Skip to main content
Log in

A Psychological Approach to Causal Understanding and the Temporal Asymmetry

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article provides a conceptual account of causal understanding by connecting current psychological research on time and causality with philosophical debates on the causal asymmetry. I argue that causal relations are viewed as asymmetric because they are understood in temporal terms. I investigate evidence from causal learning and reasoning in both children and adults: causal perception, the temporal priority principle, and the use of temporal cues for causal inference. While this account does not suffice for correct inferences of causal structure, I show it to serve as a preliminary understanding of causal concepts as asymmetric, that later incorporates other types of evidence (leading up to difference-making, or causal processes). This approach supplies causal models with an asymmetric concept of causation that underlies hypotheses about causal structure, as I will illustrate from the framework of the knowledge-based causal induction model. I further argue for an integrating perspective, showing how the understanding of causes as preceding their effects underlies both psychological models and philosophical debates over time and the causal asymmetry, particularly regarding problem cases such as simultaneous causation or backwards causation, and the conceptual connection between causation and action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In relation to Woodward’s account, my view can be seen in opposition to Gijsbers and de Bruin (2014) who argue for an agency concept of causation to address the issue of circularity: while Gijsbers and de Bruin recognize the importance of temporal information but do not deem this kind of understanding causal, I argue that prior to incorporation in models of causal inference causal concepts are primarily understood in temporal terms. Two caveats here are that my view targets causal models more broadly, not solely interventionism, and that I do not make a definite developmental claim.

  2. In particular, Loew makes the case for the use of local asymmetric models in causal explanation in contrast to the laws of physics.

  3. This question, thus, avoids the clash between realist and projectivist views, by narrowing down the scope to how the causal reasoners understand the asymmetry. Whether this corresponds to a feature of causality in the world (say, the metaphysics of time and causation) is a separate issue.

  4. As mentioned above, for this reason, my view here can be roughly labeled as Humean. This applies to the temporal account for the causal asymmetry, but not to patterns of association, as I am relying on causal models instead.

  5. See Schaffer, section 2.2.

  6. Though a further question would arise regarding the extent to which these various possibilities would account for the direction of causality – counterfactuals, for instance, could go both ways as shown in the cases of causal and diagnostic reasoning. Nevertheless it is also possible that if the causal asymmetry is epistemically irreducible, such intuitive understanding would be the source of hypotheses.

  7. Another example falling under psychological research is mental time travel – while people can mentally switch between past and future scenarios, this capacity obviously is in no way dependent on the possibility of time travel.

References

  • Ahn, W., C.W. Kalish, D.L. Medin, and S.A. Gelman. 1995. The role of covariation versus mechanism information in causal attribution. Cognition 54: 299–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechlivanidis, C., and D. Lagnado. 2013. Does the “why” tell us the “when”? Psychological Science 24 (8): 1563–1572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechlivanidis, C., and D. Lagnado. 2016. Time reorder: Causal perception guides the interpretation of temporal order. Cognition 146: 58–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bramley N., Gerstenberg, T., Lagnado, D. (2014) ‘The order of things: Inferring causal structure from temporal patterns’, Proceedings of the 36th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society.

  • Bullock, M., and R. Gelman. 1979. Preschool children’s assumptions about cause and effect: Temporal ordering. Child Development 50: 89–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bullock, M., R. Gelman, and R. Baillargeon. 1982. The development of causal reasoning. The developmental psychology of time: 209–254.

  • Cohen, L.B., and L.M. Oakes. 1993. How infants perceive a simple causal event. Developmental Psychology 29 (3): 421.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood, R.G. (2002) Essay on metaphysics, Oxford University Press.

  • Danks, D. (2009) ‘The psychology of causal perception and reasoning’, in Helen Beebee, Peter Menzies & Christopher Hitchcock (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation, Oxford University Press, 447–470.

  • Fenker, D., M.R. Waldmann, and K.J. Holyoak. 2005. Accessing causal relations in semantic memory. Memory and Cognition 33: 1036–1046.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frosch, C., T. McCormack, D. Lagnado, and P. Burns. 2012. Are causal structure and intervention judgments inextricably linked? A developmental study. Cognitive Science 36: 261–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gijsbers, V., and L. de Bruin. 2014. How agency can solve interventionism’s problem of circularity. Synthese 191 (8): 1775–1791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2009. ‘Causal Pluralism’ in Helen Beebee, Peter Menzies & Christopher Hitchcock (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Causation, Oxford University Press. 326—337.

  • Gopnik, A., D. Sobel, L. Schulz, and C. Glymour. 2001. Causal learning mechanisms in very young children: Two-, three- and four-year-olds infer causal relations from patterns of variation and covariation. Developmental Psychology 37: 620–629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., C. Glymour, D.M. Sobel, L.E. Schulz, T. Kushnir, and D. Danks. 2004. A theory of causal learning in children: Causal maps and Bayes nets. Psychological Review 111: 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004) ‘Two concepts of causation’, in Collins et al., Causation and Counterfactuals, the MIT Press, 225-276.

  • Harris, P.L., T. German, and P. Mills. 1996. Children’s use of counterfactual thinking in causal reasoning. Cognition 61 (3): 233–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hong, L., Z. Chijun, G. Xuemei, G. Shan, and L. Chongde. 2005. The influence of complexity and reasoning direction on children’s causal reasoning. Cognitive Development 20 (1): 87–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748) Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, in Enquiries concerning Human Understanding and concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge, 3rd edition revised by P. H. Nidditch, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975.

  • Kant, I. (1781) Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp Smith. New York: Macmillan Press, 1965.

  • Lagnado, D., and Sloman. 2004. The advantage of timely intervention. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 30 (4): 856–876.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagnado, D.A., and S.A. Sloman. 2006. Time as a guide to cause. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 32 (3): 451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagnado, D., Waldmann, M., Hagmayer, Y., Sloman, S. (2007) ‘Beyond covariation: Cues to causal structure’, in Gopnik, A., & Schultz, L. (Eds.), Causal learning: Psychology, philosophy, and computation, Oxford University Press, pp. 154-173.

  • Leslie, A.M. 1982. The perception of causality in infants. Perception 11 (2): 173–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A.M., and S. Keeble. 1987. Do six-month-old infants perceive causality? Cognition 25 (3): 265–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loew, C. 2017. Causation, physics, and fit. Synthese 194 (6): 1945–1965.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J.L. 1965. Causes and conditions. American Philosophical Quarterly 2 (1965): 245–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormack, T., and C. Hoerl. 2017. The development of temporal concepts: Learning to locate events in time. Timing & Time Perception 5 (3–4): 297–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCormack, T., Frosch, K., Patrick, F., Lagnado, D. (2014) ‘Temporal and statistical information in causal structure learning’, Journal of Experimental Psychology, Learning-Memory and Cognition.

  • Michotte, A. 1963. The perception of causality. New York: Basic Books.

  • Oakes, L.M., and L.B. Cohen. 1990. Infant perception of a causal event. Cognitive Development 5 (2): 193–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (2007) ‘Causal Perspectivalism’, in H. Price & R. Corry (eds.), Causation, Physics, and the Constitution of Reality: Russell’s Republic Revisited, Oxford University Press, pp. 250-292.

  • Rankin, M.L., and T. McCormack. 2013. The temporal priority principle: At what age does this develop? Frontiers in Psychology 4.

  • Saxe, R., and S. Carey. 2006. The perception of causality in infancy. Acta Psychologica 123 (1–2): 144–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2016) ‘The metaphysics of causation’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, E.N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/causation-metaphysics/>.

  • Schlottmann, A. 1999. Seeing it happen and knowing how it works: How children understand the relation between perceptual causality and underlying mechanism. Developmental Psychology 35 (5): 303–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlottmann, A. 2000. Is perception of causality modular? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4 (12): 441–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlottmann, A., K. Cole, R. Watts, and M. White. 2013. Domain-specific perceptual causality in children depends on the spatio-temporal configuration, not motion onset. Frontiers in Psychology 4: 365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulz, L., A. Gopnik, and C. Glymour. 2007. Preschool children learn about causal structure from conditional interventions. Developmental Science 10: 322–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, D.L., and T. Black. 1999. Inferences through imagined actions: Knowing by simulated doing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning Memory Cognition 25: 116–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shultz, T. R. (1982) ‘Rules for causal attribution’, Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 47 (1, Serial No. 194).

  • Sloman, S., and D. Lagando. 2015. Causality in thought. Annual Review of Psychology 66: 3.1–3.25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. 1974. Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science 185: 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldmann, M. 1996. Knowledge-based causal induction. Psychology of Learning and Motivation 34: 47–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldmann, M. R., & Mayrhofer, R. (2016). Hybrid causal representations. In Psychology of Learning and Motivation (Vol. 65, pp. 85-127). Academic Press.

  • Walker, C.M. & Gopnik, A., (2013) ‘Causality and imagination’ The Oxford handbook of the development of imagination, 342–358.

  • White, P.A. 2006. The causal asymmetry. Psychological Review 113 (1): 132–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, P.A. 2009. Perception of forces exerted by objects in collision events. Psychological Review 116 (3): 580–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003) Making things happen, Oxford University Press.

  • Woodward, J. (2007) ‘Interventionist theories of causation in psychological perspective’, in Gopnik, A., Schulz, L. (eds), Causal Learning, Oxford University Press, 19–36.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank David Lagnado, Phyllis Illari, and Federica Russo for comments on the dissertation chapter from which this article draws. I am also grateful to Matteo Colombo and Jan Sprenger for feedback on a related project during a fellowship at the Tilburg Center for Logic, Ethics, and Philosophy of Science that has helped shape this paper. I would also like to thank one anonymous referee and the editor of this journal for suggestions on improving the main argument.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elena Popa.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Popa, E. A Psychological Approach to Causal Understanding and the Temporal Asymmetry. Rev.Phil.Psych. 11, 977–994 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-019-00459-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-019-00459-4

Navigation