1 Introduction

This paper proposes a solution of the Easterlin paradox, what this paper prefers to call the “income-happiness paradox.” Easterlin (1974, 1995, 2010, 2017) uncovered a contradiction in two sets of data regarding whether happiness tracks income. The correlation between income and happiness is positive in point-of-time data (i.e., cross-sectional data set within a country) as well as data across countries irrespective of level of prosperity. However, happiness does not rise with income in life-cycle data (i.e., time-series data spanning more than a decade) for countries where the average income surpasses about $75,000 threshold using 2010 price level (see also Kahneman and Deaton 2010). As “Appendix 1” details, there has been a wide-ranging debate about the Easterlin paradox and the two sets of data. This paper accepts the reality of the Easterlin paradox, in step of the assessment of most scholars (e.g., Kahneman and Deaton 2010; Deaton and Stone 2013).

The cross-sectional data set is grit for the mill of the stylized economist—but it is anomalous for the stylized psychologist as best expressed by set point theory. In its textbook formulation, set point theory registers that whatever happens to substantive goods that the economist studies, and whatever happens to the consequent substantive utility that the economist studies, the person’s happiness returns to a pre-fixed set point (Brickman and Campbell 1971; Brickman et al. 1978).

Conversely, the time-series data set is grit for the mill of the stylized psychologist—but it is anomalous to the stylized economist who espouses the eminence of income. In its textbook formulation, economic theory registers that whatever happens to substantive goods consumed, the outcome must reflect such change. That is, the person’s level of happiness must positively track substantive goods consumption.Footnote 1

This paper questions whether the inconsistency of the cross-sectional and the time-series data sets amounts to a paradox. If each set gauges a different kind of satisfaction, there would be no paradox.

Some practitioners have reached the conclusion that we have two different kinds of satisfaction (e.g., Kahneman and Deaton 2010; Deaton and Stone 2013). Indeed, Deaton and Stone distinguish between “evaluative” and “hedonic” measures. Kahneman (2011, Chs. 37–38) calls them, respectively, “life satisfaction” or “life evaluation,” on the one hand, and “experienced well-being,” on the other.

The distinction between the two kinds of satisfaction led Deaton and Stone to explicitly warn against the naïve use of “the term “happiness” or, indeed, subjective well-being”. They state that the term is unhelpful, as it is a catch-all term given the difference between the evaluative and hedonic measures:

The important distinction between evaluative and hedonic well-being renders unhelpful the portmanteau uses of the term “happiness,” or, indeed, subjective well-being (Deaton and Stone 2013, 592).

Kahneman also warns against the portmanteau use of the term “happiness”, as it is not indicative of a simple meaning:

[W]e learned that the word happiness does not have a simple meaning and should not be used as if it does. Sometimes scientific progress leaves us more puzzled than we were before (Kahneman 2011, p. 407).

This paper adds its voice against the portmanteau use of the term “happiness.” It also adds its voice against the use of the term “subjective well-being”—but for unrelated reason. As for the term “happiness,” we must tread carefully and specify the variety of happiness under focus. But for the term “subjective well-being,” the term connotes a confusing abridgment of two kinds of satisfactions or utilities. One is “well-being” à la economist’s concept “utility,” while the other is “happiness” à la alternative view of satisfaction that is supposed to escape the standard economist toolkit. Given that “well-being” is already subjective as far as the economist is concerned, the term “subjective well-being” is a pleonasm. If the term denotes something beyond the economist’s well-being, let us call it “happiness.” So, this paper uses the terms “well-being” and “happiness” as separate concepts—while avoiding the term “subjective well-being” as it amounts to conflating well-being and happiness.

Indeed, this paper argues that well-being is “substantive utility” in the standard economist sense. Well-being or substantive utility function is a function of what can be called “substantive goods”. This paper prefers to use the term “substantive goods” and “substantive utility”—rather than “material goods” and “material utility”—to stress that substantive goods that occasion well-being is not limited to narrow “material” goods purchased by income. The set of substantive goods includes leisure, physical health, neighborhood security, environmental quality, marital status, and so on (see David et al. 2014). In this regard, the term “well-being” covers the empirical studies of social indicators that include these substantive goods—and even include mental health (e.g., Huppert and So 2013; Niemiec and Ryan 2014).

However, the term “well-being” as used here does not cover empirical studies that include variables related to non-substantive satisfaction. Examples of non-substantive satisfaction, what is called here “transcendental utility,” includes: (1) reflection on current income while comparing it to an imagined past income; (2) imagining an aspired goal that lifts well-being above the normal, predicted path of the future; (3) familial/communal bonding (see Khalil 2021); and (4) hopeful disposition; (This paper ignores the latter two varieties of transcendental effects, as they are not pertinent to the solution of the income-happiness paradox).

It is often the case that many empirical studies measures satisfaction by lumping “well-being”, i.e., substantive satisfaction that includes health, environmental quality, and other variables just discussed, with “happiness”, i.e., non-substantive satisfaction just defined (see David et al. 2014). The lumping is assisted with the “subjective well-being” portmanteau term (e.g., Pavot and Diener 2014; Miao et al. 2014; Cummins 2014; Gelatt 2013).

Specifically, lumping takes place when well-being is not distinguished from religious engagement, which is better understood as non-substantive satisfaction (e.g., David 2014). Further, lumping takes place when aspired goal and comparison of income are combined to measure life satisfaction (e.g., Dumludag and Gokdemir 2022), when aspired goal, acceptance of current well-being, and social relations are combined (e.g., Vendrik 2013). In addition, many researchers suppose that if they take into consideration goods that cannot be purchased, such as social life and environment, they are discussing happiness, and not simply “economics” (e.g., Hendriks and Bartram 2016; Graham and Markowitz 2011). Such a supposition is based on defining economics à la Alfred Marshall’s sense, i.e., about material goods that are purchased, rather than about economizing the allocation of all arguments that make up the substantive goods function à la Lionel Robbins and Gary Becker (see Khalil 1996b).

The conceptual axis upon which the proposed solution of the income-happiness paradox stands is the non-lumping of well-being and happiness. While well-being is a function of substantive goods that are not limited to purchased goods, happiness is another genus, transcendental utility. This paper defines transcendental utility as qualitatively different from substantive utility (well-being). This paper focuses on two varieties of transcendental utility mentioned briefly above: (1) the satisfaction from contemplating/ruminating a given well-being in light of an imagined well-being in the past; and (2) the satisfaction from aspiring/desiring an imagined well-being that can be achieved in the future. As stated above, the difference between the two facets of transcendental utility hinges on whether the context employed is an imagined well-being in the past or an imagined well-being of the future.

The identified dual facet of happiness captures what Deaton, Stone, and Kahneman have identified as two different gauges of happiness. They have called them the “evaluative” and “hedonic” measures. This paper goes further and proposes a hypothesis of how these two measures or, what is the same thing, the dual facet of happiness, are linked. This paper argues that the link between the two measures is the key to solving the income-happiness paradox.

It is a challenge to solve the paradox, as other attempts suffer from shortcomings. “Appendix 2” details the shortcomings of three major attempts: Kahneman’s, relative income hypothesis, and Easterlin’s. The proposed solution promises to supersede such shortcomings. The proposed solution is based on a framework laid in Sect. 1. The framework, first, delineates “well-being” from “happiness,” and, second, delineates the dual facet of happiness. While Sect. 2 analyzes one facet (happiness-as-aspiration), Sect. 3 analyzes the other (happiness-as-tranquility). Sections 4 and 5 present the solution. Section 6 concludes.

2 Two sets of distinction

To elaborate on the two sets of distinction already mentioned:

  1. 1.

    Two Genera of Utility There is a difference between two genera of utility: “well-being” understood as substantive utility in the economist substantive sense as contra to “happiness” understood as transcendental utility that differs from well-being. Well-being is function of (monetary) income, which allows the decision maker (DM) to purchase goods, and other substantive inputs such as leisure, work conditions, and amenities. Happiness is rather a function of well-being that is situated against a context. Such contextualized well-being allows the DM to ruminate and to ponder about the meaning and purpose of his or her life.

  2. 2.

    Dual Facet of Happiness There is a difference between two kinds of rumination or pondering about the meaning and purpose of one’s life. These two kinds are at the origin of two facets of happiness: “happiness-as-tranquility” understood as transcendental utility arising from the rumination over past achievements as contra to “happiness-as-aspiration” understood as another facet of transcendental utility arising from the rumination over forward looking goals. The difference lies with the kind of context used in such rumination. If the context is the evaluation of one’s life in general, the DM experiences happiness-as-tranquility or, if negative, the lack of such happiness. If the context is one’s emotional going during the day, as one attempts to attain a goal, the DM experiences happiness-as-aspiration or, if negative, the lack of such happiness.

For the first distinction (see Khalil 2022a), utility is not a single genus, made up only of well-being defined as satisfaction that is a function of primitives such as income, leisure, health, work conditions, and amenities. Utility is also happiness, defined as the satisfaction that is a function of contextualized well-being.

For the second distinction (see Khalil 2022b), contextualized well-being is not a single kind. There are different kinds of context and, corollary, different kinds of happiness. This paper identifies and discusses only two kinds of context, giving rise to the dual facet of happiness.

Table 1 represents the two kinds of context/happiness. For the first row, the first kind is what Kahneman calls “life evaluation”—or the literature calls “evaluative” measure. The outcome is what the DM experiences as tranquility. This facet of happiness is captured by the point-of-time, cross-sectional data set (both within a country and across countries). For this measure, happiness tracks income. This measure pleases the stylized economist, but not the stylized psychologist.

Table 1 The dual facet of happiness

According to the second row, the second kind of context is what Kahneman calls “experienced well-being”—or what the literature calls “hedonic” measure. The outcome is what the DM experiences as aspiration. This facet of happiness is captured by the life-cycle, time-series data set (spanning more than a decade). For this measure, happiness does not track income once a country becomes rich, surpassing an income threshold. This measure pleases the stylized psychologist, but not the stylized economist.

Still, what divides the two kinds of transcendental utility—i.e., happiness-as-tranquility and happiness-as-aspiration? What is the difference that makes the latter insensitive to income while the former sensitive? When the DM stands in the present and reflects on the future, the DM usually adopts an aspired goal. Such aspired goal must be steady. This explains why forward-looking happiness (aspiration) is insensitive to income. In contrast, when the DM stands in the present and reflects on the past, the DM assesses an accomplishment against a counterfactual. If the accomplishments, such as income, grows while the counterfactual is steady, it explains why backward-looking happiness (tranquility) is sensitive to income.

Table 1 should act as a guide for the rest of the paper, given that the paper shall go through contours discussing other solutions of the paradox, developing more terms to differentiate forward- as opposed to backward-looking assessment, and propose conceptual distinctions necessary for the defense of the proposed thesis. One of the challenges is to develop terms that allow for the modification of rational choice theory to incorporate the role of context—a role that psychologists have emphasized for a long time and only recently heeded by some (behavioral) economists.

3 Aspirational utility

Let us define exhilaration as the excitement or joy that arises from the pursuit of a goal in one’s career—or it can be as little as the pursuit of a goal in one's day. Exhilaration is a positive function of the desired goal in comparison to the current well-being. When the DM aspires to achieve a goal during the day—which can be as simple as painting one's kitchen—or to achieve a higher rank during a career, the DM experiences exhilaration. The mere act of aspiration affords meaning to one’s life.

The act of aspiration means that the desire, what can be called “aspired well-being,” aims to lift well-being beyond what can be dubbed “predicted/projected well-being.” The “predicted/projected well-being” concept denotes the stable flow of income and the flow of other variables such as health or neighborhood quality that the DM projects in the future. The projection is based on current capacity, where the DM does not undertake further human capital investment (other than the usual learning). It is also based on the current profession, where the DM does not venture into a different career that is more challenging. When the DM stands in the present and assesses the predicted/projected well-being, he or she is already discounting future streams of income and other variables according to an intertemporal discount rate. Further, he or she is already discounting future streams of income and other variables according to macro shocks as well as industry-specific shocks according to a risk aversion discount rate.

In contrast, the “aspired well-being” concept is based on the DM’s desire to achieve a goal that is beyond what is predicted/projected. The DM standing in the present and imagines the aspired well-being, he or she also discounts the aspired-based returns according to an intertemporal discount rate and risk aversion discount rate. As long as such rates are the same as in “predicted/projected well-being”, we may ignore them in the model presented here. Introducing these discounts rates complicate the model without any additional analytical insight.

The act of aspiration amounts to creating a gap, as the aspired well-being is greater than the predicted/projected well-being. For example, the DM may earn a wage of $50,000/year and it is projected to rise each year by 3% on average following a predicted path of learning-by-doing. If the DM aspires for the salary to rise by 7% each year, and takes steps to fulfill the desire, the DM creates a gap that is 4% in this example.

This paper proposes that the desired gap of 4% allows the DM to enjoy the feeling of exhilaration. This paper also proposes a contrary effect: the same desired gap also generates misery. That is, aspiration affords simultaneously exhilaration and misery.

While it is intuitive to understand the exhilaration effect, what is the source of the misery effect that inextricably accompanies the exhilaration? While raising a goal or posing a desire affords exhilaration, it makes the person feel that he is behind what is desired. This feeling is unpleasant and originates misery. If the goal is much higher than the predicted/projected well-being, the misery may develop into excessive misery.

Stated differently, the DM can reap a positive rush of excitement by dreaming big. But given that sheer dreaming does not change the projected well-being, dreaming big has a cost. It widens the gap between the big dream and the unchanged projected goal. Such an enlargement of the gap makes the DM aware of how far one's aspired goal is from the projected well-being. While this awareness generates a (positive) aspirational effect in the form of exhilaration, it also exacts a (negative) relative effect in the form of misery. If there is no such cost, then it pays to aspire to infinite greatness, never to worry about the gnawing gap between the aspired goal and projected well-being.

Dreaming big differs from “daydreaming.” Dreaming big, say, to become a popstar, does not amount to daydreaming if the dreaming big is associated with a series of acts that increase the possibility of becoming the desired goal. But if the aspired goal to become a popstar is not associated with a series of acts that increase the possibility of attaining the goal, such a goal can be defined as daydreaming. This difference is important to note since daydreaming and aspired well-being share, by definition, the common feature of being “unrealistic.” Both involve imagining a station that transcends the projected well-being. But insofar as no series of acts follows the dream, the goal becomes mere daydreaming.

Daydreaming resembles consumerism. Consumerism can be defined as the obsessive activity focused on possessing objects (Schumacher 1973; Schwartz 2004; Scitovsky 1992; Frank 2004). Such obsession blocks the DM from engaging the self with everyday experiences. In consumerism, the obsession locks the DM into “inactive entertainment” that basically keep the senses busy without engaging them. With consumerism, the DM is not engaged in undertaking any series of acts to improve the possibility of attaining a goal. In this regard, consumerism and daydreaming function like addiction to some consumption activity. Addictive consumption is inactive entertainment when it shuts down the senses, making it hard for the DM to take steps, such as investment in human capital and the coordination of resources to attain the desired goal. While daydreaming, consumerism and other addictive consumption give rise to pleasures, this paper does not model such pleasures as aspirational utility.

For a desire to function as an aspired well-being, the DM must undertake steps necessary to make the goal more possible. Given that the DM is not daydreaming, i.e., undertake the necessary steps entailed by the posed desired goal, the posing of an aspired goal involves a two-edged sword:

  1. 1.

    The Positive Edge The posing of a desired goal engenders exhilaration since it affords the person a satisfaction of seeing a goal ahead, i.e., a goal to attain. As part of posing a goal higher than one’s predicted/projected well-being, the DM undertakes a style of consumption that is not pursued for its substantive utility but pursued for what Khalil (2000) calls “symbolic” effect, and what Becchetti et al. (2008) designate as “relational goods.” Indeed, Becchetti et al. (2008) find that the consumption of relational goods contributes to the DM’s report of greater life satisfaction. However, Becchetti et al. (2011) finds a reverse effect of relational goods (see also, Becchetti et al. 2019, pp. 377–388): higher income leads to a lower demand of relational goods which undermines happiness. At a closer examination, though, they define relational goods differently, namely, as “local public goods” that typifies familial/communal bonding. With such alternative definition, higher income makes it more expensive for DMs, in terms of opportunity cost, to invest in familial/communal bonding. Hence, higher income may undermine happiness, as DMs invest less in local public goods that promote familial/communal bonding. (Anyhow, as indicated as the outset, this paper ignores familial/communal bonding, and other pillars of happiness such as hope.)Footnote 2

  2. 2.

    The Negative Edge The posing of a desired goal engenders a cost as already mentioned. The literature identifies this cost as the “relative income effect” (Duesenberry 1949; Clark et al. 2008; Boyce et al. 2010). Namely, when the DM poses a goal that is higher than the predicted or projected well-being, the DM creates what can be called a “negative gap”. It is similar to the negative gap that the DM creates when he or she joins a club or a peer group whose average income is higher than his or her predicted/projected well-being. The negative gap occasions the feeling of misery, as it amounts to a reminder that the DM’s state of affairs is lower than the desired one.

If the DM poses a goal that is lower than the predicted/projected well-being, the DM creates what can be called a “positive gap”. It is similar to the positive gap that the DM creates when he or she joins a club or a peer group whose average income is lower than his or her predicted/projected well-being. The positive gap occasions the feeling of cheerfulness, contrary to misery, as it amounts to a testimony that the DM’s state of affairs is higher than the goal.

Actually, the “relative income effect” literature focuses exclusively on this positive gap, i.e., the tendency of DMs to join clubs of lower average income or status than their own. While this effect may push some people to join and identify with goals lower than their predicted/projected well-being, it might not be the dominant effect. As Khalil et al. (2021) show, the dominant effect is for people to aspire and identify with clubs of higher average income or status than their own. Although such membership or identification involves the pain or misery arising from the negative gap, this negative gap occasions the “aspiration income effect,” i.e., exhilaration. For DMs to join clubs that express goals higher than their predicted/projected well-being, the exhilaration effect must be greater than the inescapable misery.

Throughout this paper, it is assumed that DMs seeks the negative gap, i.e., tolerate the inescapable misery associated with the pursuit of a desire. Hence, it refers to the negative gap as simply the “gap.”

To recapitulate, the pursuit of the gap, i.e., desire, occasions two opposing simultaneous effects: exhilaration as well as misery. To manage these two edges of desire—viz., exhilaration and misery—the DM needs to balance the relative income effect of aspiring, which is negative, and the aspirational income effect of aspiring, which is positive. The two effects are dialectical aspects of aspirational utility, i.e., happiness-as-aspiration (Ha):

$$H^{{\text{a}}} = H^{{\text{a}}} \left( {W^{{\text{f}}} |W^{{{\text{pr}}}} } \right)$$
(1)

where Wpr is predicted/projected well-being, and Wf is the future (aspired) well-being that acts as the context or counterfactual. This paper assumes that (Wf − Wpr) > 0, i.e., the pursuit of an aspired well-being that is higher than the predicted/projected well-being. This creates a gap between the predicted/projected well-being and the desired one. The decision maker tries to keep the gap at the optimal level—where the positive effect, i.e., the aspirational income effect, should never at the margin dip below the negative effect, what is known as the relative income effect.

As Fig. 1 shows, the optimal gap is the optimal level of desired well-being (Wd*) along the horizontal axis that measures the degree of aspiration, i.e., desired well-being (Wd). The vertical axis measures the transcendental utility identified as happiness-as-aspiration (Ha). The relative income effect curve measures the cost of Wd, while the aspirational income effect curve measures the benefit of the same degree of Wd. The DM attains the maximum Ha (Ha*) just when the marginal cost of aspiration equals the marginal benefit of aspiration, i.e., at Wd*. That is, the DM selects Wd* that maximizes the distance between the cost and benefit of aspiration.

Fig. 1
figure 1

The benefit and cost of aspiration

The two effects captured in Fig. 1 are based on some technical assumptions. The most important are the ones that guarantee the usual first and second-order conditions. Aside from such assumptions, the basic idea is that people are rational in the manner they select the degree of desire. The selection of the optimal, i.e., proper, degree of desire is key to mental health.

The positive psychology literature—to recall, e.g., Ryff (1989), Deci and Flaste (1996), Ryan and Deci (2001), Csikszentmihalyi (1990), Seligman (2002, 2004, 2011), Seligman and Csikszentmihalyi (2000)—extensively discusses studies of how people maintain mental health. To wit, as Crum and Salovey (in David et al. 2014) argue, at least some of the emotions that the DM adopts are crucial in motivating the DM to undertake challenging and aspiring goals. The DM undertakes such goals by choosing an efficient degree of aspiration—although this literature does not employ the rational choice concept.Footnote 3

While people are rational in choosing the degree of desire, this should not mean that people do not occasionally, and some cases pathologically, over-shoot and choose sub-optimal degrees of desire.Footnote 4 Smith (1976, pp. 50–62) illustrates such over-shooting, and regards it as an illusion, in his famous parable of the poor man’s son whom the heavens punished with ambition.Footnote 5

Aside from anecdotal evidence, a closer look at the time-series data of highly prosperous countries, it is possible to witness the phenomenon of over-shooting, what Graham and Pettinato (2002) call “frustrated achievers”. As they demonstrate with regard to Peru and Russia (Graham and Pettinato 2002, pp. 101–136) and what Becchetti and Rossetti (2009) show with regard to the German socioeconomic panel data between 1992 and 2004, a portion of the people whose absolute income is rising declare lower life satisfaction. The sources vary from job insecurity, health deterioration, decline of relative income despite rise of absolute income, marital status shocks, and poorer social life. Hirschman and Rothschild (1973) have long noted the phenomenon of frustrated achievers in developed countries, characterizing it as a “tunnel effect,” Even if drivers in one lane in a tunnel are advancing, they would feel as frustrated achievers if the drivers in adjacent lanes in the tunnel are advancing faster than themselves. The tunnel effect is negative happiness-as-aspiration. It is the outcome of the adoption of non-optimal gap. That is, the setting of a goal that is excessively high, i.e., where the DM’s achievement falls short, would generate a negative happiness-as-aspiration. As further confirmation, while absolute income decline plays a role, Becchetti and Conzo (2021) find that high-income expectations (i.e., excessive goals or desires) contribute to the rise of depression, as accounted by the despair death crisis, in the European Social Survey data.

Still, it is misguided to conclude that any aspired well-being, which may lead to over-shooting, as an “illusion” as the case of Kahneman and Thaler (2006) and Erez et al (1995).Footnote 6 To wit, Loewenstein et al. (2003) regard aspired well-being per se as non-rational, expressing an innate expression of being human to commit “projection bias.” In the proposed model, aspired well-being can be rational, and only becomes non-rational when the degree of desire exceeds an optimal level.

DMs may act non-rationally, especially in countries undergoing unprecedented GDP per capita growth. These DMs adopt non-efficient degrees of desire—trying to become rich as fast as their neighbors. This situation usually leads to misery, undermining happiness-as-aspiration. This may explain the puzzling rise of suicide rates and mental illness in fast-growing countries (see Lyubomirsky et al. 2005; Marmot 2004; Ng 2002).

The proposed model has two payoffs. First, it allows us to characterize the occasional cases when people cease to aspire, which would amount to daydreaming or indulgence in addictive consumption that can be called the “collapse of will.” Such a collapse should not be confused with succumbing to temptation, usually called the “weakness of willpower.” One way to distinguish the two phenomena is that the weakness of willpower is giving in to a suboptimal choice when the issue at hand is not aspiration, while the collapse of will is the giving up on choosing an aspired well-being when the issue at hand is aspirational (see Khalil 2015, 2017). In this context, we may reinterpret the thesis of Ray (2006), viz., that the collapse of aspiration is the root of the poverty trap, as being about the case when the DM finds it too hard to reach the aspired goal, and hence gives up altogether. Ray’s thesis, hence, resonates with Karelis’ (2009) thesis of how the poor are over-burdened with problems and, hence, become unmotivated, and Oxoby’s (2003) model of the emergence of the underclass as the outcome of the disappearance of aspiration (see also Senik 2008).

The second payoff is pertinent to the proposed solution of the income-happiness paradox. While the DM chooses the level of desired well-being, such a choice is a function of the DM's projected well-being. Given that the DM is constrained by whatever is the level of projected well-being, the chosen desired well-being cannot deviate too far. This explains why the gap between the desired and the projected well-being, i.e., the origin of happiness-as-aspiration, is constant, i.e., it does not vary with the variation of the level of projected well-being.

The task of solving the income-happiness paradox is not yet complete. To tackle the paradox, we need to also study the other facet of transcendental utility, happiness-as-tranquility.

4 Tranquility utility

There is another facet of happiness that the DM experiences when he or she reflects on the level of their current well-being in general. This facet arises from assessing what the DM has attained or achieved, i.e., contrasting it to an imagined well-being in the past. This imagined well-being acts as a counterfactual well-being against which the DM evaluates realized (current) well-being. The counterfactual well-being acts as “context” or “frame” through which the DM makes sense of his or her current well-being. The concept of “context” or “frame” is similar to the one advanced by Tversky and Kahneman (1981). Namely, DMs do not only sense utility in the pure, naked sense. DMs also sense “framing effects,” outcomes once such utility is placed within diverse contexts.

For instance, a person might experience flooding and consequently loses all belonging, say, in the basement of his or her house. If the counterfactual is the loss of belonging in all floors of the house, a salient counterfactual if most neighbors lost everything, the DM would feel fortunate and, hence, experience positive happiness-as-tranquility (Ht). However, if the counterfactual is the loss of nothing, a salient counterfactual if most neighbors lost nothing, the DM would feel unlucky and frustrated, i.e., negative Ht:

$$H^{{\text{t}}} = H^{{\text{t}}} \left( {W^{{\text{c}}} |W^{{\text{p}}} } \right)$$
(2)

where Wc is current well-being and Wp is the past well-being that acts as the context or counterfactual. If Wc > Wp, Ht would be positive. Otherwise, Ht would be negative.

The finding of Clark (2003) is pertinent. Clark examines the happiness level of full-time employees in eleven waves of British panel data, as measured by life satisfaction and other standard measures. He finds that life-satisfaction falls with the rise of average income of the reference group. The DMs seem to take the average income of the reference group as the counterfactual. Of more interest is that he also finds that life-satisfaction significantly rises with the rise of the variance in income, i.e., the rise of income inequality. Clark expresses surprise with this finding, which he calls “inequality loving.” It is surprising given the standard assumption in the economics literature that, all other things equal, inequality is a “bad” (e.g., Fehr and Schmidt 1999). But “inequality loving” should not be surprising in light of the proposed concept of “happiness-as-tranquility.” The greater the variance, the greater is the possibility for most people above the worst-off strata to compare their current income to the income of the worst-off strata. The income of the worst-off strata becomes, obviously, more salient the greater is the variance. That is, the greater is the gap between one’s current income and the income of the worst-off strata, the greater solace or happiness-as-tranquility.

This notion of happiness-as-tranquility can be traced to ancient Greek thought, starting with Zeno, leading to the mature Stoic Roman philosophy (see Annas 1995; Brennan 2005; Nussbaum 2009; Sellars 2006). The basic idea of stoicism is that whatever his or her current well-being, the DM must always evaluate it as a gift, i.e., choose the counterfactual of the past (Wp) as close to zero. Even when the DM experiences a negative shock, where current well-being is below the normal, the DM should place the shock in the context that the current well-being could be worse. Therefore, the DM can experience contentment even in the most calamitous state of nature. Whatever happens is part of the work of cosmic events that were, anyhow, never within the control of the DM in the past.

However, do people try, with seriousness and frequency, to select rationally a counterfactual well-being that is lower than the current one? Is it not too often the case that unfortunate events, whether unleashed by nature or fellow humans, send people into great frustration, if not bitterness. In The Book of Job (The Old Testament), Job’s wife tried to convince Job to recant God, to cease his trust, and to curse the day he was born. On the other hand, Job’s four friends convinced him not to choose bitterness, while only Elihu grounded such a recommendation on the choice of the proper counterfactual. Namely, Job must see life itself as a gift. And given that Job is still alive, he should experience tranquil utility over his (miserable) current well-being.

Many of the religious parables of suffering humanity—or their secular equivalents ranging from poems, songs, novels to feature films—provide people with solace that eases the unhappiness arising from their misfortune state of nature. From casual empiricism, people seemingly derive relaxation upon learning about the calamities that strike others—and they do so not out of schadenfreude. The stories of calamities that strike others—even ones who lived long ago or in far-away land—act as counterfactual background that prompts people to count their blessings, if religious, or to express gratitude and kindness, if secular.

The DM should maintain equanimity in the face of misfortune, ever remembering that their luck could even be worse. What is less analyzed is that the DM should not, equally, express glee in the face of fortune. Indeed, according to the Stoics, the DM should remain calm, i.e., the DM should never give in to excitement and thrill upon the revelation of good luck. If the DM exhibits excitement with respect to good luck, he or she might slip and attribute the good luck to astute decisions taken in the past, i.e., slip into self-congratulation, if not conceit. The DM should be aware of the role of luck in both directions and, hence, express humility in the face of triumphs as much as he should appreciate the gifts of life in the face of disasters.

How to handle luck in both directions is expressed best in Rudyard Kipling’s famous poem, “If'”:

If you can meet with Triumph and Disaster

and treat those two imposters just the same.

That is, if the DM wishes to sustain equanimity, they must realize that “Triumph” and “Disaster” are imposters. Hence, as much the DM should not surrender to despair in the case of “Disaster,” the DM should not indulge in excitement over “Triumph.” Both are pretenders in the sense that they are random shocks, i.e., they do not express the true underpinning movement of well-being.

This alerts us to the observation that the DM employs a similar counterfactual in both disasters and triumphs. In both states of nature, the DM employs a counterfactual well-being that is lower than the current well-being. In the case of triumph, the DM would experience calmness—like the case of disaster. The employment of the lower counterfactual in both cases allows for stability and steadiness of happiness, i.e., happiness-as-tranquility, where one’s happiness is only a function of the true progress of well-being. The tranquility utility would not reflect the stochastic shock. This explains why the question about the evaluation of one’s life in general, discussed below, allows happiness-as-tranquility to track well-being which, in turn, tracks income.

As already mentioned, for the DM keep positive happiness-as-tranquility—irrespective if the current well-being is triumph or disaster—the DM employs a counterfactual well-being of the past (Wp) that is always lower than current well-being (Wc). In the case of misfortune, where Wc is lower than normal well-being (Wn), happiness-as-tranquility (Ht) takes the form of “contentment” (Ht–c). To put it formally,

$$H^{{{\text{t}} - {\text{c}}}} = H^{{{\text{t}} - {\text{c}}}} \left( {W^{{\text{c}}} |W^{{\text{p}}} } \right)$$
(3)

where Wc < Wn

If 0 ≤ Wp < Wc, Ht–c > 0.

In the case of fortune, where Wc is higher than Wn, happiness-as-tranquility takes the form of “equanimity” (Ht–e),

$$H^{{{\text{t}} - {\text{e}}}} = H^{{{\text{t}} - {\text{e}}}} \left( {W^{{\text{c}}} |W^{{\text{p}}} } \right)$$
(4)

where Wc > Wn

Wp < Wc, Ht–c > 0, even if Wp > Wn.

According to functions (3) and (4), the DM’s happiness-as-tranquility are positive if the DM is rational. That is, irrespective of the shocks, the DM chooses Wp < Wc.

While functions (3) and (4) obey the condition (Wp < Wc), they differ with respect to the value of Wc in relation to the normal (Wn). The possibility in function (4) that Wp > Wn in the case of triumph allows for the possibility that some improvement of well-being rather expresses steady progress. Of course, if there is no such steady progress, i.e., if all the improvement is momentary and the outcome of fortune, Wp < Wn.

In post-WWII, most countries have experienced steady progress of well-being. Therefore, most likely, even after editing out the shocks, happiness-as-tranquility has risen, which is indeed recorded by the “evaluative measure” noted by Deaton and Stone (2013). That is, given that the evaluation of life-satisfaction has been rising with the rise of well-being, the DMs must have been employing Wp > Wn in the cases of triumphs. Such a scenario confirms the stylized economist regarding the time-series data uncovered by Easterlin (1974).Footnote 7

It is still possible that the DM acts non-rationally, i.e., chooses the counterfactual that does not lead to the increase in happiness-as-tranquility. If the DM acts non-rationally in function (4), i.e., if the DM sets Wp > Wc, the DM would slide into bitterness and ingratitude that is far from contentment (see Tai et al. 2012). Such ingratitude is the emotion of the “frustrated achievers” discussed above (Graham and Pettinato 2002; Becchetti and Rossetti 2009).

Even if the DM may have experienced great prosperity, the DM may slide into ingratitude if the DM thinks he or she deserves more. In this case, despite Wc > Wn, the DM is setting the counterfactual of the past to be higher than current well-being, Wp > Wc.

Thus, achieving positive happiness-as-tranquility, whether contentment or equanimity, is not guaranteed even with rising prosperity. Happiness-as-tranquility is rather the product of choice, the selection of the context, whereas such choice can be non-rational. Therefore, it varies, contrary to Gilbert’s (2006) notion of “synthetic happiness.” It is not always the case that people are rational, i.e., accepting the current well-being as at least partially the outcome of stochastic shocks.

5 What question? Which facet of happiness?

As Deaton and Stone (2013) have argued, the “hedonic measure” gauges happiness as shown in the time-series (life-cycle) data—where happiness does not track well-being, at least once a country becomes rich. In contrast, the “evaluative measure” gauges happiness as shown in the point-of-time (cross-section) data—i.e., happiness tracks well-being.

But is the happiness that the hedonic measure gauges happiness-as-aspiration, while the happiness that the evaluative measure gauges is happiness-as-tranquility? Does the survey question that prompts the hedonic measure indeed evoke happiness-as-aspiration, while the survey question that prompts the evaluative measure actually evokes happiness-as-tranquility? This an intricate question, as both facets of happiness are commensurable, as they both involve transcendental utility.

Deaton and Stone (2013) characterize clearly the evaluative measure, which Cantril (1965) uses, in contradistinction with the hedonic measure:

We look at two different ways of measuring well-being, an evaluative measure, the Cantril ladder, and a hedonic measure, daily happiness. The former invites respondents to rate their lives on a “ladder” with 11 steps, marked from 0, which represents the worst possible life for you, to 10, which represents the best possible life for you. Answering such a question requires the respondent to think about his life and interpret the question. We also look at a dichotomous measure in response to the question “Did you experience a lot of happiness yesterday?” This is one of several hedonic questions, which should be distinguished from the evaluative question in the ladder (Deaton and Stone 2013, 592).

That is, the evaluative measure prompts the respondent “to think about his life” and give a general assessment of how he or she interprets it. Thus, the evaluative measure identifies “happiness-as-tranquility.” Conversely, the hedonic measure prompts the respondent to think “about happiness today” or in other surveys, about happiness yesterday. Thus, the hedonic measure identifies “happiness-as-aspiration” insofar as it gauges the emotions of the DM during the day as the DM takes actions that are by definition forward-looking.

Deaton and Stone characterize evaluative measure as cognitive, while the hedonic measure as non-cognitive. Aside from this criterion, Deaton and Stone report that the evaluative measure, i.e., happiness-as-tranquility, correlates with income even at high levels, but the hedonic measure (similar to what Easterlin finds for the time-series in rich countries) does not correlate with income after a threshold:

Hedonic questions do not require the cognitive effort required to answer evaluative questions, they refer to different aspects of experience, and they often have different correlates. For example, hedonic measures are uncorrelated with education, vary over the days of the week, improve with age, and respond to income only up to a threshold. Evaluative measures remain correlated with income even at high levels of income, are strongly correlated with education, are often U-shaped in age, and do not vary over the days of the week (Deaton and Stone 2013, 592).

Similarly, Kahneman and Deaton (2010) reach the same conclusion about the two questions and, correspondingly, the two measures when they analyze data from the Gallup-Healthways Well-Being Index (GHWBI) consisting of more than 450,000 responses of 1000 US residents surveyed in 2008 and 2009. Kahneman and Deaton find that once annual income exceeds $75,000, income has no effect on happiness if happiness is gauged as the emotional responses of people to everyday experiences influenced by health, caregiving, loneliness, divorce, and smoking. These experiences and events are at the edge of everyday life as the DMs strive and feel the emotions of trying to reach an aspired goal. While they call this measure “emotional well-being,” it confirms what is argued here—viz., that happiness-as-aspiration is constant—with the qualification that this might not be the case for people with an income below a threshold. In contrast, in response to questions about life satisfaction, usually in terms of income that is a proxy of well-being, income is a strong predictor of happiness. While they call this measure “life evaluation” as discussed above, it confirms what is maintained here: that happiness-as-tranquility is sensitive to well-being.

Moreover, Cummins et al. (2008) use a set of questions that ask participants to monitor and report fluctuations in their well-being at different intervals during a short time span. During such short periods, individuals tend to state what is on their mind as they contemplate the next decision that is part of a forward-looking chain of actions for achieving a goal. Given the contemplation of the goal in their minds, not surprisingly, one's happiness appears to be independent of current income.

Likewise, Easterlin notes the difference between the two survey questions. The hedonic question takes the form: “In general, how happy you say you are—very happy, pretty happy, or not so happy?” (Easterlin 2004, p. 26). This question measures happiness-as-aspiration since it asks people to state how they feel today. Therefore, over the life-cycle, say over a span of 50 years, the response should be the same if the person has chosen a level of aspiration that is rational. Such a response explains the time-series data. Even if the DM’s income has risen, the DM feels the same each day if asked to state what is the level of “happiness today.” People give the same answer, i.e., that they experience constant happiness irrespective of the fact that their current income has risen. This is expected because they are not reflecting on their current income. They are rather reflecting on their desired well-being and, hence, the series of acts needed to surpass the projected well-being.

In everyday life, DMs struggle and strive, while equipped with the same degree of desire and the entailed series of acts, if rational. If so, they would choose a degree of desire that is just adequate, given the variation of personality characteristics, ahead of their projected income. The DMs want the same desired well-being relative to projected income, focusing on the difference, not the absolute well-being. As part of everyday of life, DMs are desiring the same optimal degree of desire that keeps them aspiring and striving. And once reflected upon, the sheer aspiration and striving give rise to a more-or-less steady level of happiness, happiness-as-aspiration.

It is true that the amount of desire most likely changes over the course of the life-cycle of the DM. Nonetheless, the DM chooses the amount in such a way that he or she avoids the pain of excessive desire, on one hand, or the lethargy of recessive desire, on the other. It is the choice of optimal desire, rather than its absolute amount, which makes happiness-as-aspiration steady.

In contradistinction, the evaluative question takes the form: “How satisfied are you with your life as a whole—very, somewhat, so-so, not very, or not at all?” (Easterlin 2004, p. 26). This question measures happiness-as-tranquility since it asks people to state how they feel about their life-satisfaction in general. Therefore, at a point-of-time, the response depends on one’s substantive consumption afforded by their income. That is, the question engenders the cross-sectional data. The question prompts the DM to suspend his focus on desired well-being, i.e., the sense of the gap between what is desired and what is projected. This question prompts the DM to take stock of current absolute well-being, and hence abstract from occasional shocks of disasters and triumphs. Therefore, the DM would feel well-being as rising with income and, hence, happiness as rising, viz., happiness-as-tranquility.

Easterlin notes rather quickly that the two survey questions differ, but only slightly. Hence, Easterlin treats them interchangeably:

Although there are subtle differences between happiness [hedonic measure] and life satisfaction [evaluative measure], I will treat them for the present purpose as interchangeable measures of overall feelings of well-being, that is, of subjective well-being. My focus will be on what we are learning from the survey data on the causes of subjective well-being, and, based on this, what we might do as individuals to improve it (Easterlin 2004, 26).

But once Easterlin conflates the two measures, as if the subject of measurement, i.e., happiness, is a uniform metric, he stumbles onto the income-happiness paradox. This is expected since the two measures do not gauge the same subject. It is not surprising that Deaton and Stone do not find a puzzle: for them, each measure gauges a different entity, what this paper registers as the dual facet of happiness.

If we follow the Kahneman/Deaton and the Deaton/Stone route, i.e., if we avoid conflating the two survey questions à la Easterlin, we come to realize that the product of each question, happiness, differs from the other. There is no puzzle and, as Appendix 2 demonstrates, there is no need for the relative income hypothesis as well as for set point theory. Also, there is no need for Easterlin’s ad hoc theory about the out-of-control internal norm that negates any gains from the absolute-income component of happiness. Rather, as shown above, the steadiness of happiness-as-aspiration arises from the careful selection of the optimum degree of desire.

6 Linking the dual facet of happiness

We are now able to join the two kinds of transcendental utility, happiness-as-aspiration (Ha) and happiness-as-tranquility (Ht), into a single metric: happiness (H):

$$H = H\left( {H^{{\text{a}}} ,H^{{\text{t}}} } \right)$$
(5)

where H denotes happiness in toto. Happiness in toto is a compound function. It is a positive function of its elements—viz., happiness-as-aspiration (Ha) and happiness-as-tranquility (Ht). Each element is a different facet of happiness, the product of well-being once placed against its corresponding context as shown above.

Figure 2 captures the dual facet of happiness. The x-axis measures the degree of desired well-being (aspiration) as in Fig. 1. The y-axis measures happiness in toto. Let us use the absolute well-being of the poor class (W0) as the benchmark and, further, normalize it: Ht = 0. In this manner, the poor class chooses the optimal degree of desire, and the vertical distance at that point captures only Ha.

Fig. 2
figure 2

The two functions of happiness

Such Ha remains constant even when we move to middle-class well-being, i.e., when we shift the curve from W0 to W1. (We must shift the curve since Fig. 2 does not show absolute well-being along the axes.) The vertical distance between W0 to W1—and further, between W1 and the higher-class well-being at W2—expresses only the change of Ht—i.e., the response to the change of absolute well-being.

Figure 2, in short, illustrates the proposed framework for how to think of the link between well-being and happiness. Happiness is constant irrespective of the absolute level of well-being—but only so with respect to happiness-as-aspiration (Ha) indicated by the degree of desire. In contrast, happiness rises with the rise of absolute well-being—i.e., with respect to happiness-as-tranquility (Ht).

In this light, the difference between the cross-sectional and time-series data, need not be contradictory. Each is rather measuring a different facet of happiness. The cross-sectional data expresses the happiness-as-tranquility (Ht). This is the focus of the stylized economist. In contrast, the time-series data expresses the happiness-as-aspiration (Ha). This is the focus of the stylized psychologist.

7 Conclusion

This paper starts with the Easterlin paradox. The paradox, better called the “income-happiness paradox”, highlights a contradiction in the data that links happiness with income. While one set of data finds that happiness rises with the rise of income irrespective of how prosperous the country under focus is, the other set of data finds that happiness ceases to rise with the rise of income once a country reaches a threshold level of prosperity.

“Appendix 1” discusses the paradox in detail, while “Appendix 2” explains why the offered solutions of the paradox suffer from different shortcomings. This paper starts afresh and proposes a solution of the paradox that avoids such shortcomings. This paper shows that each data set uncovers a different facet of happiness as the data is based on a different question.

When the question is about the assessment of well-being in general, the respondents reflect on their current well-being vis-à-vis a well-being in the past that is better imagined to be worse than the current well-being. This imagined well-being of the past acts as the context, and if the decision maker manages to imagine it to be worse than the current one, the experienced happiness would be tranquility. The happiness-as-tranquility expresses the decision maker’s contentment with current well-being. Thus, happiness-as-tranquility rises with income as such income is compared to the distant income in the past.

In contrast, when the question is about the assessment of well-being at the moment, the respondents reflect on their current well-being vis-à-vis a well-being in the future. At each moment, the decision maker is making plans for the week or the month to achieve a goal. Naturally, there is a gap between the current state and the aspired goal. Given that people maintain an optimal gap, which they can do once a country is prosperous, the expressed happiness is steady. Such steady happiness, happiness-as-aspiration, does not tend to rise with the rise of income.

In short, the contradiction between the two data sets is no contradiction. Each data set reveals a different facet of happiness, depending on whether the question prompts the decision maker to reflect on well-being within the context of forward-looking as opposed to backward-looking well-being.

Further research is needed to investigate other facets of happiness that arise from other kinds of context. As this paper mentions, bonding that characterizes familial and friendship relations contributes to happiness—but is ignored in this paper. Hope also contributes to happiness—but is ignored in this paper. For solving the income-happiness paradox, it is sufficient to focus on the identified dual facet of happiness, i.e., happiness-as-aspiration and happiness-as-tranquility.