Skip to main content
Log in

The role of persuasion in cultural evolution dynamics

  • Research Article
  • Published:
International Review of Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We analyze the evolution of a society in which types evolve not only depending on how much they are fit but also on how much they are able to persuade others about their fitness. This mechanism makes possible to reach equilibria not feasible under standard dynamics. We first provide necessary conditions for a generic matrix and generic class of cultural competition mechanisms in order to observe polymorphic equilibria, comparing it with the standard case. Then, necessary and sufficient conditions for polymorphic equilibrium stability are provided in the case of particular competition rule family, at each competition level. We show that some social dilemmas as prisoner’s dilemma or stag hunt can have their dynamics dramatically changed. We then analyze the prisoner’s dilemma framework finding that also full cooperation is sustainable in equilibrium. Finally we show that this persuasion mechanisms generally increase the equilibrium aggregate production of the society.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There had been one prominent case of cultural evolution literature based not on a form of explicit persuasion, but on genetic inheritance, that is Memetics. It is interesting to note that this literature reached a dead-end since, without an active persuasion process, it fails in explaining cultural evolution phenomena.

  2. Cultural transmission theories have also been applied to evolutionary game-theoretic frameworks analyzing how long-run equilibria may be affected by the intergenerational transmission of preferences. This is the case of Gintis (2003), Bisin et al. (2004), Mengel (2008), Calabuig and Olcina (2009) and Tabellini (2008): These contributions model cultural evolution as an intergenerational process through which preferences for cooperation are transmitted from one generation to the other by an indirect evolutionary process, considering this as the main way by which traits are acquired. In this paper we use a different approach not relying on indirect evolution and relying on intragenerational rather than intergenerational transmission.

  3. In particular we can build a model in which at each period t a share \(\lambda\) of agents are matched to perform the task and a share \(1-\lambda\) evaluates the performance and imitate according to this judgment. The analysis of the equilibria and their stability properties does not change.

  4. In the interpretation without the third parties, these priors are also the priors agents have about own and other’s contribution to the matching.

  5. I thank a referee for having pointed this out.

  6. I thank a referee for having clarified this out.

  7. The analysis that follows can be performed with any other set of values \(\beta >\gamma\) different from 1 and 0 without changing the quality of the results. We use these values in order to have a more tractable analysis.

  8. A similar reasoning holds even if \(\gamma >0\). In this case, when \(z=1\) C agents have an incentive to produce a positive effort. Thus, depending on the parameter, it can happen that the C agents’ effort curve is non-monotone with respect to z. However, it always happens that \(\tau ^{NC^*}\ge \tau ^{C^*}\). The qualitative shape of the matching total productivity is not affected.

References

  • Binmore K (2006) Why do people cooperate? Polit Philos Econ 5(1):81–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bisin A, Topa G, Verdier T (2004) Cooperation as a transmitted cultural trait. Ration Soc 16:477–507

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bisin A, Verdier T (2001) The economics of cultural transmission and the dynamics of preferences. J Econ Theory 97(2):298–319

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowles S (1998) Endogenous preferences: the cultural consequences of markets and other economic institutions. J Econ Lit 36:75–111

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Richerson PJ (1985) Culture and the evolutionary process. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Richerson PJ (2005) The origin and evolution of cultures. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruni L (2008) Reciprocity, altruism and civil society. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bruni L, Panebianco F, Smerilli A (2014) Beyond carrot and sticks: how cooperation and its rewards evolve together. Rev Soc Econ 72(1):55–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calabuig V, Olcina G (2009) Cooperation and cultural transmission in a coordination game. J Econ Behav Organ 72(1):188–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavalli-Sforza L, Feldman M (1973) Cultural versus biological inheritance: phenotypic transmission from parents to children. Am J Hum Genet 25:618–637

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavalli-Sforza L, Feldman M (1981) Cultural transmission and evolution: a quantitative approach. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Cordes C, Richerson P, McElreath R, Strimiling P (2008) A naturalistic approach to the theory of the firm: the role of cooperation and cultural evolution. J Econ Behav Organ 68(1):125–139

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordes C, Richerson P, Schwesinger G (2010) How corporate cultures coevolve with the business environment: the case of firm growth crises and industry evolution. J Econ Behav Organ 76(3):465–480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durham WH (1991) Coevolution: genes, culture, and human diversity. Stanford University Press, Redwood City

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellingsen T, Robles J (2002) Does evolution solve the hold up problem?. Games Econ Behav 39(1):28–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Fischbacher U (2002) Why social preferences matter the impact of non-selfish motives on competition, cooperation and incentives. Econ J 112:C1–C33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Fischbacher U (2004) Social norms and human cooperation. Trends Cogn Sci 8:185–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garfinkel MR, Skaperdas S (2007) Economics of conflict: an overview. In: Sandler T, Hartley K (eds) Handbook of defense economics, vol II

  • Gintis H (2003) Solving the puzzle of prosociality. Ration Soc 15:155–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gintis H, Bowles S, Boyd R, Fehr E (2005) Moral sentiments and material interests. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Guiso L, Sapienza P, Zingales L (2006) Does culture affect economic outcomes? J Econ Perspect 20(2):23–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mengel F (2008) Matching structure and the cultural transmission of social norms. J Econ Behav Organ 67:608–623

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak M (2006) Five rules for the evolution of cooperation. Science 314:1560–1563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olcina G, Penyarrubia C (2002) Specific investments and coordination failures. Econ Bull 3

  • Sugden R (2004) The economics of rights, cooperation and welfare, 2nd edn. Palgrave Macmillian, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Tabellini G (2008) The scope of cooperation: values and incentives. Q J Econ 123(3):905–950

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weibull J (1997) Evolutionary game theory. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This study has been partially funded by ERC 324004 Grant TECTACOM—The economics of Cultural Transmission and Applications to Communities, Organizations and Markets and the Spanish Ministry of Economia y Competitividad under Grant [ECO-2014-58297-R].

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fabrizio Panebianco.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that he does not have any conflict of interest.

Additional information

I am very grateful to Luigino Bruni, Sergio Currarini, Pierluigi Sacco, Alessandra Smerilli and Luca Stanca for their comments. All errors are mine.

Appendices

Appendix 1: Proofs of Propositions

1.1 Proof of Lemma 1

Consider a heterogeneous matching ij with \(i\in \{A\}\) and \(j\in \{B\}\). Then \(\pi _t^{ij}=\beta q_t^{ij}(\bar{\tau }_t)+\gamma (1-q_t^{ji}(\bar{\tau }_t))-c(\tau _t^{i})\), with \(\beta q_t^{ij}(\bar{\tau }_t)+\gamma (1-q_t^{ji}(\bar{\tau }_t))\) being the utility of playing a given \(\tau _t^{i}\) and \(c(\tau _t^{i})\) being the cost. Call \(MU(\tau _t^{i})\) the marginal utility of playing \(\tau _t^i\). Since Assumption 2a holds, then \(MU(\tau _t^{i})\ge 0, \forall \tau _t^{i}>0\) and is monotonic in \(\tau _t^{i}\). Thus if \(c^{\prime }(\tau _t^{i})|_{\tau _t^{i}=0}=0\) and \(c^{\prime }(\tau _t^{i})|_{\tau _t^{i}=1}>(\beta \frac{\partial q_t^{ij}(\bar{\tau }_t)}{\partial \tau _t^{i}}-\gamma \frac{\partial q_t^{ji}(\bar{\tau }_t)}{\partial \tau _t^{i}})|_{\tau _t^{i}=0}\), as Assumption 1 requires, then there exist a unique optimal \(\tau _t^{i*}\), and \(\tau _t^{i*}\in (0,1)\). The same proof holds for \(\tau _t^{j*}\) so that it is also unique and \(\tau _t^{j*}\in (0,1)\).

1.2 Proof of Proposition 1

Consider the first part of the proposition. Suppose that Assumption 2b holds so that \(\bar{q}_t\) is independent from \(p_t\). Given the set of Eq. 1, then also \(\pi _t^{ij}\) is independent from \(p_t\), \(\forall i\ne j\). Consider now the dynamics in Eq. 3. A polymorphic equilibrium exists if and only if there exists a \(p^*\) such that \(\pi ^A=\pi ^B\). Reminding that \(\pi ^A\) and \(\pi ^B\) are averages payoffs defined in the set of Eq. 2, then this happen whenever \(p\alpha +(1-p)\pi _t^{AB}-p\pi _t^{BA}-(1-p)\delta =0\). Since this is linear in p, then there exists at most one \(p^*\) such that this condition is satisfied. Thus, if it exists, the polymorphic equilibrium is unique.

Consider now the second part of the proposition. Since there exists at most one polymorphic equilibrium, then a necessary and sufficient condition for its existence is that the points \(p=0\) and \(p=1\) are unstable. Call \(\Delta _t\equiv \pi _t^{A}-\pi _t^{B}\), then instability conditions of the extreme points can be rewritten as \(\Delta _t|_{p=0}>0\) and \(\Delta _t|_{p=1}<0\). Given (3) we have that \(\Delta _t|_{p=0}=\beta q_t^{AB}+\gamma (1-q_t^{BA})-c(\tau _t^{A})-\delta\) and \(\Delta _t|_{p=1}=\alpha -\beta (1-q_t^{A})-\gamma q_t^{B}+c(\tau _t^{B})\).

A necessary condition for \(\Delta _t|_{p=0}>0\) is that \(c(\tau _t^{A})<\beta q_t^{AB}+\gamma -\gamma q_t^{BA}-\delta\). Since \(c(\tau _t^{A})>0\), in order to have this it is necessary that \(q_t^{BA}<\frac{\beta q_t^{AB}+\gamma -\delta }{\gamma }\) that, since \(q_t^{BA}\in [0,1]\), can be true only if \(\frac{\beta q_t^{AB}+\gamma -\delta }{\gamma }>0\). This happens when \(q_t^{AB}>\frac{\delta -\gamma }{\beta }\) that, since \(q_t^{AB}\in [0,1]\), it is satisfied only if \(\frac{\delta -\gamma }{\beta }<1\) and thus \(\beta +\gamma >\delta\).

Using the same reasoning, take \(\Delta _t|_{p=0}<0\): This is satisfied when \(c(\tau _t^{B})<\gamma q_t^{BA}-\alpha +\beta -\beta q_t^{AB}\). Since \(c(\tau _t^{B})>0\), the previous condition is satisfied only if \(\gamma q_t^{BA}-\alpha +\beta -\beta q_t^{AB}>0\). This happens when \(q_t^{AB}<\frac{\gamma q_t^{BA}-\alpha +\beta }{\beta }\) that, since \(q_t^{AB}\in [0,1]\), it holds only if \(\frac{\gamma q_t^{BA}-\alpha +\beta }{\beta }>0\), that is to say \(q_t^{BA}>\frac{\alpha -\beta }{\gamma }\). Since \(q_t^{BA}\in [0,1],\) then this happens only if \(\frac{\alpha -\beta }{\gamma }<1\) so that only if \(\beta +\gamma >\alpha\).

1.3 Proof of Proposition 2

Consider the problem each agent faces. Using Mathematica software, by substituting the q-Rule equations into \(\pi _t^{AB}\) and \(\pi _t^{BA}\) and solving the first-order conditions we get

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{l} \tau _t^{A^*}=\frac{2\beta ^2(z-1)^2+\gamma (1-z)(2-z\gamma )+\beta (5z-3z^2-2)}{2(1+(\beta -\gamma )^2(z-1)^2)}\\ \tau _t^{B^*}=\frac{\beta ^2(z-1)z+\gamma (z+2\gamma (z-1)^2)+\beta (1-z)(2-2\gamma +3z\gamma )}{2(1+(\beta -\gamma )^2(z-1)^2)}\\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
(4)

Substituting now these values into \(\pi _t^A\) and \(\pi _t^B,\) we are able to compute \(\Delta _t=\pi _t^A-\pi _t^B\). We thus have that \(p=0\) is unstable if and only if \(\Delta _t|_{p_t=0}>0\) and \(p=1\) is unstable if and only if \(\Delta _t|_{p_t=1}<0\). By solving \(\Delta _t|_{p_t=0}=0\) with respect to \(\delta,\) we obtain \(\bar{\delta }\) and by solving \(\Delta _t|_{p_t=1}=0\) by \(\alpha\) we obtain \(\bar{\alpha }\). What remains is then to check that \(\bar{\delta }\in (0,1)\) and \(\bar{\alpha }\in (0,1)\).

1.4 Proof of Proposition 3

This proposition is proved just by substituting in \(\bar{\delta }\) and \(\bar{\alpha }\) the values of \(\beta =1\) and \(\gamma =0\) and noting that \(\bar{\delta }>\bar{\alpha }\) so that all 4 areas are feasible in the space \((\alpha , \delta )\in (0,1)^2\) with \(\alpha <\delta\).

1.5 Proof of Proposition 4

Suppose first that the third party is considering the possibility of lowering the competition, so that z becomes higher. We now analyze how this change in z affects \(\bar{\alpha }\), \(\bar{\delta }\) and the stability properties of equilibria. Now, if \(p=1\) is an unstable outcome, an increase in z does not change stability properties of this point. In order to see this, notice, with the help of Fig. 3, that an increase from z to \(z^{\prime }\) makes \(\bar{\alpha }(z)<\bar{\alpha }(z^{\prime })\) so that if \(\alpha <\bar{\alpha }(z)\) then it is also \(\alpha <\bar{\alpha }(z^{\prime })\). In this way \(p=1\) is unstable under \(z^{\prime }\). Following the same reasoning, if \(p=1\) is a stable outcome an increase from z to \(z^{\prime }\) may make \(p=1\) to become unstable since in this case it can happen that \(\alpha >\bar{\alpha }(z^{\prime })\). Consider now the point \(p=0\). Now, if \(z>\bar{z}\) and \(p=0\) is unstable, an increase in z can make it stable, while if \(p=0\) is stable nothing changes. In fact, in the first case since \(\bar{\delta }\) is decreasing in z, it can happen that \(\delta <\bar{\delta }(z)\) but \(\delta >\bar{\delta }(z^{\prime })\); in the second case if \(\delta >\bar{\delta }(z)\) it has to be valid that \(\delta >\bar{\delta }(z^{\prime })\). Differently from these cases, by applying the same properties, if \(z<\bar{z}\) and \(p=0\) is unstable, then an increase in z does not change the stability properties of the point while if \(p=0\) is stable an increase in z can make it unstable. Thus, if competition level is low enough (\(z>\bar{z}\)), then lowering it may have a positive effect on the presence of C agents in the long run, while if \(z<\bar{z}\) this policy may induce instability in both extreme points. Consider now the case for an increase in competition level from z to \(z^{\prime \prime }\). If \(p=1\) is stable, then this policy does not change the stability property of the point, while if \(p=1\) is unstable it may make it stable. Consider now \(p=0\). If \(z>\bar{z}\) and \(p=0\) is stable, then a decrease in z can make it unstable, while nothing changes in the case in which \(p=0\) is unstable. On the contrary if \(z<\bar{z}\) and \(p=0\) is stable, then a decrease in z has no effect while if \(p=0\) is unstable it may make it stable. Thus we can summarize by saying that if competition is low such that \(z>\bar{z}\) making competition higher does not decrease the long-run presence of NC agents in the society, while augmenting it may induce stability in the extreme points. All these results can be summed up in the following statement.

Appendix 2: Areas extensions

We now provide the formulas for the extensions of the 4 areas of Fig. 1 if a PD-like matrix occurs. Notice first that since \(\bar{\delta }>\bar{\alpha }\) , then as stated by Proposition 3 all 4 areas are feasible. We define \(\Delta i\equiv \frac{\partial Areai}{\partial z}\) \(\forall i\in \{I, II, III, IV\}\), \(D\bar{\alpha }\equiv \frac{\partial \bar{\alpha }}{\partial z}\) and \(D\bar{\delta }\equiv \frac{\partial \bar{\delta }}{\partial z}\). Now,

  • Area I: The extension of area I is given by \(\bar{\alpha }(1-\bar{\delta })\) so that \(\Delta I=(1-\bar{\delta })D\bar{\alpha }-\bar{\alpha }D\bar{\delta }\)

  • Area II: The extension of area II is given by \(\frac{[(1-\bar{\alpha })+(\bar{\delta -\bar{\alpha }})](1-\bar{\delta })}{2}\) so that \(\Delta {II}=\bar{\alpha }D\bar{\delta }+\bar{\delta }D\bar{\alpha }-\delta D\bar{\delta }-D\bar{\alpha }\)

  • Area III: The extension of area III is given by \(\frac{(\bar{\delta }-\bar{\alpha })^2}{2}\) so that \(\Delta III=(\bar{\delta }-\bar{\alpha })(D\bar{\alpha }-D\bar{\delta })\)

  • Area IV: The extension of area IV is given by \(\frac{[\bar{\delta }+(\bar{\delta }-\bar{\alpha })]\bar{\alpha }}{2}\) so that \(\Delta IV=\bar{\alpha }D\bar{\delta }+\bar{\delta }D\bar{\alpha }-\bar{\alpha }D\bar{\alpha }\)

Substituting the threshold values and their first derivatives, then Fig. 4 is produced.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Panebianco, F. The role of persuasion in cultural evolution dynamics. Int Rev Econ 63, 233–258 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12232-016-0253-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12232-016-0253-4

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation