1 Introduction

According to the relational theory of memory, genuine memories are relational states of affairs consisting in the acquaintance relation obtaining between the remembering subject and an event she once experienced.Footnote 1 In cases of total confabulation, however, the experiencing subject is not acquainted with any past event.Footnote 2 Consequently, relationalists must endorse a disjunctive theory of episodic memory, on which cases of genuine memory and cases of mere confabulation involve distinct kinds of mental event with different natures. In cases of genuine memory, the relevant experience has a past event that the subject once experienced as a constituent. In cases of total confabulation, by contrast, this is not so, and hence confabulatory experiences must be given a different analysis.Footnote 3,Footnote 4

This aim if this paper is not to motivate disjunctivism. Rather, I take it to be a view well worth taking seriously, and am concerned here instead with two related challenges to it, which are analogues of the ‘casual argument’ and the ‘screening off argument’ that have been pressed in recent literature against the relationalist (and hence disjunctivist) theory of perception.Footnote 5 The first part of the paper sets out these two arguments against the memory disjunctivist (sections 2 and 3). The second part then develops a novel and unified response to these two arguments on the memory disjunctivist’s behalf (sections 4 and 5). The central claim to be advanced is that to reply to these two arguments, memory disjunctivists both can and should draw on resources that are already standardly appealed to by traditional common factor theories of memory, and, in particular, to the idea that genuine memories and merely confabulatory ones are to be distinguished, at least in part, in terms of the distinctive ways in which they are caused. On the proposed view, there are substantive causal constraints associated both with cases of genuine memory and with cases of mere confabulation. The theory thus tells us something important about the nature both of genuine memories and of mere confabulations, namely, that such experiences must be caused in certain distinctive ways and cannot occur except as the result of distinctive sorts of causal process. In addition, the proposed view enables the disjunctivist to offer a unified response to an important pair of arguments against her view.

2 The Causal Argument

In light of their commitment to disjunctivism, relational theories of memory face an argument analogous to the ‘causal argument from hallucination’ that has been pressed against relationalist theories of perception.Footnote 6 We might refer to this as the ‘causal argument from confabulation’.Footnote 7 It relies on two main premises:

Proximate Causes

For every genuine memory experience, m, there is a nomically possible confabulatory experience, c, with the same proximate cause as m.

And,

Same Cause, Same Effect

If an event of kind A is the proximate cause of an event of kind B, then, it is nomically necessary that whenever an event of kind A occurs, it produces an effect of kind B as its immediate effect.

Both premises are plausible. Jointly, however, they imply that the disjunctivist theory of memory is false. Consider the following argument. In cases of total confabulation, there is no past event with which one is acquainted. For memory disjunctivists, however, genuine memories constitutively involve acquaintance with past events. Accordingly, such theorists must deny that one can be have the sort of experience involved in genuine memory in merely confabulatory cases. By Proximate Causes, however, we can imagine a memory experience m and a confabulatory experience c with the same proximate cause. Therefore, by Same Cause, Same Effect, we can infer that an experience of the same kind as m will be produced by the brain state that produces c. This, however, implies that one could have the sort of experience involved in genuine memory in a merely confabulatory case, contrary to what disjunctivists must say.

To reply to this argument, disjunctivists must reject either Proximate Causes or Same Cause, Same Effect. It seems to me, however, that they should accept Proximate Causes. In general, it is plausible to think that psychological states and events, including memories (both real and apparent), have antecedent neural causes.Footnote 8 Given that, however, it seems easy to imagine, for each genuine memory, a merely confabulatory experience that has an antecedent neural cause of the same kind. Presumably, such token neural causes would have importantly different aetiologies. However, they could well be neural causes of the same type.Footnote 9

If that is right, then to push back against the causal argument, memory disjunctivists should challenge Same Cause, Same Effect. Later on, I develop a response that does just that (see section 5). First, however, it is worth flagging a version of this move that will not work. In the perception literature, relationalists about perception tend to respond to the causal argument from hallucination by criticising Same Cause, Same Effect on the grounds that it rules out the existence of relational effects of a certain kind, namely relational effects one of whose relata need not exist just in virtue of the existence of the relevant kind of proximate cause (Campbell: 2010: §§3–4; Nudds 2013: 274–275; Langsam, 1997: 42–46; Martin 2004: 56–58; 2006: 268–371; McDowell 2010; Travis 2011). What relationalists about perception claim is that perceptual experiences consist in the relation of acquaintance obtaining between subjects and external objects of awareness. For such relationalists, therefore, genuinely perceptual experiences can occur only given that there exists a suitable object of perception. Moreover, no mere proximate brain state could guarantee that this condition is met. The relationalist about perception can therefore object to Same Cause, Same Effect on the basis that it wrongly rules out the kind of relational effect that she takes to be involved in genuine perception. The present thought I want to consider is that in the same way, the memory disjunctivist might object to Same Cause, Same Effect on the grounds that genuine memories constitutively involve acquaintance with past events, but that no mere brain state could guarantee that a suitable past event exists—meaning that no such brain state could be sufficient to produce a genuine memory, contrary to what Same Cause, Same Effect implies.

It should be granted, I think, that this reply would undermine the causal argument in its original form. After all, insisting on the Same Cause, Same Effect principle at this stage would seem to beg the question against any disjunctivist view, including relationalist views of both memory and perception, that recognises the existence of genuinely relational effects. Unfortunately, however, the causal argument, both from hallucination and from confabulation, can be patched up by appealing to cases of veridical hallucination/veridical confabulation.Footnote 10 To see this, consider the following weaker version of the causal principle:

Same Cause, Same Effect*

If an event of kind A is the proximate cause of an event of kind B, then it is nomically necessary that if an event of kind A occurs in some context C, such that in C, all of the background conditions on a kind-B effect occurring are met, the kind-A event will produce a kind-B event as its immediate effect.

Essentially, the response to the causal argument that we are presently considering rejects Same Cause, Same Effect by claiming that since certain effects have background conditions on their instantiation (e.g. the existence of the right kind of external object of sense or the right kind past event), sameness of proximate cause is insufficient for sameness of effect. The revised version of the principle, however, cannot be rejected on those grounds, since it allows that there can be events with substantive background conditions on their instantiation. Moreover, the revised version of the principle is rather plausible. If an event of kind A produces an event of kind B, it seems to follow that events of kind A have the power to produce type-B events as their immediate effects. Granted, this might be a conditional power, which can be exercised only when the relevant background conditions on a type-B event occurring are satisfied. However, in cases where those conditions are in fact satisfied, it is hard to see how the type-A event should fail to exercise its power to produce a type-B event. It appears, therefore, that there is good reason to accept the weaker principle (cf. Martin 2004; Nudds 2013).

The weaker principle, however, still causes trouble for disjunctivists, both about perception and about memory. Consider first the case of perception. A disjunctivist about perception will insist that a genuinely perceptual experience can only occur if there exists a suitable external object of sense that is available to be perceived, i.e., she takes this to be a background condition that must be met if a perceptual experience is to occur. Consider, however, a perception p and an hallucination h, whereby h is a veridical hallucination (e.g. h might be an hallucination as of a red apple in the presence of an actual red apple). By Proximate Causes, we can suppose that p and h have the same proximate cause. And by Same Cause, Same Effect*, we know that like proximate causes produce like immediate effects whenever the relevant background conditions are met. Moreover, we know that in the case of veridical hallucination, the relevant background condition is met, i.e. there is a suitable external object and it is available to be perceived. Thus, it seems to follow that the neural event that causes h will also produce an experience of the perceptual kind. However, the disjunctivist has to deny this, since in hallucination, whether veridical or otherwise, we don’t perceive external things, and hence we do not have experiences of the kind that according to the disjunctivist are involved in cases of genuine perception.

The same problem arises for the memory disjunctivist once we consider cases of veridical confabulation. The memory disjunctivist can rightly insist that on her view, a genuine episodic memory can occur only if there exists in the subject’s past a suitable event she once experienced. However, we can imagine a pair of experiences m and c, such that m is a genuine memory and c is a veridical confabulation. By Proximate Causes, we can suppose that m and c have the same proximate cause. By Same Cause, Same Effect*, we know that like proximate causes produce like immediate effects whenever the relevant background conditions are met. Moreover, we know that in the case of veridical confabulation, the background condition that the memory disjunctivist believes is operative is met, i.e. there does exist a suitable event located in the subject’s personal past that is available to be remembered. Accordingly, it seems to follow that the neural event that causes c will also produce an experience of the same kind as m. However, the memory disjunctivist must deny this. After all, in cases of mere confabulation, whether veridical or otherwise, the subject is not actually remembering some past event. Therefore, she cannot be having the kind of experience that the memory disjunctivist takes to be involved in genuinely remembering, namely an experience that constitutively involves acquaintance with a past event.

One way to capture all of this is to say that the revised causal argument in effect relies on three main premises, namely Proximate Causes, Same Cause, Same Effect*, and then the following further claim, namely:

Event Condition

The only background condition that must be met for an experience of the kind involved in genuine memory is for a suitable past event to exist.

Given Proximate Causes, Same Cause, Same Effect*, and Event Condition, it follows that in cases of veridical confabulation, the subject will undergo an experience of the kind involved in genuine memory. Disjunctivism, however, implies that one never undergoes the kind of experience involved in genuine memory during a case of total confabulation, whether veridical or otherwise. Accordingly, we can conclude that Proximate Causes, Same Cause, Same Effect*, and Event Condition jointly imply that disjunctivism is false.

The upshot, I submit, is that in order to properly resist the causal argument from confabulation, the memory disjunctivist must do more than just reject Same Cause, Same Effect. In addition, it seems that she must reject Event Condition. More exactly, what she must do is to locate a further background condition on undergoing the sort of experience involved in genuine memory, such that this condition cannot be met in cases of (either veridical or non-veridical) confabulation. Only then will she able to rule out the concern that the sort of experience involved in genuine memory might occur even during total confabulation.Footnote 11

Later in the paper, I develop a causalist version of memory disjunctivism that has precisely this consequence (sections 4 and 5). Before getting to that, however, I want to set out the second, related, argument that memory disjunctivists face. Again, this is a direct analogue of the ‘screening off argument’ that arises for those who hold a disjunctivist view about perception.

3 The Screening off Argument

The screening off argument against memory disjunctivism proceeds in two main steps.Footnote 12 The first stage aims to establish that even in cases of genuine memory, the subject undergoes the sort of experience involved in pure confabulation. This claim is strictly speaking compatible with memory disjunctivism, since there is logical space for claiming that in cases of genuine memory one undergoes two different kinds of memory-experience, namely, a genuine memory consisting in acquaintance with a past event, and a merely confabulatory experience which does not consist in acquaintance with past event and which instead has some other nature. The second step, however, argues that this position is unstable, and, therefore, that if indeed one undergoes the kind of experience involved in pure confabulation even in cases of genuine memory, then memory disjunctivism is false. Accordingly, the argument can be represented as follows:

  1. 1.

    Even in cases of genuine memory, one undergoes the kind of experience involved in total confabulation.

  2. 2.

    If one undergoes the kind of experience involved in mere confabulation even in cases of genuine memory, then memory disjunctivism is false.

∴ Memory disjunctivism is false.

The argument for premise 1 turns once again on Proximate Causes and on the weakened causal principle, Same Cause, Same Effect*. It also draws on one further premise, to the effect that nothing more is required, in order to produce an experience of the kind involved in mere confabulation, beyond the right kind of proximate neural cause. We might refer to this as further premise as:

No Conditions

To produce an experience of the kind involved in total confabulation, nothing more is required than the right kind of proximate cause.

As we saw in the previous section, memory disjunctivists can plausibly insist that in order to produce the kind of experience involved in genuine memory, more is required than merely producing the right kind of proximate cause: in addition, a suitable event must exist in the personal past of the remembering subject. Whatever mere confabulations are, however, i.e. whatever nature these apparent memories turn out to have, there would appear to be no such substantive background conditions on their instantiation. In this way, total confabulations resemble total hallucinations. As Mike Martin (2004: 58) explains, we intuitively think of hallucinatory experiences as being ‘inner events’, and, therefore, as being such that no further condition, beyond the subject being in the right kind of antecedent brain state, must be met in order for such events to be produced (cf. Snowdon 2005: 288). I suggest that in much the same way, confabulatory experiences are naturally thought of as ‘inner events’. Whatever nature such events turn out to have, it is plausible to think that nothing more is required for their instantiation than an instance of the right kind of local neural cause.Footnote 13

Consider now the following argument. By Same Cause, Same Effect*, we know that like proximate causes produce like immediate effects whenever all the background conditions associated with the relevant effect are met. Moreover, given No Conditions, we know that no background conditions need be met for an experience of the merely confabulatory kind to occur (or, equivalently, that all of the conditions on the occurrence of this kind of event are met in every possible situation.) Hence, we can infer if some brain state b produces an experience of the merely confabulatory kind, then any brain state of the same kind as b will produce an experience of that sort. By Proximate Causes, however, we know that for every genuine memory m, there is a merely confabulatory experience c with the same proximate cause. Accordingly, we can infer that in every case of genuine memory, the proximate brain state also produces an experience of the merely confabulatory kind. This establishes that premise 1 is true.

Note again that premise 1 is logically consistent with memory disjunctivism. That is, the memory disjunctivist can coherently maintain that in cases of genuine memory, one undergoes both an experience of the kind involved in confabulation, and the kind that she believes to be involved exclusively in genuine memory (i.e. the kind consisting in acquaintance with past events).Footnote 14 What, then, is the argument for premise 2? Why think that if the kind of experience involved in total confabulation is present also in the case of genuine memory, then the position of the memory disjunctivist is thereby undermined?

The argument turns on the thought that once premise 1 is accepted, the memory disjunctivist faces an insurmountable problem involving explanatory exclusion or ‘screening off’. Consider a pair of cases: C is one of genuine memory, and C* is one of total confabulation. Say that the subject in C is undergoing an experience of kind Km (i.e. the kind involved exclusively in genuine memory, and which consists in acquaintance with a past event), and that the subject in C* is undergoing an experience of kind Kc (i.e. the merely confabulatory kind). And focus now on the subject in C*. The fact that S in C* is undergoing this experience is capable of explaining various things. For instance, it can explain the various beliefs that she will form in C* (e.g. that such and such an event happened in her personal past). It will also explain why she ends up with a whole range of related psychological attitudes and associated behaviours (perhaps the past event she seems to remember makes her feel regret, or induces a desire to make certain changes, etc.). Moreover, the fact that the confabulating subject is undergoing an experience of kind Kc will also explain why it phenomenally seems to her as if a certain event happened in her past. But now consider C, the case of genuine memory. We are supposing that the subject in C also has an experience of kind Kc (which follows given premise 1). Accordingly, we can appeal to this fact to explain all of the same things we could explain about C*. That is, we can appeal to the fact that the remembering subject is having an experience of the merely confabulatory kind to explain why she ends up with a whole range of psychological attitudes and why she exhibits a whole range of behaviours, as well as explaining why the situation she is in has the phenomenology it does (i.e. why things seem phenomenally to her as they do). The trouble, however, is that this seems to leave no explanatory work for the supposed fact that the remembering subject is having an experience of kind Km to do—where, again, ‘Km’ names the kind of memory-experience which, according to the memory disjunctivist, is said to be relational in nature, and to occur exclusively in cases of genuine memory. In short, it is coherent for the memory disjunctivist to grant that even in the case of genuine memory, the subject has an experience of the confabulatory kind. However, it also seems that this is not ultimately a stable position. For, once it is admitted that the confabulatory kind of experience is involved even in the case of genuine memory, it is hard to see what explanatory work the idea that a further kind of experience that is relational in nature and unique to the genuinely memorial case could do. That is, the confabulatory kind of experience would seem to ‘screen off’ the relational kind of experience (consisting in acquaintance with a past event) from playing any substantive explanatory role. This then appears to tell strongly against the disjunctivist position.Footnote 15

The memory disjunctivist must reject either premise 1 or premise 2 of the screening off argument. One option, therefore, is to push back against the second premise. In the analogous case of perception, in fact, this is the move that is standardly made (cf. Moran 2019a). In particular, disjunctivists about perception tend to put forward ‘deflationary’ or ‘minimalist’ accounts of the nature of the hallucinatory case specifically designed to allow them to accept that even in cases of genuine perception, the subject undergoes the kind of experience involved in hallucination, yet without this entailing that the hallucinatory kind of experience ‘screens off’ the distinctively perceptual kind of experience (which for the perception disjunctivist consists in acquaintance with external objects of perception) from playing a distinctive explanatory role.Footnote 16 Such accounts, however, have come under a great deal of criticism, and in my view rightly so. One problem is that the kinds of ‘deflationary’ theory of hallucination that this strategy requires are unattractive in and of themselves (see e.g., Conduct 2010; Burge 2005; Farkas 2006; Hawthorne & Kovakovich 2006; Moran 2019a; Pautz 2011; Searle 2015; Siegel 2004, 2008; Smith 2008). Another is that even given these ‘deflationary’ theories of hallucination, it is unclear that the worry about explanatory exclusion really goes away Moran (manuscript-b). There is reason, moreover, to think that these problems would carry over straightforwardly to the case of memory. In principle, then, in a bid to reject premise 2, the memory disjunctivist could offer a ‘deflationary’ or ‘minimalist’ account of the nature of confabulatory experiences, analogous to the accounts of hallucination that some disjunctivists about perception have offered.Footnote 17 However, there will then be the concern that any such account of confabulation is unattractive or problematic in and of itself. Moreover, the worry will arise that even given the relevant theory of confabulatory experience, the screening off problem will still remain.

Accordingly, this paper recommends an alternative strategy. In particular, I recommend rejecting premise 1. As we have seen, premise 1 follows from three main claims: Proximate Causes, Same Cause, Same Effect*, and No Conditions. Moreover, I have already indicated that memory disjunctivists should accept the first two claims. What I’ll be suggesting, however, is that disjunctivists should reject No Conditions. On the view to be developed, there are substantive causal conditions, going beyond the occurrence of the right kind of proximate cause, that must be met if an experience of the confabulatory kind is to occur. The idea, moreover, is that these conditions cannot be met in cases of genuine memory. Given this view, the argument for premise 1 can then be blocked. Indeed, as we will see, the view implies the falsity of premise 1, since it entails that the confabulatory kind of experience simply cannot occur in cases of genuine memory.

4 Towards a Causalist Disjunctivism

As we have seen, relationalists about memory must be disjunctivists, i.e. they must deny that genuine memory and mere confabulation involve mental events of the same kind. In the memory literature, however, it is much more common for philosophers to endorse a ‘common factor’ theory of memory, on which the same kind of mental event is involved in both genuine memory and mere confabulation. Examples of such views include the mental image theory, according to which memory-experiences consist in acquaintance with mental images, as well as the representationalist theory, on which memory-experiences are to be understood as being a certain kind of representational state.Footnote 18 On views of this kind, regardless of whether one is remembering or confabulating, the experience involved has the same intrinsic nature. That is, cases of genuine memory and cases of mere confabulation involve mental events of precisely the same kind.

Unlike disjunctivists, proponents of a common factor theory face the following explanatory challenge. Some memory-experiences are genuine memories. Others are mere confabulations.Footnote 19 Yet, on a common factor theory, we cannot explain why this is so in terms of the mental natures of the relevant events. Common factor theorists, therefore, must locate a non-mental difference between memory-experiences that can serve to explain why some are genuine memories (which make subjects aware of past events they once experienced) whereas others are mere confabulations (which do not make subjects aware of past events).

One traditional, and still quite standard, way for common factor theorists to meet this challenge is to appeal to the causal theory of memory.Footnote 20 According to that theory, whether a memory-experience is a genuine memory or else a case of mere confabulation is determined, at least in part, by the manner in which it is caused. In particular, we must distinguish between ‘standard’ causation, which is the sort involved in genuine memory, and ‘deviant’ or ‘non-standard’ causation, which is the sort involved in confabulation. The idea is that when a memory-experience is the product of a standard causal chain, it is a genuine memory, whereas when a memory-experience is the product of a deviant or non-standard causal chain, it is merely confabulatory experience instead.Footnote 21

Begin with the case of genuine memory. In such a case, the subject is aware of a past event she once experienced. What the causal theorist claims is that a part of what it takes for this to be the case is for there to be an appropriate causal connection between the subject’s original experience of the remembered event and the experience that constitutes her episodic memory of that event. In such cases, we have ‘standard causation’, and hence the memory-experience has the property of being a genuine memory. So, when one has a genuine episodic memory, an event of the very same kind might be involved in some merely confabulatory case. However, the confabulatory experience will not stand in the same sort of causal connection to past experience that one once enjoyed, and will for that reason lack the property of being a genuine memory.Footnote 22

Consider now the case of total confabulation. In such a case, the subject is not aware of a past event she once experienced; she merely seems to be. What the causal theorist claims, moreover, is that part of what it takes for this to be the case is for the subject’s experience to have been deviantly or non-standardly caused. The idea, in other words, is that while genuine memories are memory-experiences that are caused in a distinctive way by past experiences of suitable past events, confabulations are memory-experiences that have instead been produced in a deviant or non-standard way, and hence in a manner that does not connect the subject to a past experience in the kind of way that, for the causal theorist, is involved in cases of genuine memory.

One important source of motivation for the traditional causalist picture involves contrasting genuine memory with veridical confabulation.Footnote 23 Let ‘E ‘be an event that subject S once experienced in her personal past. In situation C, we can suppose, S has a genuine memory of E. In situation C*, by contrast, she has a veridical confabulatory experience that is indistinguishable from her experience in C. (We are supposing here that E exists in S’s personal past in both C and C*.) The question is: what makes it the case that only one of her experiences is a genuine memory, whereas the other is a mere veridical confabulation? In both cases, the relevant event exists, and is a part of S’s personal past. So why does S only remember E in C, and not in C? That is, why is her memory-experience only a genuine memory of event E in C and not in C*?

The causalist has a compelling answer. On her view, the difference is to be explained in causal terms. In both C and C*, the subject S has an experience of the same kind. Moreover, the relevant event, E, is a part of S’s personal past in both situations. Nonetheless, the causalist asserts, there is room to identify a crucial difference. In C, S’s memory-experience is appropriately causally connected to some past experience of E. In C*, by contrast, this isn’t so, and therefore S’s memory-experience will have been deviantly caused. The idea, moreover, is that this difference is what serves to explain why S genuinely remembers E in C but is merely confabulating in C*. The proposed explanation, that is, is that her memory-experience in C is a genuine memory of E whereas her memory-experience in C* is merely confabulatory, despite the fact that E is still apart of S’s personal past in C*, because in C, and not in C*, S’s memory-experience appropriately caused by S’s past experience of E.

In short, the causalist can offer a compelling picture as to how veridical confabulations are possible. In a veridical confabulation, the subject’s personal past really is as her memory-experience portrays it as being. Nevertheless, she is confabulating, not remembering. The causalist is able to account for this by noting that genuine memories must be appropriately caused by past experiences of remembered events, and that confabulatory experiences arise when memory-experiences are not caused in this way, but are instead non-standardly produced. On this approach, the explanation as to why veridical confabulations are possible is that there can be memory-experiences that portray the subject’s past in an accurate way but which are also non-standardly and so deviantly caused.

There is also a more general way to motivate the causal theory. In cases of genuine memory, one is aware of some past event that one once experienced. A natural thought, moreover, is that in order for this to be so, one has to be appropriately connected to the original experience one had of that event. In other words, it just seems very plausible to think that this kind of causal connection must be in place to underwrite the fact that one is genuinely remembering some event from one’s personal past. In the same way, it seems very natural to think that cases of confabulation arise precisely when this sort of causal connection is absent. When one is suitably causally hooked-up to some past sense-experience of some event, one is thereby able to remember that past event. When one is not suitably causally hooked-up in this manner, however, what results is a confabulatory experience, which is at best indistinguishable from a genuine memory, but which is not itself a case of remembering some event from one’s past.

I submit, then, that the causal theory captures something important about the distinction between genuine memory and mere confabulation. In particular, it seems to correctly identify that genuine memories must be appropriately caused by prior experiences of past events, whereas confabulations are the product of deviant causal chains that don’t connect the subject to a past experience of an event in her personal past in the right kind of way. However, memory disjunctivists cannot accept the causal theory as it stands, given its commitment to the common factor (and therefore non-disjunctive) conception. The question, then, is whether there is a version of the causal theory that can be held in a disjunctivist setting.

In my view, there is. That is, I think that there is a nearby position to the original causal theory that even disjunctivists can accept. This can be articulated as follows. In cases of genuine memory, one undergoes an experience of a distinctive kind. Such experiences, moreover, must be caused in a specific way. In particular, the sort of experience involved in genuine memory must be produced by a causal chain connecting the subject to a prior experience of an event that is in her personal past. More precisely, the idea is that it lies in the nature of experiences of this kind to be caused in just that way, which then entails that they are necessarily produced in just that way. In other words, the claim is that the kind of experience involved in genuine memory must be produced in the standard way by a suitable past experience of the remembered event because it is an essential feature of events of that kind to be produced in that manner. Similarly, in cases of confabulation, one also undergoes an experience of a distinctive kind. And these experiences, too, must be caused in a specific way. In particular, confabulatory experiences must be generated by a deviant or non-standard causal chain that does not connect the subject in the right way to a past experience of a past event. The idea, moreover, is that it lies in the nature of experiences of this kind to be caused in just that way. That is, such experiences must be non-standardly or deviantly caused because it is an essential feature of events of that kind to be produced in just that manner.

This view, I submit, represents a natural way of accepting something like the traditional causal theory within a disjunctivist setting. There is, however, a crucial difference between the standard causal theory and the above disjunctivist alternative. On the disjunctivist version of the theory, genuine memories are caused in a certain way precisely by virtue of being the kinds of experiences they are, and the same is true for experiences of the confabulatory kind. That is, it lies in the nature, or essence, of genuinely memorial experiences to be caused in one sort of way, and in the nature, or essence, of confabulatory experiences to be caused in another. The traditional causal theory, however, merely specifies the conditions under which instances of one common kind of memory-experience will have one or another extrinsic property, namely that of being a genuine memory/being a mere confabulation. The disjunctivist version of the causal theory, therefore, goes beyond the traditional version, by making claims about the respective essences of two experiential kinds, namely the kind involved in genuine memory, and the kind involved in mere confabulation.Footnote 24

Despite this important difference, however, I think a case can be made for thinking that disjunctivists should be attracted to the above kind of causalist view. One way to see this, moreover, is to again consider cases of veridical confabulation, this time within a disjunctivist setting. In situation C, S has a genuine memory of E. In situation C*, by contrast, S has a veridical confabulatory experience. (The idea, again, is that in both situations, E is an event from S’s personal past she once experienced.) Now, the disjunctivist will want to say that two distinct kinds of experience are involved across these cases: in C, the subject has a genuinely memorial experience, consisting in acquaintance with E, whereas in C*, the subject has an experience that does not consist in acquaintance with any past event. The question, however, is what explains this. In both C and C*, the relevant past event, namely E, exists. So why does S have one kind of experience in C, and a quite different kind of experience in C*? Surely there must be something to explain this fact. So what resources can disjunctivist appeal to?

Given the causal theory sketched above, the disjunctivist can meet this challenge. On the causal theory, it lies in the nature of genuinely memorial experiences to be caused in the standard way by a prior experience of a past event. It also lies in the nature of merely confabulatory experiences to be caused in a deviant or non-standard way. Accordingly, given this theory, the disjunctivist can explain why S has a genuinely memorial experience in C and yet a merely confabulatory experience in C*. In particular, she can insist that while E exists both in C and C*, it is only in C that S’s memory-experience is caused in a suitable way by a prior experience of that event. Because of this, S has a genuine memory of E in C, and therefore an experience consisting in acquaintance with that remembered event. In C*, however, S’s experience is caused in a deviant way. Accordingly, S does not have the kind of experience involved in genuine memory. That is, she does not have an experience consisting in acquaintance with a past event. Rather, she has the distinct kind of experience involved in cases of mere confabulation, whatever nature these events turn out to have.

Additionally, the more general way of motivating the causal theory we considered above seems to carry over to a disjunctivist setting. What we noted earlier is that it’s very plausible to think that part of what it takes to genuinely remember a past event is for there to be a suitable causal connection to one’s past experience of it, and that likewise, it seems very natural to hold that part of what is going on in mere confabulation is that one is having a memory-experience in the absence of any such causal connection to a previous experience of a past event. If that is right, however, then the disjunctivist needs somehow to incorporate this insight into her preferred view of episodic memory. My suggestion is that she can do this by claiming that in her view, the kind of experience involved in genuine memory is essentially and therefore necessarily caused in the standard way by a prior experience of some past event, whereas the kind of experience involved in mere confabulation is essentially and therefore necessarily caused in a deviant or non-standard way.

I conclude that there is good independent reason for the disjunctivist to endorse the kind of modified causal theory that I have sketched. What I want now to do, in the next section, is to explain how this theory can be put to work in responding to the arguments against disjunctivism that we considered above.Footnote 25

5 The Causalist Response

We can think of the disjunctivist version of the causal theory just articulated as the conjunction of the following two claims:

  1. (D1)

    It lies in the nature of genuine memory experiences to be standardly caused. That is, events of the sort involved in genuine memory are essentially produced in just that way.

  2. (D2)

    It lies in the nature of confabulatory experiences to be non-standardly caused. That is, events of the sort involved in confabulation are essentially produced in just that way.Footnote 26

Importantly, if both these claims are true, it follows the kind of memory-experience that a given brain state will be able to produce depends on the broader causal context in which it is embedded. In turn, this means that the causal chain that generates an experience effectively plays two different kinds of role. On the one hand, it plays a straightforwardly causal role in bringing the relevant memory-experience about. On the other hand, however, it also plays the role of background condition in determining what kind of experience the proximate brain state (occurring at the end of the long causal chain) is able to produce. In other words, not only does the causal chain generate the relevant experience in the straightforward causal way. In addition, the character of the causal chain plays the further role of a background condition determining what kind of experience the embedded brain state may generate. When the causal chain involved is standard, and thus connects the subject to a past experience of some suitable past event, this enables the brain state to produce an experience of the genuinely memorial kind, and disables it from producing an experience of the confabulatory kind. But when the causal chain involved is non-standard or deviant, and hence does not connect the subject in the right kind of way to a prior experience of some event in her personal past, this then enables the brain state to produce an experience of the confabulatory kind, and disables it from producing an experience of the kind involved in genuine memory. The kind of experience we end up with is therefore a function of the nature of the causal chain involved. Whether we end up with one kind of experience or the other depends upon whether the broader causal chain is standard or deviant.Footnote 27

My main contention at this point is that in light of the above, it follows that if the disjunctivist accepts the form of causal theory captured by (D1) and (D2), then she ends up with the resources to answer the challenges posed both the casual argument and the screening off argument. Moreover, it emerges that she can do so in a unified way. To see this, let us reconsider these arguments in turn.Footnote 28

Again, the causal argument depends on two main premises: Proximate Causes, and Same Cause, Same Effect. By Proximate Causes, we can imagine that some genuine memory m has the same proximate cause as some mere confabulation c. By Same Cause, Same Effect, therefore, it follows that the proximate cause of c also produces an experience of the same kind as m. However, the disjunctivist has to deny this, since on her view, the experience of the sort involved in genuine memory could not occur in a merely confabulatory case.

The thing to note is that given (D1) and (D2), we can now explain why Same Cause, Same Effect is false. According to that principle, proximate causes of the same kind always produce the same sort of immediate effect. In turn, at least given Proximate Causes, this then implies that the neural cause of a merely confabulatory experience must also produce an experience of the sort involved in genuine memory. However, the disjunctivist who accepts the casual theory that is captured by (D1) and (D2) can push back against this reasoning. By (D2), the proximate cause of any confabulatory experience must itself be produced in the deviant way. By (D1), however, the sort of experience involved in genuine memory must be produced in the standard and hence in a non-deviant way. Consequently, the brain state that produces the confabulatory experience could not produce an experience of the genuinely memorial kind. Therefore, Same Cause Same Effect is false, and the casual argument from confabulation fails.

What of the revised version of the causal argument, which depends on Proximate Causes and the weaker principle of Same Cause, Same Effect*? Again, this argument turns on a case involving veridical hallucination. By Proximate Causes, we can imagine we can imagine that some genuine memory m has the same proximate cause as some veridical confabulation c. The worry, therefore, is that even if the disjunctivist insists (rightly) that a proximate brain state can only produce an experience of the sort involved in genuine memory when a suitable past event exists, Same Cause, Same Effect* will still imply that in the case of veridical hallucination, the subject has an experience of the genuinely memorial kind, since in that case, there does exist a suitable past event for the subject to remember. Given (D1) and (D2), however, we can resist this line of reasoning. For, (D1) implies that a proximate brain state can only produce a genuinely memorial experience if it is embedded within a standard casual chain. By (D2), however, we know that the brain state that produces the veridical confabulation c is not embedded in a standard causal context, but rather is a part of a deviant causal chain. Thus, a crucial background condition on the occurrence of a genuinely memorial experience, namely, that the causal context involve standard causation, is not met, and so Same Cause, Same Effect* no longer implies that the proximate brain state in the veridical confabulatory case will produce an experience of the genuinely memorial kind. In other words, the claim here is that Event Condition is false. That claim tells us that the only background condition on genuine memory is the existence of a suitable past event. On the causalist theory proposed here, however, this is not so, since in addition to a suitable past event, the right kind of causation must also be in play. This then implies that even given Proximate Causes and Same Cause, Same Effect*, we cannot infer that in cases of veridical confabulation one undergoes an experience of the sort involved in genuine memory.

Turn now to the screening off argument. Again, this goes as follows:

  1. 1.

    Even in cases of genuine memory, one undergoes the kind of experience in-volved in total confabulation.

  2. 2.

    If one undergoes the kind of experience involved in mere confabulation even in cases of genuine memory, then memory disjunctivism is false.

∴ Memory disjunctivism is false.

In section 3, I indicated that disjunctivists should reject premise 2. At this juncture, moreover, we are in a position to explain how. The argument for premise 2 turns on three main principles: Proximate Causes, Same Cause Same Effect*, and No Conditions. By Proximate Causes, we can imagine a genuine memory m and a mere confabulation c with the same proximate cause. By Same Cause Same Effect*, we know that the brain state that produces m will also produce an experience of the same kind as c so long as all of the relevant background conditions on the occurrence of an event of that kind are met. But No Conditions tells us that no further conditions beyond the occurrence of the right kind of brain state need be met in order for an experience of that kind to be produced. It therefore follows that even in the case of genuine memory, an experience of the kind involved in confabulating is going to be produced. But that establishes that premise 2 is true.

The crucial point is that given (D1) and (D2), we can push back against this argument. After all, (D2) implies that for a confabulatory experience to occur, the relevant brain state must be embedded in a deviant casual chain. Accordingly, it follows that contra No Conditions, the mere occurrence of the right kind of brain state is not enough to produce a confabulatory experience. Rather, the antecedent brain state has to be embedded within a deviant causal chain. By (D1), however, any brain state that produces a genuine memory will be embedded in a standard rather than a deviant causal chain. Accordingly, it emerges that a crucial background condition on the occurrence of a merely confabulatory experience can never be met in genuinely memorial cases. In turn, this means we can infer that premise 2 is false. Indeed, we can infer that it is never possible for a confabulatory experience to occur in a case of genuine memory.Footnote 29

Given the disjunctivist version of the causal theory sketched above, therefore, we can put forward a unified response to the causal argument and the screening off argument. Essentially, these arguments be understood as posing a pair of related challenges to the memory disjunctivist. Again, it seems possible for there to be two subjects such that one of them is genuinely remembering while the other is merely confabulating, whereby their respective experiences share the same proximate cause. The causal argument puts pressure on the disjunctivist by threatening to show that the proximate cause of the subject’s confabulatory experience also causes an experience of the sort involved in genuine memory. Meanwhile, the screening off argument puts pressure on the disjunctivist by threatening to show that the proximate cause of the subject’s genuine memory also causes an experience of the sort involved in confabulation. To deal with these two arguments, therefore, the disjunctivist must explain both (i) why the proximate cause of a merely confabulatory experience does not also produce an experience of the kind involved in genuine memory, and (ii) why the proximate cause of a genuine memory does not also produce an experience of the kind involved in mere confabulation. What I have argued is that by accepting (D1) and (D2), this explanatory challenge can be met. In particular, In particular, I have argued that the disjunctivist can meet this challenge by drawing on (D1) and (D2) by way of insisting that the causal context in which a given proximate brain state is embedded is crucial to determining the kind of memory-experience that it is able to cause.Footnote 30

6 Conclusion

In this paper, I have considered two related challenges to memory disjunctivism: the causal argument from confabulation, and the screening off argument. My central argument has been that by accepting a revised form of the traditional common factor causal theory, disjunctivists have the resources to respond to these arguments in a unified way. On the proposed view, genuine memories, by their very natures, have to be caused in the standard way, whereas mere confabulations, by their very nature, must be produced in a non-standard or deviant manner. As we have seen, given this kind of view, disjunctivists have the resources to undermine both the causal argument and the screening off argument. I submit, therefore, that disjunctivists about episodic memory should supplement their view by embracing precisely the causalist theory developed here.