Skip to main content
Log in

The public economics of self control

  • Published:
Journal of Economics and Finance Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper analyzes self-control problems in intertemporal consumption of a sin good where current consumption imposes a negative externality on one’s future selves due to the existence of present-biased preferences. We introduce the negative externality dubbed ‘internality’, which is augmented by the cumulative distribution function of the sum of previous consumption. We show that the shot-run self with self-control problem over consumes the sin good compared to that of the long-run self without present-biased preferences. Further, we investigate the effectiveness of self-bargaining with the presence of an external control devise as possible punishment. The short-run self faces three possible options: do nothing, accept the long-run self’s offer, or reject the offer. In the latter case an external control devices is implemented. It is shown that successful self-bargaining depends on the efficiency of the control device.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are many variants of paternalism: patronizing paternalism (Burrows 1993), libertarian paternalism (Sunstein and Thaler 2003), permissible paternalism (Goodin 1991), benign paternalism (Choi et al. 2003), and asymmetric paternalism (Camerer et al. 2003). For a survey of the literature see Ott (2007). “State Paternalism and Rules of Reason”, presented at the 64th International Atlantic Economic Conference in Savannah, Georgia, October 2007.

  2. This is the standard form as proposed by Laibson (1997).

  3. Given the cost of implementing the external control device e, we define two critical types of LR-2 in terms of his/her reduction of consumption denoted by ξ. There is LR-2 self who is indifferent between doing nothing and making a rejectable offer, this is denoted as the ‘credible-threat threshold’ \(\ifmmode\expandafter\bar\else\expandafter\=\fi{\Delta }^{{LR - 2}} \) where

    $$\underline \Delta ^{{\text{LR}} - 2} \equiv \alpha \ln x_2^{{\text{SR}} * } - \alpha \ln \left( {x_2^{{\text{SR}} * } - \xi } \right) + c\delta \left[ {F\left( {x_1 + x_2^{{\text{SR*}}} - \xi } \right) - F\left( {x_1 + x_2^{{\text{SR}} * } } \right)} \right].$$

    Also, we define the ‘acceptable-offer threshold’, \(\bar \Delta ^{{\text{LR}} - 2} \) in which LR-t self is indifferent between making an acceptable offer and making a rejectable offer:

    $$\overline \Delta ^{{\text{LR}} - 2} \equiv \alpha \ln x_2^A - \alpha \ln \left( {x_2^{{\text{SR}} * } - \xi } \right) + c\delta \left[ {F\left( {x_1 + x_2^{{\text{SR}} * } - \xi } \right) - F\left( {x_1 + x_2^A } \right)} \right].$$
  4. Given the efficiency of the external control device, we define two critical types of SR-2 self in terms of the reduction in consumption level. There is SR-2 self who is indifferent between accepting the offer and rejecting the offer is denoted by the ‘acceptance threshold’, \(\overline \Delta ^{SR - 2} \) where

    $$\overline \Delta ^{SR - 2} \equiv \alpha \ln x_2^A - \alpha \ln \left( {x_2^{SR * } - \xi } \right) + \left( {x_2^{SR * } - x_2^A } \right) + c\beta \delta \left[ {F\left( {x_1 + x_2^{SR * } - \xi } \right) - F\left( {x_1 + x_2^A } \right)} \right].$$

    Also, we define the ‘reject threshold’ as \(\underline \Delta ^{SR - 2} \) in which SR-2 self is indifferent between to doing nothing and rejecting the offer:

    $$\underline \Delta ^{SR - 2} \equiv \alpha \ln x_2^{SR * } - \alpha \ln \left( {x_2^{SR * } - \xi } \right) + c\beta \delta \left[ {F\left( {x_1 + x_2^{SR * } - \xi } \right) - F\left( {x_1 + x_2^{SR * } } \right)} \right].$$

References

  • Buchanan J (1975) The Samaritan’s dilemma. In: Phelps E (ed) Altruism morality, and economic theory. New York, Russell Sage Foundation, pp 71–85

  • Buchanan J, Tullock G (1965) The calculus of consent: logical foundations of constitutional democracy. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, MI

    Google Scholar 

  • Burrows P (1993) Patronizing paternalism. Oxf Econ Pap 45:542–572

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer C, Issacharoff S, Lowenstein G, O’Donoghue T, Rabin M (2003) Regulation for conservatives: behavioral economics and the case for ‘Assymetric Paternalism’. Univ PA Law Rev 151:1211–1254

    Google Scholar 

  • Choi J, Laibson D, Madrian B, Metrick A (2003) Benign paternalism and active decision: a natural experiment in saving. Mimeo. Harvard University, Boston, MA

  • Fudenberg D, Levine DK (2006) A dual-self model of impulse control. Am Econ Rev 96(5):1449–1476

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin R (1991) Permissible paternalism: in defense of the Nanny State. Responsive Community 1:42–51

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrnstein R, Loewenstein G, Prelec D, Vaughan W (1993) Utility maximization and melioration: Internalities in individual choice. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 6(3):149–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laibson D (1997) Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. Q J Econ 112(2):449–477

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill J (1859) On Liberty. New York; The Liberal Arts Press; Reprint 1984

  • Musgrave, R (1959) The theory of public finance: a study in public economics. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donoghue T, Rabin M (1999) Incentives for procrastinators. Q J Econ 114:769–816

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donoghue T, Rabin M (2003) Studying optimal paternalism, illustrated by a model of sin taxes. Am Econ Rev Papers Proceedings 93(2):186–191

    Google Scholar 

  • Ott A (2007) State paternalism and rules of reason. A conference paper presented at The Atlantic Economic Society meeting, October 7-11, 2007, Savannah, GA

  • Schelling T (1978) Egonomics, or the art of self-management. Am Econ Rev 68(2):290–294

    Google Scholar 

  • Schelling T (1960) The strategy of conflict. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (1759) The theory of moral sentiments. Millar, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein C, Thaler R (2003) Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron. Univ Chic Law Rev 70(4):1159–1201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler R, Shefrin H (1981) An economic theory of self-control. J Polit Econ 89(2):392–406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler R, Sunstein C (2003) Libertarian paternalism. Am Econ Rev 93(2):175–179

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitman G (2006) Against the new paternalism, internalities and the economics of self-control. Policy Analysis CATO Institute 563:1–16

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Attiat F. Ott.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bae, S.H., Ott, A.F. The public economics of self control. J Econ Finance 32, 356–367 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12197-008-9047-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12197-008-9047-1

Keywords

JEL

Navigation