Skip to main content
Log in

Transitive supermajority rule relations

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Bulletin Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper identifies necessary and sufficient single-profile conditions for a consistent decision under a supermajority rule. It is demonstrated that a preference profile generates a transitive supermajority rule relation if and only if it is not sufficiently balanced. These conditions link transitivity of a supermajority rule to the cardinal outcomes of plurality and anti-plurality elections.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For the case of simple majority rule in particular, existence of a maximal element is guaranteed when preferences are intermediate (Grandmont 1978; Rothstein 1990) and when they satisfy the single-crossing property (Gans and Smart 1996). Barberà and Moreno (2011) suggest the top-monotonicity domain restriction, which includes the previous ones, and extend the result of Austen-Smith and Banks (2000) to these types of preferences.

  2. Consider for example a university department which has an open tenure-track position and an open post-doc position and three candidates for both these positions.

  3. For every supermajority rule one may find preferences profiles such that the resulting supermajority rule relation is intransitive (see Greenberg 1979). Caplin and Nalebuff (1988) show, though, that under certain non-extreme domain restrictions, a \(64\%-\)majority rule never results to electoral cycles.

  4. Simple majority has many good properties (Dasgupta and Maskin 2008) compared to other rules (including supermajorities) and has been characterized by May (1952) and Campbell and Kelly (2000).

  5. Moreover, Xefteris (2013) provides single-profile conditions for the transitivity of the Pareto extension order.

  6. In anti-plurality elections each voter votes once for her most disliked alternative and the least voted alternative wins.

  7. Notice that \(\mathcal {P}\subset \mathcal {R}\subset \mathcal {C}.\)

  8. We say that a preference relation satisfies transitivity if it satisfies the following four properties (see Chapter [2] in Arrow 1963):

    $$\begin{aligned} xPy,yPz\rightarrow xPz&(PP \mathrm{property}) \\ xPy,yIz\rightarrow xPz&(PI \mathrm{property}) \\ xIy,yPz\rightarrow xPz&(IP \mathrm{property}) \\ xIy,yIz\rightarrow xIz&(II \mathrm{property}) \end{aligned}$$

    Arrow (1963) notion of transitivity is indeed demanding. For a group of weaker transitivity notions one is referred to Cato (2013).

  9. This is without loss of generality since any supermajority rule can be modeled by an \(a^{*}\) that satisfies these constraints. We explain the necessity of this technical assumption after the presentation of the formal analysis.

  10. To see this, suppose that \(N=\{1,2,3\}\) and assume that \(P_{1}=P_{2}\). Moreover, assume that agents \(1\) and \(3\) are mutually exclusive. Then \(N_{0}\) consists of either \(1\) or \(2\). However, the preferences of the agent in \(N_{0}\) remain the same.

  11. Notice that when \(n\) is an even number there is a possibility that the reduced population set is empty \((N_{0}^{\prime }=N)\). In this case (a) condition (ii) is trivially violated (\(a^{*}>0\) implies \(a>-1/2\) and hence \(\frac{n_{0}-1}{2}-a<0\)) and (b) any supermajority rule gives a social ordering with indifferences only, since for every \(x\) and \(y\) exactly half of the population prefers \(x\) over \(y\) (transitivity is satisfied).

  12. On contrary we would have \(\frac{n_{0}-1}{2}-a<0\). This inequality, together with the fact that every alternative is top-ranked and bottom-ranked for at least zero individuals violates condition (ii).

  13. Notice that the second ranked alternative has to be different in each of the \(Q_{i}\)’s. Otherwise we would have a preference profile with a mutually exclusive pair. This implies that the top alternatives could be different in every linear order \(Q_{i}\) (case b) or that there is one alternative that is top (last) choice in two linear orders (case a).

References

  • Arrow, K.J.: Social choice and invidual values, vol. 12. Yale university press (1963)

  • Austen-Smith, D., Banks, J.S.: Positive political theory: collective preference, vol. 1. University of Michigan Press (2000)

  • Barberà, S., Moreno, B.: Top monotonicity: a common root for single peakedness, single crossing and the median voter result. Games Econ. Behav. 73(2), 345–359 (2011)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Black, D.: On the rationale of group decision-making. J. Polit. Econ. pp. 23–34 (1948)

  • Black, D.: The theory of committees and elections. Springer (1986)

  • Campbell, D.E., Kelly, J.S.: A simple characterization of majority rule. Econ. Theory 15(3), 689–700 (2000)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Caplin, A., Nalebuff, B.: On 64%-majority rule. Econometrica J. Econ. Soc. pp. 787–814 (1988)

  • Cato, S.: Social choice, the strong pareto principle, and conditional decisiveness. Theory Decis. 75(4), 563–579 (2013)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Coughlin, P.J.: Necessary and sufficient conditions for \(\delta \)-relative majority voting equilibria. Econometrica 49(5), 1223–1224 (1981)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P., Maskin, E.: On the robustness of majority rule. J. Eur. Econ. Assoc. 6(5), 949–973 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feld, S.L., Grofman, B.: Research note partial single-peakedness: an extension and clarification. Public Choice 51(1), 71–80 (1986)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C.: The theory of social choice, vol. 264. Princeton University Press Princeton (1973)

  • Gans, J.S., Smart, M.: Majority voting with single-crossing preferences. J. Public Econ. 59(2), 219–237 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grandmont, J.M.: Intermediate preferences and the majority rule. Econometrica 46(2), 317–330 (1978)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, J.: Consistent majority rules over compact sets of alternatives. Econometrica 47(3), 627–636 (1979)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, J., Weber, S.: Consistent d-relative majority equilibria. Econometrica 53(2), 463–464 (1985)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Inada, Ki: A note on the simple majority decision rule. Econometrica 32(4), 525–531 (1964)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Kaneko, M.: Necessary and sufficient conditions for transitivity in voting theory. J. Econ. Theory 11(3), 385–393 (1975)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • May, K.O.: A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision. Econometrica 20(4), 680–684 (1952)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Parks, R.P.: An impossibility theorem for fixed preferences: a dictatorial bergson-samuelson welfare function. Rev. Econ. Stud. 43(3), 447–450 (1976)

    Article  MATH  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, P.: Order restricted preferences and majority rule. Soc. Choice Welf. 7(4), 331–342 (1990)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A., Pattanaik, P.K.: Necessary and sufficient conditions for rational choice under majority decision. J. Econ. Theory 1(2), 178–202 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A.K.: A possibility theorem on majority decisions. Econometrica 34(2), 491–499 (1966)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Slutsky, S.: Equilibrium under \(\alpha \)-majority voting. Econometrica 47(5), 1113–1125 (1979)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Xefteris, D.: A necessary and sufficient single-profile condition for transitivity of the majority rule relation. Economics Lett. 116(3), 516–518 (2012)

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Xefteris, D.: A necessary and sufficient single-profile condition for transitivity of the pareto extension order. Int. J. Econ. Theory 9(4), 313–317 (2013)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank S. Barberà and B. Moreno for helpful discussions and suggestions about the topic. R. Gjorgjiev acknowledges the researchers Grant ECO/1186/2013 provided by Agència de Gestió d’Ajuts Universitaris i de Recerca. R. Gjorgjiev also acknowledges the financial support from Ministerio de Ciencia e Innovación through grant ECO2013-45395-R and Generalitat de Catalunya through Grant 2014-SGR-1360.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dimitrios Xefteris.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gjorgjiev, R., Xefteris, D. Transitive supermajority rule relations. Econ Theory Bull 3, 299–312 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-014-0060-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-014-0060-6

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation