions on participating in St. Petersburg games are invariant to the sign of prizes. If risk attitudes over negative payoffs are risk-seeking (a common finding in the literature as well as in our risk elicitation control treatment in Experiment 2), then data from experiments in this paper challenge stability of risk attitudes over negative prizes. Thus, the present research re-emphasizes a fruitful field of future inquiry on risk attitudes in negative domains of payoffs.

3 Experiment 1: the St. Petersburg game with monetary payments

3.1 Experimental design and procedure

Fifteen students from a major German university from different fields of study participated in the experiment. Subjects were invited by email and were informed that the experiment would spread over 2 weeks and that real losses could result from participation, but the losses could be avoided by individuals’ decisions. Subjects were also informed that, in the event that a participant realized a loss, she would have to pay it from her own money.

During the first meeting, the participants received a show-up fee of €10. The information from the invitation was read aloud to the subjects and, subsequently, the participants filled out a form stating they were fully aware of the information provided by the experimenter and they agreed to pay any losses that might occur from participation in the experiment.

The actual experiment on decisions about St. Petersburg lotteries was performed during the second meeting, 2 weeks later, which minimizes the possibility of introducing a bias resulting from house-money effects (e.g., Rosenboim and Shavit 2012; Thaler and Johnson 1990). The experiment consisted of the same lotteries used in Cox et al. (2009) with the only difference being that all payoffs were multiplied by the factor − 1 (i.e., a sign-mirrored version of a finite St. Petersburg original game). For a total of 9 lotteries, the participants could choose between participating in the lottery or not (see Table 1 for n = 4 and n = 9). The lotteries varied in the maximum number of coin tosses, n with n = 1, 2,…,9. After the participants made their decisions for all of the 9 lotteries, for each participant one lottery was randomly chosen for realization.

A subject choosing to participate in a lottery, Sn with maximum of n tosses received n euros. Then a coin was tossed until either a head occurred or the maximum number (n) of tosses for that lottery was reached. If the coin turned up heads on the ith (i < n) toss, the participant was required to pay €2i.

If the coin did not turn up heads on any of the n tosses, the participant was not required to pay anything and her payoff remained at n euros. Thus, potential payoffs from the game participation are n, n −2, n −4,…, n −2n with probabilities ½n, ½, ¼, …, ½n. In case of a rejection, the subject receives no payment. The expected value of the St. Petersburg game, Sn is − n, and therefore the expected value of participation is 0. Risk-seeking individuals would prefer participation whereas risk-averse individuals would reject it.Footnote 4

3.2 Results of Experiment 1

The analysis of the data from our version of the St. Petersburg lotteries is adapted from the procedures used in Cox et al. (2009) to make comparisons. The analysis focuses on the proportion of subjects rejecting the St. Petersburg lottery for the maximum number of coin tosses, n. For the original form of the St. Petersburg lotteries involving positive prizes, researchers (Cox et al. 2009; Neugebauer 2010) found that the proportion of subjects rejecting a lottery increased with increasing numbers of maximum tosses of the coin, which is consistent with risk-aversion because increasing n increases the spread of payoffs while preserving the mean. We see the same pattern in the sign-mirror version of St. Petersburg game with negative prizes. Figure 1 shows choices for positive prizes (light grey bars) and negative prizes (dark grey bars). While the proportion of subjects rejecting the lotteries is higher on average with negative prizes, the pattern of increasing rejections appears in both games. Therefore, there is a pattern to be found when subjects make decisions about St. Petersburg lotteries that is robust to whether monetary prizes are positive or negative. Specifically, a significant correlation between the n and the number of subjects rejecting to play (rSpearman = 0.983, p < 0.001) supports the notion of increasing rejection. Likewise, across n, the Pearson correlation between the rates of rejection reported in Cox et al. (2009) and Experiment 1 approaches 1 (rPearson = 0.941, p < 0.001). Additionally, whereas risk-seeking behavior suggests an increasing willingness to play with increasing n, we were not able to observe this tendency for any of the individuals (p < 0.001 in a binomial test). With S-shaped utility and loss aversion, acceptance of positive St. Petersburg game implies rejection of negative St. Petersburg game (see “Appendix”). This is rejected by data from games with 1, 2, and 3 tosses. Acceptance rates in the positive St. Petersburg game are [0.87, 0.87, 0.8]; rejection rates in the negative St. Petersburg game are predicted to be larger but we observe [0.4, 0.47, 0.67].

Fig. 1
figure 1

Comparison of choices for positive or negative money prizes

3.3 Discussion of Experiment 1

The experiment’s results highlight that St. Petersburg game play is invariant to gain vs. loss framing of lotteries. Experiment 1, however, involves two limitations. First, literature proposes that subjects sometimes might have a hard time believing that potential financial losses realized in experiments become relevant for them (e.g., Thaler and Johnson 1990). Likewise, a special type of subject tends to be more prone to participate in experiments with potential monetary losses, creating the possibility of a selection bias (Etchart-Vincent and l’Haridon 2011). Both aspects could be problematic for the internal validity of findings.Footnote 5 Second, Experiment 1 drew on extant studies in assuming a risk-seeking tendency for gambles on financial losses. Therefore, we did not control whether our subjects’ risk attitudes over losses were risk-seeking.

Experiment 2 addresses the aforementioned issues, while simultaneously operating with a larger sample. This second investigation substitutes waiting times for financial losses, which previously has been shown to provide an appropriate way for integration of realized losses in the context of prospect theory experiments (e.g., Abdellaoui and Kemel 2014). In addition, a control treatment provides data, which reveals that subjects are risk-seeking in gambles over waiting times.

4 Experiment 2: waiting times

4.1 Experimental design and procedure

The experiment was conducted with 86 students from different fields of study enrolled at the same major German university as in Experiment 1. The participants were randomly divided into three groups, with one eliciting risk preferences for waiting time (Treatment 1, 36 participants), and two groups playing St. Petersburg lotteries with different base waiting times (Treatment 2, 25 participants, 10 min and Treatment 3, 25 participants, 45 min). All participants received a show-up fee of €8 before experiment instructions were handed out in the university’s behavioral economics laboratory. Furthermore, it was made clear that there would be no other monetary rewards from participation in the experiment other than the consequences described in the experiment instructions. Unlike Experiment 1, the second experiment did not draw on two separate appointments because subjects are unlikely to integrate a monetary show-up fee with waiting times into one mental account (Abdellaoui and Kemel 2014).

4.1.1 Risk preference for waiting time

To elicit preferences over waiting time, participants were asked to choose between two lotteries in each of ten pairs of lotteries where “payoffs” were determined as waiting time. After choices were made, one choice pair was randomly selected for realization (e.g., Lichters et al. 2016). In the experiment, participants were told that their decisions would determine a waiting time in the laboratory. This waiting time started after all decisions were made and the chosen lotteries were played out. The participants spent this waiting time in a laboratory cabin without any communication devices or books.

The options were presented in a format similar to the one used in Holt and Laury (2005), where option A offered less risk but a higher minimum waiting time (with a waiting time of either 30 or 40 min), and option B offered a higher risk but the chance of a much smaller waiting time (with a waiting time of either 5 or 60 min). The probability of the favorable outcome was always the same in the two options but varied between 0.1 and 1.0 as shown in Table 2. Therefore, risk preferences for waiting time could be elicited for each participant by the row in which option B was chosen over A for the first time. If the switching point was in row four or earlier, the choice pattern would indicate risk-seeking behavior, if it was in row five or later, the choice pattern would show risk-averse behavior.

Table 2 Lottery choices determining waiting time

After the choices were made, the experimenter drew a ball from a bingo cage with balls labeled from one to ten that determined which decision was selected. Then the outcome from the lottery the participant chose for the decision in the corresponding row was realized and the waiting time started.

4.1.2 St. Petersburg game

Participants in these treatments were offered a series of St. Petersburg lotteries. All subjects had a base waiting time (Treatment 2, 10 min; Treatment 3, 45 min) and were offered an opportunity to participate in a lottery where this waiting time could be reduced or increased depending on their decision and the outcome of the lottery. This lottery was designed analogously to the St. Petersburg lottery used in Experiment 1 (and Cox et al. 2009). For participation in the lottery, the waiting time was first reduced by n minutes and subsequently a coin was tossed until a head occurred, with a maximum of n tosses. If head occurred on the ith toss, the waiting time was increased by 2i minutes. Each participant was offered nine lotteries with only one decision being randomly selected for implementation, with the lotteries differing by the maximum number of tosses n. Table 3 shows potential waiting times for n = 9 and base time 10 min, here we describe the case for n = 3. Suppose decision 3 was randomly selected for implementation. If the subject had chosen not to play the game then his waiting time was at the base waiting time of 10 min (or 45 min in the 45 min base-time condition).

Table 3 St. Petersburg lotteries for waiting time (n = 9, base time 10 min)

If the subject had chosen to play the game, then the base waiting time was reduced by 3 min–7 (or 42) minutes. Then, a coin was tossed. If it came up heads at the first toss (an event with probability ½), the waiting time was increased by 2–9 (or 44) min. If it came up heads at the second toss (an event with likelihood ¼), the waiting time was increased by 4 min–11 (or 46) min. If it came up heads at the third toss, the waiting time was increased by 8 min–15 (or 50) min. If the coin did not come up heads at any of the three tosses, the waiting time remained at 7 (or 42) min.

After the participants made their choices, the experimenter drew a ball from a bingo cage containing balls numbered from one through nine to select which game would be realized. Waiting time for all participants who chose not to play the selected game was the baseline time. For each participant who chose to play the game, the experimenter tossed the coin as described above and determined the actual waiting time. All participants spent their waiting time in a laboratory cabin without communication devices or other kinds of entertainment possibility. To control for scale and/or reference point effect (Farber 2008; Kőszegi and Rabin 2007), we ran two treatments with different base waiting times of 10 and 45 min.

4.2 Results of Experiment 2

4.2.1 Risk preferences for waiting time

As described above, subjects can be classified as risk-seeking or risk-averse for choices on waiting time by looking at the first row in which option B is chosen. In Table 2, it can be inferred from the differences in expected values that risk-seeking individuals would choose option B for the first time in row four or earlier, while the switching point from option A to option B would be in row five or later for risk-averse subjects. Table 4 reports the frequencies for rows in which subjects switched to option B: any subject who chooses option A in rows one through three and chooses option B in rows four through ten is noted in column four, while any subject who chooses option A in rows one through four and then switches to option B is noted in column five.

Table 4 Risk-preference for waiting time
Table 5 Illustration of valuations of St. Petersburg games with linearity in probabilities and power function of payoffs \(\begin{aligned} u(x) = \frac{1}{1 - r}x^{1 - r} ,\quad \quad x > 0 \hfill \\ \quad \quad = - \frac{\lambda }{1 - r}( - x)^{1 - r} ,\quad x < 0 \hfill \\ \end{aligned}\)

We observe 27 out of 36 subjects (75.00%; 95% CI [0.58, 0.88]) who made choices consistent with risk-seeking behavior. Therefore, we conclude that the vast majority of subjects exhibit risk-seeking behavior when making decisions about stochastic waiting time (p = 0.002, binomial test).

4.2.2 St. Petersburg game

Data from elicitation of risk attitudes over waiting time suggest that the majority of subjects are risk-seeking and therefore would play all of the offered St. Petersburg lotteries for waiting time. The expected value of the offered gambles on waiting times is equal to the base waiting time. Therefore, a risk-seeking individual would choose to participate in all offered gambles. Data from the St. Petersburg game with waiting times as prizes show that while individuals do participate in the gambles for small reductions of the base waiting time, they do not for higher possible reductions of the base waiting time. Furthermore, decision patterns are similar to those found in the real-payoff experiment with St. Petersburg lotteries with positive money prizes (Cox et al. 2009) and to the Experiment 1 reported above, with negative money prizes (Fig. 2).

Fig. 2
figure 2

Comparison of rejecting St. Petersburg lotteries of money risk-averse and time risk-seeking subjects

With increasing n, subjects exerted decreasing willingness to play. Within the 10-min condition (dark grey bars), the correlation between n and the number of subjects rejecting is rSpearman = 0.880, p = 0.002, whereas the 45-min condition (ocher bars) yields an r of 953, p < 0.001. Like in Experiment 1 on monetary losses, both waiting time conditions show a pronounced correlation with the results reported by Cox et al. (2009) on positive monetary prizes (rPearson, 10 min = 0.922, p < 0.001, rPearson, 45 min = 0.937, p < 0.001). Again, we were hardly able to observe risk-seeking-conform behavior at the individual level (increasing willingness to play with increasing n), either in the 10-min condition (3/25, p < 0.001 in a binomial test) nor in the 45-min condition (1/25, p < 0.001 in a binomial test).

In the treatment with a base waiting time of 10 min, 2 of the 25 participants chose to never play the game, while the rest mostly started by playing the first game, but switched to answering ‘no’ at some n. None of the participants chose to play all offered games. The data from the treatment with a base waiting time of 45 min yielded similar results. Fewer subjects were willing to play lotteries with high reductions of the base waiting time (n ≥7) than observed in the 10-min treatment. However, the difference is not meaningful, as we were not able to identify significant differences based on Fisher’s exact tests: pn = 7 =0.609, pn = 8 =0.609, pn = 9 =1.0.

5 Discussion and conclusion

The St. Petersburg paradox was initially designed to challenge expected value theory. It inspired the idea of using utilities, with decreasing marginal utility of money, rather than monetary payoffs to resolve the paradox. From that point on, economists have focused on developing theories of decision-making under risk that can accommodate risk-averse behavior as initially reported for hypothetical experiments with the infinite horizon St. Petersburg lottery. Alternative ways of modeling risk-aversion have been proposed in the literature (for a review of mathematical model attempts see, Seidl 2013). Risk-averse behavior can be modeled by nonlinear transformation of: (1) payoffs (Bernoulli 1954; Pratt 1964; Arrow 1971), (2) probabilities (Yaari 1987), or (3) both (Quiggin 1993; Tversky and Kahneman 1992). But there are versions of St. Petersburg lotteries that produce paradoxes for all of these theories if they are defined on unbounded domains (Cox and Sadiraj 2009). If, instead, the domain is bounded, then the paradox disappears. For example, if the largest credible prize offered in a St. Petersburg lottery is 35 billion euros, then the expected value of the lottery is about 35 euros and it would not be paradoxical if people were unwilling to pay large amounts to play.

Although the original infinite horizon St. Petersburg game cannot credibly be offered to anyone in a real-payoff experiment, finite versions are still of interest for elicitation of risk preferences. Real-money experiments with positive prize St. Petersburg lotteries produced data that are inconsistent with risk-neutrality but consistent with risk-aversion (Cox and Sadiraj 2009; Neugebauer 2010). Data from the first experiment in this paper implement a setting in which subjects are believed to be risk-loving. It is interesting to see that St. Petersburg lotteries elicit similar behavior with negative or positive monetary prizes. Even more strikingly, our second experiment on the St. Petersburg game, with waiting times as prizes, elicits similar patterns of behavior even though most subjects appear to be risk seekers in this domain. The payoff domain invariance of behavior in these St. Petersburg games provides a challenge for decision theory under risk.

While the hypothesis of infinity (Brito 1975; Cowen and High 1988), associated with the original form of the game, is not directly relevant for our finite St. Petersburg games, the concern on whether participants would regard the offer of the original game as credible (Shapley 1977) remains valid. Thus, while infinity is not the problem in our games, is it possible to control whether participants regarded the offer as genuine?

If subjects would regard an offer as not credible, it is reasonable to assume that high monetary losses or the longer waiting times would not be realized and, therefore, a subject playing the lotteries with relatively large maximum number of coin tosses, n would prefer participation in St. Petersburg game with negative prizes. That is not what we observe in the experiment.

Other papers argue that very small probabilities are regarded as zero (Brito 1975) or that small probabilities for high wins result in a high risk for the decision maker (Allais 1952; Weirich 1984) with a large payment. While these arguments can explain increasing pattern of rejections for positive St. Petersburg game, they fail badly in explaining increasing pattern of rejections of participation that we observe in our data from St. Petersburg games with negative prizes. This is so as nullification of small probabilities or increasing risk for a risk-seeker (as revealed in Holt–Laury elicitation treatment in Experiment 2) make participation in the game with negative prizes more attractive as n increases, so we should observe a decreasing pattern of rejections as n increases, the opposite of what we see in our data, with monetary payment as well as waiting time.

In conclusion, it can be noted that various conjectures have been advanced to explain behavior with St. Petersburg lotteries. However, with the exception of risk-aversion, none of the conjectures can explain what is observed in our experiments with decisions for real monetary and waiting time outcomes. Nevertheless, while risk-aversion can explain behavior in our St. Petersburg game, such risk-aversion in the waiting time experiments conflicts with risk-seeking attitudes elicited by the Holt–Laury procedure.

As our results are both, surprising and relevant to business research, future researchers should empirically reevaluate models that have been proposed to explain the behavior observed in the St. Petersburg paradox relying on experiments involving real economic consequences. Likewise, other domains of seemingly irrational decision-making would benefit from experiments drawing on real consequences involving losses. For example, in case of violations of rational choice such as context-dependent choice (Cox et al. 2014), researchers recently discovered that some choice anomalies decrease (e.g., the compromise effect, Lichters et al. 2015) while others increase (e.g., the attraction effect, Lichters et al. 2017) in magnitude with the introduction of economic consequences instead of mere hypothetical choices.