Skip to main content
Log in

What (if anything) morally separates environmental from neurochemical behavioral interventions?

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Drawing from the literatures on the ethics of nudging and moral bioenhancement, I elaborate several pairs of cases in which one intervention is classified as an environmental behavioral intervention (EBI) and the other as a neurochemical behavioral intervention (NBI) in order to morally compare them. The intuition held by most is that NBIs are by far the more morally troubling kind of influence. However, if this intuition cannot be vindicated, we should at least entertain the Similarity Thesis, according to which EBIs and NBIs share relevant moral features to the extent that moral conclusions about one are implied about the other in the described pairs of cases. I test this thesis by putting forward a number of possible moral grounds for setting EBIs and NBIs apart, including three of the most promising ones – physical invasiveness, disclosure and avoidance, and inevitability. I conclude that although these promising grounds might not bear the full burden of vindicating the intuition against Similarity by themselves, clustering them together can establish discernible moral separation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The Cafeteria B example is adopted from Douglas [6].

  2. See Gelfand [8] for a similar comparison.

  3. See also Schaefer’s claim that the greater efficiency of NBIs compared to EBIs is owed to their greater capacity to “isolate particular psychological functions” [33].

  4. Similarity should be distinguished from Levy’s parity principle [34], which states that the moral permissibility of these interventions should only be assessed in terms of their costs and benefits, and not their natures. On the Similarity Thesis, the natures of interventions are not ignored; the moral permissibility of both EBIs and NBIs should still be determined not only on the basis of outcomes, but also on the basis of the kinds of interventions that they are. Similarity only asserts that their natures are morally indistinguishable and warrant the same conclusions about their permissibility.

  5. Note that we might reach different conclusions about different pairs of EBIs and NBIs in the examples, either because of the goal that they promote or because the particular EBIs (and/or NBIs) are morally dissimilar between themselves. I will point out explicitly in what follows when a particular distinguishing feature is more significant for some pair of cases than for another.

  6. However, the use of the intend/foresee distinction in characterizing NBIs’ effects could also be contested here, e.g., by noting that the physical interference seems constitutive to the intended effect, rather than an unintended side-effect [38].

  7. See more about the mere substitution of influence in Section "Inevitability".

  8. Alternatively, one might argue that the vanilla aroma is an NBI, not an EBI, but that comes at the cost of the distinctions between EBIs and NBIs on the one hand, and between direct and indirect interferences on the other, becoming seriously disjointed. More about the latter distinction in the next section.

  9. Note that the distinction between direct and indirect interventions doesn’t always fit neatly with the distinction between EBIs and NBIs. For instance, if subliminal effects were used to garner sympathy among targeted individuals for some pro-social cause (see [40]), then such influences would not involve any neurochemical effects on the brain, and would thus more likely be classified as EBIs, yet they would, in Bublitz and Merkel’s words, only be using “peripheral routes of perception” [4] and would arguably not be mediated via perception as most other EBIs. Still, the two distinctions will fit each other neatly in most other cases.

  10. In a hypothetical example, Coons and Weber say that if we were forcibly injected with a love potion that has its standard imaginary effects, and we were told about this beforehand, disclosure would only make things worse for our agency as we would witness ourselves succumbing to its effects [42]. Intuitively at least, the love potion seems more analogous to NBIs than to EBIs. This is not to suggest that NBIs hijack agency in the same way as the love potion. However, agents might similarly witness their mental states being affected before coming to resist the NBI.

  11. One piece of empirical evidence seems to suggest that nudges need not lose their potency even if made transparent; namely, informing people that their choices regarding advanced directives are affected by defaults does not deter them from accepting the direction of the nudge [43]. Some might suggest that this means nudges still work even when disclosed. Two points should be made on this matter. First, it isn’t clear that, following disclosure, the default in the study still works as a heuristic trigger, since those exposed to the default may have simply become aware of the reason behind it and have consciously endorsed it. In other words, it isn’t clear whether behavior is still changed as a consequence of the behavioral technique being employed [44]. Second, it’s not clear that what the study shows can be extended to other cases of triggering heuristics.

  12. We should also be cautious about my assumptions regarding NBIs. Conceivably, their influence could be so mild that we hardly notice ourselves being affected before resisting them. But I want to retain the understanding that, as direct interventions, NBIs will produce some change in mental states before it can be resisted, slight as it may be.

  13. A similar strategy for the utilization of nudges is advocated in Ivanković and Engelen [44].

  14. Of course, this distinguishing feature may be more applicable to our current technological context. New technological solutions may narrow the gap between EBIs and NBIs in terms of the costs and reliability of tracking particular influences.

  15. Similar appeals to inevitability can be found in Sunstein [52, 53], Cohen [54], Brooks [55], and Engelen et al. [56].

  16. However, a more sophisticated, and, in my mind, quite convincing version of the inevitability argument, which states that there is little, if any moral difference between actively changing environments and allowing them to take effect when all likely outcomes are reliably predictable to the choice architect, is offered by Blumenthal-Barby [59, emphasis in original]: “once behavioral science helps us gain insight into how choice is affected, intentionality is forced, in a sense. It becomes increasingly difficult for us to maintain that we did not know how various factors in the choice architecture would impact […] choice. […] Given that we then have to make a decision about how to set things up, we are forced to engage in nudging or shaping choice one way or the other”.

  17. I thank Tom Douglas for putting this example forward in correspondence. Note that, as in the case of Cafeteria A, the decision-maker would be acting blameworthy if her choice of ventilation system was predictably harmful to the inhabitants, e.g., by making them docile. I thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this concern.

  18. More specifically, for a criticism about the impracticability of SSRIs as a means of moral bioenhancement, see Wiseman [62].

References

  1. Bleicher, S. 2005. Contemporary color: Theory and use. Clifton Park: Thomson/Delmar Learning.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Berman, M. 2007. Street-smart advertising: How to win the battle of the buzz. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Wren, A.M., L.J. Seal, M.A. Cohen, A.E. Brynes, G.S. Frost, K.G. Murphy, W.S. Dhillo, and S.R. Bloom. 2001. Ghrelin enhances appetite and increases food intake in humans. The Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism 86 (12): 5992–5995. https://doi.org/10.1210/jcem.86.12.8111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Bublitz, J., and R. Merkel. 2014. Crimes against minds: On mental manipulations, harms and a human right to mental self-determination. Criminal Law and Philosophy 8 (1): 51–77. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-012-9172-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Marcano-Olivier, M., Pearson, R., Ruparell, A., Horne, O.J., Viktor, S., Erjavec, M. 2019. A low-cost Behavioural Nudge and choice architecture intervention targeting school lunches increases children’s consumption of fruit: a cluster randomized trial. International Journal of Behavioral Nutrition and Physical Activity 16. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12966-019-0773-x.

  6. Douglas, T. 2022. The mere substitution defence of nudging works for neurointerventions too. Journal of Applied Philosophy 39 (3): 407–420. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Rehman, S.U., P.J. Nietert, D.W. Cope, and A.O. Kilpatrick. 2005. What to wear today? Effect of doctor’s attire on the trust and confidence of patients. American Journal of Medicine 118 (11): 1279–1286. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.amjmed.2005.04.026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Gelfand, S.D. 2016. The meta-nudge – a response to the claim that the use of nudges during the informed consent process is unavoidable. Bioethics 30 (8): 601–608. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Helbich, M., D. de Beurs, M.-P. Kwan, R.C. O’Connor, and P.P. Groenewegen. 2018. Natural environments and suicide mortality in the Netherlands: A cross-sectional, ecological study. Lancet Planetary Health 2 (3): 134–139. https://doi.org/10.1016/S2542-5196(18)30033-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Schrauzer, G.N., and K.P. Shrestha. 1990. Lithium in drinking water and the incidences of crimes, suicides, and arrests related to drug addictions. Biological Trace Element Research 25 (2): 105–113. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02990271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Vita, A., L. De Peri, and E. Sacchetti. 2015. Lithium in drinking water and suicide prevention: A review of the evidence. International Clinical Psychopharmacology 30 (1): 1–5. https://doi.org/10.1097/YIC.0000000000000048.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Thaler, R.H., and C.R. Sunstein. 2008. Nudge: Improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gilovich, T., D. Griffin, and D. Kahneman, eds. 2002. Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  14. Sunstein, C.R. 2014. Why nudge? The politics of libertarian paternalism. New Haven & London: Yale University Press.

  15. Krishnamurthy, M. 2015. Nudging global poverty alleviation? The Law & Ethics of Human Rights 9 (2): 249–264. https://doi.org/10.1515/lehr-2015-0008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Beraldo, S., and J. Karpus. 2021. Nudging to donate organs: Do what you like or like what we do? Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 24 (3): 329–340. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-021-10007-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Moles, A. 2015. Nudging for liberals. Social Theory and Practice 41 (4): 644–667. https://doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract201541435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Grüne-Yanoff, T. 2012. Old wine in new casks: Libertarian paternalism still violates liberal principles. Social Choice and Welfare 38 (4): 635–645. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-011-0636-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Rozeboom, G. 2020. Nudging for rationality and self-governance. Ethics 131 (1): 107–121. https://doi.org/10.1086/709986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Kosfeld, M., M. Heinrichs, P.J. Zak, U. Fischbacher, and E. Fehr. 2005. Oxytocin increases trust in humans. Nature 435 (7042): 673–676. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature03701.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Zak, P.J., R. Kurzban, and W.T. Matzner. 2004. The neurobiology of trust. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1032: 224–227. https://doi.org/10.1196/annals.1314.025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Tse, W.S., and A.J. Bond. 2002. Serotonergic intervention affects both social dominance and affiliative behaviour. Psychopharmacology 161 (3): 324–330. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00213-002-1049-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Douglas, T. 2015. The morality of moral neuroenhancement. In Handbook of neuroethics, ed. J. Clausen and N. Levy, 1227–1249. Dordrecht: Springer.

  24. Persson, I., and J. Savulescu. 2012. Unfit for the future: The need for moral enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  25. Crutchfield, P. 2019. Compulsory moral bioenhancement should be covert. Bioethics 33 (1): 112–121. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Harris, J. 2011. Moral enhancement and freedom. Bioethics 25 (2): 102–111. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8519.2010.01854.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Rakić, V. 2014. Voluntary moral enhancement and the survival-at-any-cost bias. Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (4): 246–250. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2012-100700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Fischer, J.M., and M. Ravizza. 1998. Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  29. Pettit, P. 1997. Republicanism: A theory of freedom and government. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Sparrow, R. 2014. Better living through chemistry? A reply to Savulescu and Persson on “moral enhancement.” Journal of Applied Philosophy 31 (1): 23–32. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12038.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Selinger, E., and K.P. Whyte. 2012. Nudging cannot solve complex policy problems. European Journal of Risk Regulation 3 (1): 26–31. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1867299X0000177X.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. John, P., G. Smith, and G. Stoker. 2009. Nudge nudge, think think: Two strategies for changing civic behaviour. The Political Quarterly 80 (3): 361–370. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-923X.2009.02001.x.

  33. Schaefer, G.O. 2015. Direct vs. indirect moral enhancement. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 25 (3): 261–289. https://doi.org/10.1353/ken.2015.0016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Levy, N. 2007. Neuroethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  35. Douglas, T. 2018. Neural and environmental modulation of motivation: what’s the moral difference? In Treatment for crime: Philosophical essays on neurointerventions in criminal justice, ed. D. Birks and T. Douglas, 208–223. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  36. Douglas, T. 2022. If nudges treat their targets as rational agents, nonconsensual neurointerventions can too. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 25 (3): 369–384. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-022-10285-w.

  37. Pugh, J. 2019. Moral bio-enhancement, freedom, value and the parity principle. Topoi 38 (1): 73–86. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9482-8.

  38. Fitzpatrick, W. 2006. The intend/foresee distinction and the problem of “closeness.” Philosophical Studies 128 (3): 585–617. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-004-7824-z.

  39. Morrison, M., S. Gan, C. Dubelaar, and H. Oppewal. 2011. In-store music and aroma influences on shopper behavior and satisfaction. Journal of Business Research 64 (6): 558–564. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jbusres.2010.06.006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Douglas, T. 2013. Moral enhancement via direct emotion modulation: A reply to John Harris. Bioethics 27 (3): 160–168. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8519.2011.01919.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Bovens, L. 2009. The ethics of nudge. In Preference change: Approaches from philosophy, economics and psychology, ed. T. Grüne-Yanoff and S.O. Hansson, 207–219. Berlin & New Yor: Springer.

  42. Coons, C., and M. Weber. 2013. Introduction: Paternalism – issues and trends. In Paternalism: Theory and practice, ed. C. Coons and M. Weber, 1–24. New York: Cambridge University Press.

  43. Loewenstein, G., C. Bryce, D. Hagmann, and S. Rajpal. 2015. Warning: You are about to be nudged. Behavioral Science and Policy 1: 35–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Ivanković, V., and B. Engelen. 2019. Nudging, transparency, and watchfulness. Social Theory and Practice 45 (1): 43–73. https://doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract20191751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Miller, P.M., and N.S. Fagley. 1991. The effects of framing, problem variations, and providing rationale on choice. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 17 (5): 517–522. https://doi.org/10.1177/0146167291175006.

  46. Sieck, W., and J.F. Yates. 1997. Exposition effects on decision making: choice and confidence in choice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 70 (3): 207–219. https://doi.org/10.1006/obhd.1997.2706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Mitchell, G. 2005. Libertarian paternalism is an oxymoron. Northwestern University Law Review 99 (3): 1245–1278.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Almashat, S., B. Ayotte, B. Edelstein, and J. Margrett. 2008. Framing effect debiasing in medical decision making. Patient Education and Counseling 71 (1): 102–107. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pec.2007.11.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Grill, K. 2014. Expanding the nudge: Designing choice contexts and choice contents. Rationality, Markets and Morals 5 (90): 139–162.

  50. White, M. 2013. The manipulation of choice: Ethics and libertarian paternalism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

  51. Hausman, D.M., and B. Welch. 2010. Debate: To nudge or not to nudge. Journal of Political Philosophy 18 (1): 123–136. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2009.00351.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Sunstein, C.R. 2015. Nudges, agency, and abstraction: A reply to critics. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (3): 511–529. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0266-z.

  53. Sunstein, C.R. 2016. The ethics of choice architecture. In Choice architecture in democracies: Exploring the legitimacy of nudging, ed. A. Kemmerer, C. Möllers, M. Steinbeis, and G. Wagner, 21–74. Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlagsgesellschaft.

  54. Cohen, S. 2013. Nudging and informed consent. American Journal of Bioethics 13 (6): 3–11. https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2013.781704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Brooks, T. 2013. Should we nudge informed consent. American Journal of Bioethics 13 (6): 22–23. https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2013.781710.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Engelen, B., A. Thomas, A. Archer, and N. van de Ven. 2018. Exemplars and nudges: Combining two strategies for moral education. Journal of Moral Education 47 (3): 346–365. https://doi.org/10.1080/03057240.2017.1396966.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Blumenthal-Barby, J.S. 2013. Choice architecture: A mechanism for improving decisions while preserving liberty? In Paternalism: Theory and practice, ed. C. Coons and M. Weber, 178–196. New York: Cambridge University Press.

  58. Engelen, B. 2019. Ethical criteria for health-promoting nudges: A case-by-case analysis. American Journal of Bioethics 19 (5): 48–59. https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2019.1588411.

  59. Blumenthal-Barby, J.S. 2021. Good ethics and bad choices: The relevance of behavioral economics for medical ethics. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  60. Buchanan, A., and R. Powell. 2018. The evolution of moral progress: A biocultural theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  61. Melo-Martin, I., and A. Salles. 2015. Moral bioenhncement: Much ado about nothing? Bioethics 29 (4): 223–232. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Wiseman, H. 2014. SSRIs as moral enhancement interventions: A practical dead end. AJOB Neuroscience 5 (3): 21–30. https://doi.org/10.1080/21507740.2014.911214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  63. Levy N. 2019. Nudge, nudge, wink, wink: Nudging is giving reasons. Ergo 6 (10). https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.12405314.0006.010

  64. DeGrazia, D. 2014. Moral enhancement, freedom, and what we (should) value in moral behaviour. Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (6): 361–368. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2012-101157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For insightful comments and suggestions on various versions of the paper, I would like to thank Tom Douglas, Gabriel De Marco, Nino Kadić, Lovro Savić, Aleksandar Simić, Zlata Božac, Andrés Moles, two anonymous reviewers, and the Ethics of Behavioural Influence and Prediction Work-in-Progress Group, as well as the audience at ‘SINe Neuroethics in a Time of Global Crises’ (Milano, May 2022).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Viktor Ivanković.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ivanković, V. What (if anything) morally separates environmental from neurochemical behavioral interventions?. Neuroethics 17, 6 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-023-09540-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-023-09540-3

Keywords

Navigation