Skip to main content
Log in

Early and Late Time Perception: on the Narrow Scope of the Whorfian Hypothesis

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The Whorfian hypothesis has received support from recent findings in psychology, linguistics, and anthropology. This evidence has been interpreted as supporting the view that language modulates all stages of perception and cognition, in accordance with Whorf’s original proposal. In light of a much broader body of evidence on time perception, I propose to evaluate these findings with respect to their scope. When assessed collectively, the entire body of evidence on time perception shows that the Whorfian hypothesis has a limited scope and that it does not affect early stages of time perception. In particular, all the available evidence shows that the scope of language modulation is limited in the case of time perception, and that the most important mechanisms for time perception are cognitive clocks and simultaneity windows, which we use to perceive the temporal properties of events. Language modulation has distorting effects, but only at later stages of processing or with respect to specific categorization tasks. The paper explains what is the role of these effects in the context of all the available evidence on time cognition and perception.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are different readings of “determines” which are relevant to understand how strong this claim by Whorf is. I focus on its scope and show that independently of how strongly one interprets this determination relation, the scope of Whorf’s hypothesis is narrow, at least in the case of time perception and representation. Establishing this narrow scope is the main goal of the paper. However, I briefly address the issue of linguistic-determination in the introduction.

  2. Because of the innate nature of the “language of thought,” at least as presented by Fodor, this version of the dependence of though on language is unlike Whorf’s original formulation, which postulates dependence of thought on specific spoken languages, thereby making it incompatible with a universalist interpretation. The debate on language-dependence and the Whorfian hypothesis rarely makes this distinction explicitly, which corresponds to Chomsky’s (1986) distinction between I-language (internal representations of language) and E-language (external language), which correlates with the distinction between competence and performance. As far as the debate is concerned, many of the findings on linguistic relativity may indicate aspects of performance, rather than competence, but I shall not elaborate on this objection here because my main goal is to show that language does not modulate early stages of time perception, regardless of the universality or relativity of linguistic modulation.

  3. As mentioned, Fodor, who defended the language of thought hypothesis, argued that the scope of language modulation is restricted (1983, 2007, 2008). Fodor proposed a universalist view, but I think the issue of modulation is independent of universalism or relativism and that this issue requires more careful analysis than it has been given. In any case, the focus of this paper is the limited scope of language modulation, as proposed by Whorf’s linguistic relativity view.

  4. A precise definition of language, as opposed to other forms of communication, is required to rigorously assess the Whorfian hypothesis. Language, however, is notoriously difficult to define (i.e., is it a single capacity or multiple capacities? Is syntax what characterizes it; if not, what characterizes it? Is it uniquely human? Is it essentially representational? Is it essentially compositional (and/or conceptual) and if so, how?) This cluster of problems presents other major difficulties that I shall not pursue here.

  5. For more on this issue see (Montemayor 2010, 2013; and Montemayor and Haladjian 2015). In particular, the evolutionary approach to early and late-time perception can allow for important new insights concerning cognitive penetration, the representation of magnitudes, and the development of conceptual capacities for time cognition.

  6. A different approach to this issue is to focus on the early and late processing of frames of reference for navigation (egocentric and allocentric). As the cognitive integration of frames of reference for action become uniformly represented into the first person perspective, such integration could produce more complex and less encapsulated forms of voluntary action (Merker 2005, 2007a, b). However, none of the early navigational frames depends on linguistic modulation.

  7. I would like to thank two anonymous Reviewers for valuable feedback on previous drafts. Thanks to Fuat Balci, Randy Gallistel and Zenon Pylyshyn, for inspiring conversations on the relationship between language and time perception.

References

  • Agostino, P.V., D.A. Golombek, and W.H. Meck. 2011. Unwinding the molecular basis of interval and circadian timing. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 5: 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Athanasopoulos, P., E. Bylund, G. Montero-Melis, L. Damjanovic, A. Schartner, A. Kibbe, N. Riches, and G. Thierry. 2015. Two languages, two minds: Flexible cognitive processing driven by language of operation. Psychological Science 26 (4): 518–526.

    Google Scholar 

  • Athanosopoulos, P., E. Bylund, and D. Casasanto. 2016. Introduction to the special issue: New interdisciplinary approaches to linguistic relativity. Language Learning 66 (3): 482–486.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balci, F., D. Freestone, and C.R. Gallistel. 2009. Risk assessment in man and mouse. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 106 (7): 2459–2463.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beike, D.R., and T.S. Crone. 2008. When experienced regret refuses to fade: Regrets of actions and attempting to forget open life regrets. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 44 (6): 1545–1550.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berwick, R.C., and N. Chomsky. 2016. Why only us: Language and evolution. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 2014. Seeing-as in the light of vision science. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (3): 560–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boisvert, M.J., and D.F. Sherry. 2006. Interval timing by an invertebrate, the bumble bee Bombus impatiens. Current Biology 16: 1636–1640.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boroditsky, L. 2000. Metaphoric structuring: Understanding time through spatial metaphors. Cognition 75: 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boroditsky, L. 2011. How languages construct time. In Space, time and number in the brain. Searching for the foundations of mathematical thought, eds. S. Dehaene, E. Brannon, 333–341. Elsevier, Academic Press.

  • Brainerd, C.J., and V.F. Reyna. 2005. The science of false memory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braun, N., J.D. Thorne, H. Hildebrandt, and S. Debener. 2014. Interplay of agency and ownership: The intentional binding and rubber hand illusion paradigm combined. PLoS One 4 (9): e111967.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, S.W. 1985. Time perception and attention: The effects of prospective versus retrospective paradigms and task demands on perceived duration. Perception & Psychophysics 38: 115–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, S.W. 1997. Attentional resources in timing: Interference effects in concurrent temporal and nontemporal working memory tasks. Perception & Psychophysics 59 (7): 1118–1140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunner, D., A. Kacelnik, and J. Gibbon. 1992. Optimal foraging and timing processes in the starling (Starling vulgaris): Effect of inter-capture interval. Animal Behavior 44: 597–613.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buhusi, C.V., and W.H. Meck. 2005. What makes us tick? Functional and neural mechanisms of interval timing. Nature Reviews, Neuroscience 6 (10): 755–765.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bylund, E., and P. Athanasopoulos. 2017. The Whorfian time warp: Representing duration through the language hourglass. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 146 (7): 991–916.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvert, A.L., L. Green, and J. Myerson. 2010. Delay discounting of qualitatively different reinforcers in rats. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior 93: 171–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheke, L.C., and N.S. Clayton. 2012. Eurasian jays (Garrulus glandarius) overcome their current desires to anticipate two distinct future needs and plan for them appropriately. Biology Letters 8: 171–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cheng, K., and W. Roberts. 1991. Three psychophysical principles of timing in pigeons. Learning and Motivation 22: 112–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1986. Knowledge of language: Its nature, origin, and use. New York: Praeger Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2000. A theory of sentience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N.S., and A. Dickinson. 1998. Episodic-like memory during cache recovery by scrub-jays. Nature 395: 272–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N.S., K.S. Yu, and A. Dickinson. 2003a. Interacting cache memories: Evidence of flexible memory use by scrub jays. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes 29: 14–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N.S., T.J. Bussey, and A. Dickinson. 2003b. Can animals recall the past and plan for the future? Nature Reviews Neurosciences 4: 685–691.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N.S., N.J. Emery, and A. Dickinson. 2006. The prospective cognition of food caching and recovery by western scrub-jays (Aphelocoma californica). Comparative Cognition and Behavior Reviews 1 (1): 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conway, M.A., and C.W. Pleydell-Pearce. 2000. The construction of autobiographical memories in the self-memory system. Psychological Review 107 (2): 261–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coull, J.T., F. Vidal, B. Nazarian, and F. Macar. 2004. Functional anatomy of the attentional modulation of time estimation. Science 303: 1506–1508.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, D.P.A., C.A. Varnon, M.B.C. Sokolowski, H. Wells, and C.I. Abramson. 2014. An assessment of fixed interval timing in free-flying honey bees (Apis mellifera ligustica): An analysis of individual performance. PLoS One 9 (7): e101262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cravo, A.M., P.M.E. Claessens, and M.V.C. Baldo. 2009. Voluntary action and causality in temporal binding. Experimental Brain Research 199 (1): 95–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cravo, A.M., P.M.E. Claessens, and M.V.C. Baldo. 2011. The relation between action, predictability and temporal contiguity in temporal binding. Acta Psychologica 136: 157–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • David, N., A. Newen, and K. Vogeley. 2008. The “sense of agency” and its underlying cognitive and neural mechanisms. Consciousness and Cognition 17: 523–534.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drew, M.R., B. Zupan, A. Cooke, P.A. Couvillon, and P.D. Balsam. 2005. Temporal control of conditioned responding in goldfish. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes 31: 31–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Droit-Volet, S., and W.H. Meck. 2007. How emotions colour our time perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11: 504–513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Droit-Volet, S., S. Fayolle, M. Lamotte, and S. Gil. 2013. Time, emotion and the embodiment of timing. Timing and Time Perception 0: 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eagleman, D.M., and A.O. Holcombe. 2002. Causality and the perception of time. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6: 323–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, J.P., and D.M. Wegner. 2010. Time warp: Authorship shapes the perceived timing of actions and events. Consciousness and Cognition 19 (1): 481–489.

    Google Scholar 

  • Firestone, C., and B.J. Scholl. 2016. Cognition does not affect perception: Evaluating the evidence for “top-down” effects. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 39: 1–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 1983. The modularity of mind: An essay on faculty psychology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 2007. Revenge of the given. In Contemporary debates in the philosophy of mind, ed. B.P. McLaughlin and J. Cohen, 105–116. New York: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 2008. The language of thought revisited. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fredrickson, B.L., and Daniel Kahneman. 1993. Duration neglect in retrospective evaluations of affective episodes. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65 (1): 45–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, E.D., A. Ipser, A. Palmbaha, D. Pauniou, P. Brown, C. Lambert, A. Leff, and J. Driver. 2013. Sight and sound out of synch: Fragmentation and renormalisation of audiovisual integration and subjective timing. Cortex 49 (10): 2875–2887.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C.R. 1990. The organization of learning. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goff, L.M., and H.L. Roediger. 1998. Imagination inflation for action events: Repeated imaginings lead to illusory recollections. Memory and Cognition 26: 20–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., S. Clark, and J. Kalogeras. 2002. Voluntary action and conscious awareness. Nature Neuroscience 5: 382–385.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herzog, M.H., T. Kammer, and F. Scharnowski. 2016. Time slices: What is the duration of a percept? PLoS Biology 14 (4): e1002433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holcombe, A.O. 2009. Seeing slow and seeing fast: Two limits on perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13: 216–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hommel, B. 2010. Grounding attention in action control: The intentional control of selection. In Effortless attention: A new perspective in the cognitive science of attention and action, ed. B. Bruya, 121–140. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyman, I.E., T.H. Husband, and F.J. Billings. 1995. False memories of childhood experiences. Applied Cognitive Psychology 9: 181–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivry, R.B., and J.E. Schlerf. 2008. Dedicated and intrinsic models of time perception. Trends in Cognitive Science 12 (7): 273–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M., S. Di Costa and P. Haggard. 2015. Intentional binding: A measure of agency. In Behavioral methods in consciousness research, ed. M. Overgaard. Oxford University Press, Oxford Scholarship Online.

  • Kahneman, D. 1973. Attention and effort. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. 2000. Experienced utility and objective happiness: a moment-based approach. In Choices, values, and frames, ed. D. Kahneman and A. Tversky, 673–692. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., B.L. Fredrickson, C.A. Schreiber, and D.A. Redelmeier. 1993. When more pain is preferred to less: Adding a better end. Psychological Science 4 (6): 401–405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Komiya, A., Y. Miyamoto, M. Watanabe, and T. Kusumi. 2011. Cultural grounding of regret: Regret in self and interpersonal contexts. Cognition and Emotion 25 (6): 1121–1130.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeDoux, J.E. 1998. Fear and the brain: Where have we been and where are we going? Biological Psychiatry 44 (12): 1229–1238.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeDoux, J.E. 2000. Emotion circuits in the brain. Annual Review of Neuroscience 23: 155–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay, D.S., L. Hagen, J.D. Read, K.A. Wade, and M. Garry. 2004. True photographs and false memories. Psychological Science 15 (3): 149–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E.F. 1975. Leading questions and the eyewitness report. Cognitive Psychology 7: 560–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E.F., and J.E. Pickrell. 1995. The formation of false memories. Psychiatric Annals 25: 720–725.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow, P. 1999. Semantics, tense, and time: An essay in the metaphysics of natural language. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lupyan, G. 2012. Linguistically modulated perception and cognition: The label-feedback hypothesis. Frontiers in Psychology 3: 54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, B., and A. Musetti. 2017. Innate and cultural spatial time: A developmental perspective. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11: 215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazur, J.E. 1991. Choice with probabilistic reinforcement: Effects of delay and conditioned reinforcers. Journal of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior 55: 63–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazur, J.E. 2000. Tradeoffs among delay, rate, and amount of reinforcement. Behavioural Processes 49: 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mazur, J.E. 2007. Species differences between rats and pigeons in choices with probabilistic and delayed reinforcers. Behavioural Processes 75: 220–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGurk, H., and J. MacDonald. 1976. Hearing lips and seeing voices. Nature 264 (5588): 746–748.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meck, W.H. 1996. Neuropharmacology of timing and time perception. Cognitive Brain Research 3: 227–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meck, W.H., and A.M. Benson. 2002. Dissecting the brain’s internal clock: How frontal-striatal ciruitry keeps time and shifts attention. Brain and Cognition 48 (1): 195–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, H., and V. de Lafuente. 2014. Introduction to the neurobiology of interval timing. Advances in Experimental Medicine and Biology 829: 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merchant, H., D.L. Harrington, and W.H. Meck. 2013. Neural basis of the perception and estimation of time. Annual Review of Neuroscience 36: 313–336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merker, B. 2005. The liabilities of mobility: A selection pressure for the transition to consciousness in animal evolution. Consciousness and Cognition 14 (1): 89–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merker, B. 2007a. Consciousness without a cerebral cortex: A challenge for neuroscience and medicine. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (1): 63–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merker, Bjorn. 2007b. Grounding consciousness: The mesodiencephalon as thalamocortical base. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (1): 110–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montemayor, C. 2010. Time: biological, intentional, and cultural. In Time: limits and constraints, ed. J.A. Parker, P. Harris, and C. Steineck, 39–63. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montemayor, C. 2013. Minding time: A philosophical and theoretical approach to the psychology of time. Boston: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montemayor, C., and F. Balci. 2007. Compositionality in language and arithmetic. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 27: 53–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montemayor, C., and H.H. Haladjian. 2015. Consciousness, attention, and conscious attention. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montemayor, C., and H.H. Haladjian. 2017. Perception and cognition are largely independent, but still affect each other in systematic ways: Arguments from evolution and the consciousness-attention dissociation. Frontiers in Psychology 8: 40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montemayor, C., and M. Wittmann. 2014. The varieties of presence: Hierarchical levels of temporal integration. Timing and Time Perception 2 (3): 325–338.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J.W., and S.S. Obhi. 2012. Intentional binding and the sense of agency: A review. Consciousness and Cognition 21: 546–561.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, S.A., and L.A. Zoellner. 2007. Overgeneral autobiographical memory and traumatic events: An evaluative review. Psychological Bulletin 133 (3): 419–437.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niemeier, S. and R Dirven. 2000. Evidence for linguistic relativity. Current issues in linguistic theory, 198. John Benjamins Publishing Company.

  • Parsons, B.D., S.D. Novich, and D.M. Eagleman. 2013. Motor-sensory recalibration modulates perceived simultaneity of cross-modal events at different distances. Frontiers in Psychology 4: 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pavlenko, A. 2009. Conceptual representation in the bilingual lexicon and secondary language learning. In The bilingual mental lexicon: Interdisciplinary approaches, ed. A. Pavlenko, 125–160. Clevendon: Multilingual Matters.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. 1992. Scenarios, concepts and perception. In The contents of experience, ed. T. Crane, 105–135. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Platt, M.L., and A.A. Ghazanfar. 2010. Primate Neuroehtology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pöppel, E. 1988. Mindworks: Time and conscious experience. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pöppel, E. 1997. A hierarchical model of temporal perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 1: 56–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z.W. 1999. Is vision continuous with cognition? The case for cognitive impenetrability of visual perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (3): 341–365 discussion 366-423.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raftopoulos, A. 2014. The cognitive impenetrability of the content of early vison is a necessary and sufficient condition for purely nonconceptual content. Philosophical Psychology 27 (5): 601–620.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renner, M. 1960. Contribution of the honey bee to the study of time sense and astronomical orientation. Cold Spring Harbor Symposium on Quantitative Biology 25: 361–367.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohenkohl, G., J.T. Coull, and A.C. Nobre. 2011. Behavioural dissociation between exogenous and endogenous temporal orienting of attention. PLoS One 6 (1): e14620.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roy C., S. Dalla Bella, and J. Lagarde. 2016. To bridge or not the time gap: Is there an optimal SOA of audio-tactile events to pace bimanual coordination? Experimental Brain Research, in press.

  • Schacter, D.L., M. Verfaille, and D. Pradere. 1996. The neuropsychology of memory illusions: False recall and recognition in amnesic patients. Journal of Memory and Language 35: 319–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D.L., S.A. Guerin, and P.L.S. Jacques. 2011. Memory distortion: An adaptive perspective. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15: 467–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stetson, C., X. Cui, P.R. Montague, and D.M. Eagleman. 2006. Motor-sensory recalibration leads to an illusory reversal of action and sensation. Neuron 51: 651–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Synofzik, M., G. Vosgerau, and A. Newen. 2008. Beyond the comparator model: A multifactorial two-step account of agency. Consciousness and Cognition 17: 219–239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A. 1996. The binding problem. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 6 (2): 171–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A. 1998. Feature binding, attention, and object perception. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences 353 (1373): 1295–1306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. 1982. The psychology of preferences. Scientific American 246 (1): 160–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Wassenhove, V. (2009). Minding time in an amodal representational space. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 364(1525), 1815–1830. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2009.0023.

  • Vatakis, A., and C. Spence. 2007. Crossmodal binding: Evaluating the “unity assumption” using audiovisual speech stimuli. Perception & Psychophysics 69: 744–756.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vatakis, A., and R. Ulrich. 2014a. Temporal processing within and across senses – Part 1. Acta Psychologica 147: 1–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vatakis, A., and R. Ulrich. 2014b. Temporal processing within and across senses – Part 2. Acta Psychologica 149: 129–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, V. 2003. A theory of magnitude: Common cortical metrics of time, space and quantity. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7: 483–488.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wenke, D., and P. Haggard. 2009. How voluntary actions modulate time perception. Experimental Brain Research 196: 311–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whorf, B. 1956. Language, thought, and reality. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittmann, M. 2011. Moments in time. Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 5: 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yarrow, K., I. Sverdrup-Stueland, W. Roseboom, and D.H. Arnold. 2013. Sensorimotor temporal recalibration within and across limbs. Journal of Experimental Psychology, Human Perception and Performance 39 (6): 1678–1689.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zakay, D., D. Nitzan, and J. Glicksohn. 1983. The influence of task difficulty and external tempo on subjective time estimation. Perception & Psychophysics 34: 451–456.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zampini, M., S. Guest, D.I. Shore, and C. Spence. 2005. Audio-visual simultaneity judgments. Perception & Psychophysics 67 (3): 531–544.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author received valuable feedback from Argiro Vatakis, Alex Holcombe, and Harry H. Haladjian.

Some aspects of this paper are discussed in “Conscious awareness and time perception.” https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/28745453

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Carlos Montemayor.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Montemayor, C. Early and Late Time Perception: on the Narrow Scope of the Whorfian Hypothesis. Rev.Phil.Psych. 10, 133–154 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0405-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0405-4

Navigation