Skip to main content
Log in

A Quinean Reformulation of Fregean Arguments

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In ontological debates, realists typically argue for their view via one of two approaches. The Quinean approach employs naturalistic arguments that say our scientific practices give us reason to affirm the existence of a kind of entity. The Fregean approach employs linguistic arguments that say we should affirm the existence of a kind of entity because our discourse contains reference to those entities. These two approaches are often seen as distinct, with indispensability arguments typically associated with the former, but not the latter, approach. This paper argues for a connection between the two approaches on the grounds that the typical arguments of the Fregean approach can be reformulated as indispensability arguments. This connection is significant in at least two ways. First, it implies that indispensability arguments provide a common framework within which to compare the Quinean and Fregean approaches, which allows for a more precise delineation of the two approaches. Second, it implies the possibility of analogical relations that allow proponents and opponents of each approach to draw upon the ideas that have been developed regarding the other.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is some disagreement over what indispensability consists in and, in particular, which theoretical virtues are key for determining indispensability—see Burgess (1983), Field (1980, p. 8), Colyvan (1999, p. 5; 2001, p. 77), and Panza and Sereni (2013). For the purposes of this paper, a rough characterisation of indispensability will suffice.

  2. The characterisations of the two approaches so far has been only rough, depending on the somewhat vague descriptions of arguments are ‘naturalistic’ or ‘linguistic’. This seems to be in line with the way the approaches are characterised in the literature. Section 4 will consider this imprecision and suggest a clearer delineation of the arguments that fall under each approach.

  3. Frege in Grundgesetze §91 might have argued for a realist attitude to mathematics on grounds of the applicability of mathematics to science, and this argument is sometimes taken to be a rudimentary predecessor of the Quine-Putnam indispensability argument (Balaguer, 1998, pp. 95–112; Colyvan, 2001, pp. 8–9; Sereni, 2014), though this connection has been disputed (Garavaso, 2005). The connection to be argued in this paper will differ from this. ‘Fregean-style arguments’ here refers to arguments premised on observations about a domain of discourse, independent of whether that domain is applicable to science. Thanks to an anonymous referee for highlighting this similar idea in the literature.

  4. Also see Molinini, Pataut, and Sereni (2016).

  5. Indeed, §3 will argue that some indispensability arguments do not fall under the Quinean approach, and §4 will consider cases where it is unclear whether an indispensability argument falls under the Quinean approach. §4 will also suggest a restriction on indispensability arguments that might define a subclass containing just Quinean-style arguments.

  6. It is not being claimed that premise (1) is true just in case the corresponding instance of premise (I) is, nor is the same being claimed about premises (2) and (II). See below for a case in which one might deny premise (1) while affirming premise (I).

  7. Some Meinongians are an example of such opponents, who argue that non-existent entities can be the referents of singular terms in true sentences (Linsky & Zalta, 1995; Priest, 2005; Routley, 1980).

  8. For instance, fictionalists deny (i) by denying the truth of all sentences in which singular terms purport reference to the target entities (Field, 1989; Leng, 2005; Mackie, 1977). Some other opponents deny (ii) by affirming some of those sentences while denying that we can infer anything about the reference of terms therein (Azzouni, 2004; Yablo, 2009). Still others affirm the reference of the relevant terms but deny that they refer to the entities under dispute (Hellman, 1989; Moltmann, 2013, 2016), thereby denying (iii). If these opponents hold that their account of the relevant discourse is at least as good as the realists, they fall under the present category of opponents; otherwise, they choose to adopt a sub-optimal interpretation of the relevant discourse (see below).

  9. Lewis’ argument is sometimes interpreted as an indispensability argument—see De (2018) and Eklund (2006).

  10. There have been doubts regarding whether some indispensability arguments can make a case for metaphysical realism (under which a kind of disputed entity exists) and not merely for semantic realism (under which a disputed kind of sentence is true)—see Liggins (2008), Pincock (2012), and Putnam (2006). However, these doubts are separate from the line of objection considered here, according to which some apparent arguments for realism can establish the existence of a kind of entity, but only in a deflationary sense. Thanks to an anonymous referee for highlighting this similar argument.

  11. See Balaguer (1998) for an attempt at deflating indispensability arguments, though Balaguer does not argue that indispensability arguments are deflationary because they yield realism in a merely verbal sense.

References

  • Audi, P. (2012). A clarification and defense of the notion of grounding. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality (pp. 101–121). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Azzouni, J. (2004). Deflating existential consequence. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114(454), 223–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical accidents and the end of explanation. In O. Bueno & Ø. Linnebo (Eds.), New Waves in Philosophy of Mathematics (pp. 137–159). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (1998). Platonism and anti-Platonism in mathematics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S. (2013). A truthmaker indispensability argument. Synthese, 190, 2413–2421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. (1990). The standard of equality of numbers. In G. Boolos (Ed.), Meaning and Method: Essays in Honor of Hilary Putnam (pp. 261–277). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (1993). Empty names. Noûs, 27, 449–469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (2005). Empty names, fictional names, mythical names. Noûs, 39(4), 596–631.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. (1989). Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, J. (1983). Why I am not a nominalist. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 24(1), 93–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. In P. Benacerraf & H. Putnam (Eds.), Philosophy of mathematics: Selected readings (pp. 241–257). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2010). There is no easy road to nominalism. Mind, 119(474), 285–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • De, M. (2018). On the Humphrey Objection to Modal Realism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 95(2), 159–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1956). Nominalism. Philosophical Review, 65, 491–505.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eklund, M. (2006). Metaontology. Philosophy. Compass, 3(1), 317–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1989). Platonism for cheap? Crispin Wright on Frege’s context principle. In M. Realism (Ed.), and Modality (pp. 147–170). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1964). The basic laws of arithmetic. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1960). The foundations of arithmetic (J. Austin, Trans. Vol. 1). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

  • Garavaso, P. (2005). On Frege’s alleged indispensability argument. Philosophia Mathematica, 13(2), 160–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (1984). Frege’s Platonism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 34(136), 225–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B., & Wright, C. (2001). The reason’s proper study: Essays towards a Neo-Fregean philosophy of mathematics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, G. (1989). Mathematics without numbers: Towards a modal-structural interpretation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. (2002). Quantifier variance and realism. Philosophical. Issues, 12, 51–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. (2005). Physical-object ontology, verbal disputes, and common sense. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 70(1), 67–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch, E. (2008). Ontological arguments: Interpretive charity and quantifier variance. In T. Sider, J. Hawthorne, & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics (pp. 367–381). Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leng, M. (2005). Revolutionary fictionalism: A call to arms. Philosophia Mathematica, 13(3), 277–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liggins, D. (2008). Quine, Putnam, and the ‘Quine-Putnam’ indispensability argument. Erkenntnis, 68(1), 113–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, Ø. (2005). To be is to be an F. Dialectica, 59(230), 235–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, Ø. (2009). The individuation of the natural numbers. In O. Bueno & Ø. Linnebo (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of mathematics (pp. 220–238). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linnebo, Ø. (2018). Thin objects. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linsky, B., & Zalta, E. N. (1995). Naturalized Platonism versus Platonized naturalism. The Journal of Philosophy, 92, 525–555.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, A. (2011). Mathematical explanations of empirical facts and mathematical realism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(3), 559–578.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1977). Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1997). Naturalism in mathematics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2001). Naturalism: Friends and foes. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 37–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molinini, D., Pataut, F., & Sereni, A. (2016). Indispensability and explanation [Special issue]. Synthese, 193(2), 317–657.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (2013). Reference to numbers in natural language. Philosophical Studies, 162(3), 499–536.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (2016). The number of planets, a number-referring term? In P. A. Ebert & M. Rossberg (Eds.), Abstractionism: Essays in the philosophy of mathematics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Panza, M., & Sereni, A. (2013). The indispensability argument: Structure and basic notions. Plato’s Problem (pp. 196–216). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Panza, M., & Sereni, A. (2016). The varieties of indispensability arguments. Synthese, 193, 469–516.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematics and scientific representation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2005). Towards non-being. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1987). Truth and convention: On Davidson’s refutation of conceptual relativism. Dialectica, 41(1–2), 69–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1994). The question of realism. Words and life (pp. 295–312). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2006). Indispensability arguments in the philosophy of mathematics. In M. DeCaro & D. Macarthur (Eds.), Philosophy in an age of science: Physics, mathematics, and skepticism (pp. 181–201). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1948). On what there is. The Review of Metaphysics, 2(5), 21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1981). Success and limits of mathematization. Theories and things (pp. 148–155). Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayo, A. (2009). Toward a trivialist account of mathematics. In O. Bueno & Ø. Linnebo (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of mathematics (pp. 239–260). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayo, A. (2013). The construction of logical space. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, M. (1995). Scientific vs mathematical realism. Philosophia Mathematica, 3(3), 166–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Routley, R. (1980). Exploring Meinong’s jungle and beyond. Australian National University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1998). Nonexistence. Noûs, 32(3), 277–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1990). Meaning and value. The Journal of Philosophy, 87(11), 602–614.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1994). A paradox of meaning. Noûs, 28(3), 279–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1996). Language-created language-independent entities. Philosophical Topics, 24(1), 149–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (2003). The things we mean. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sereni, A. (2014). Frege, indispensability, and the compatibilist heresy. Philosophia Mathematica, 23(1), 11–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1963). Physical objects and physical theories. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2009). Answerable and unanswerable questions. In D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 444–471). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2014). Ontology made easy. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Holten, W. (2002). Theism and inference to the best explanation. Ars Disputandi, 2, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1977). Creatures of fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 14(4), 299–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2003). Existence, ontological commitment, and fictional entities. In M. Loux & D. Zimmermann (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1983). Frege’s conception of numbers as objects. Aberdeen University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1999). Is Hume’s principle analytic? Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 40(1), 6–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2009). Must existence-questions have answers? In D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 507–526). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nathaniel Gan.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gan, N. A Quinean Reformulation of Fregean Arguments. Acta Anal 38, 481–494 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-022-00535-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-022-00535-y

Keywords

Navigation