Abstract
Despite the fact that information systems ontologies [ISOs] support the mutual understanding between human beings and software applications, human beings and software applications do not understand ISOs' contents in the same way. The same applies to ontological integration. This paper attempts to account for such discrepancies by emphasizing that while human being can have access to entities represented in ISOs, software applications cannot.
1 Ontology in Information Systems
According to Smith (2003), information systems ontologists generally share the assumption that
-
[1]
ontology does not deal with reality but with alternative possible worlds defined by information systems.
On one side, this means that ontologists reject the definition of ontology coming from the (analytical) philosophical investigation, according to which ontology aims to draw a complete inventory of reality by specifying its fundamental structure.Footnote 1 On the other side, they embrace the definition of ontologies coming from the IT domain, suggesting that:
-
ontology refers to an explicit (and sometimes partial) specification of a shared conceptualization that is formalized in a logical theory,Footnote 2
-
speaking of ontologies, in the plural, indicates a multiplicity of artificial worlds defined by information systems ontologies [ISOs] as well as different ways to represent such worlds.Footnote 3
Now,
-
[2]
outlining an ISOâs world means providing an inventory of all the entities (in primis, classes, instances, and relationsFootnote 4) that populate such a world.
The ontological implications of this operation, Smith holds, are essentially two:
-
[3]
only those entities exist which are represented in the ISO,
-
[4]
the entities in question possess only those properties which the ISO itself recognizes.
According to Smith, [4] suggests an analogy between fictional and ISOs entities. «It is as if Hamlet, whose hair (we shall suppose) is not mentioned in Shakespeareâs play, would be not merely neither bald nor nonbald, but would somehow have no properties at all as far as hair is concerned»Footnote 5 (Smith, 2003: 161). This means that, as well as for fiction,
-
[5]
the entities represented in an ISO are not real entitiesâthe entities of flesh and blood we find all around us.
Rather,
-
[6]
they are denatured surrogates,
-
[6.1]
possessing only a finite number of properties,
-
[6.2]
being entirely indeterminate with regard to those properties with which the ISO is not concerned.
However, as regards to [3], the analogy between ISO and fiction shows a discrepancy. If it is true that, in the domain of ISOs, only those entities exist which are represented in the system, there are cases,Footnote 6 in the realm of fiction, where we might also assume the existence of entities that are not mentioned in the fiction itself. For example, while the city of Cremona does not exist in TV shows such as Game of Thrones and Teletubbies, we cannot exclude its existence in Williamâs novel Stoner or Manzoniâs I promessi sposi, although âCremonaâ is never mentioned in these novels.
2 Internal and External Questions
We might now consider the example of
-
[7]
an ISO representing all the countries in the world
and apply to it
-
[8]
Carnapâs (1950) distinction between internal and external questions.
Varzi (2009: 6) explains such a distinction as follows: a question is internal to a framework (in our case, an ISO) if it may get answered by the resources provided by the framework; a question is external if it refers to the acceptability of the framework itself. Therefore, asking about the existence of a certain country is a question internal to [7] in so far as it concerns the existence of that country in relation to [7]. As opposed to this, asking whether countries really exist is an external question, as it concerns the reality of the world presupposed by [7], but then, what are those entities that populate [7]? According to [5] and [6], such entities are not the real countries where we live or that we can visit in our everyday life. Rather, they are merely representations (denatured surrogates, in Smithâs terms) of the real countries we have all around us. This means that internal questions involve the denatured surrogates (of the entities of the real world) represented in [7]. On the contrary, external questions refer to the real world whose entities are represented in [7] by surrogates.
The choice of introducing [8] is not random. Indeed, speaking of ISOsâ contents, Goy and Magro (2015) argue that
-
[9]
ISOs can support the mutual understanding between human beings, between human beings and software applications, and between software applications themselves.
This does not, however, imply that human beings and software applications understand ISOsâ contents in the same way, but if so, what does the difference involve? To answer this question, I find it is crucial to consider that, while human beings may have access to the objects represented in ISOsâ contents (i.e., the references of ISOsâ contents in the real world), software applications may not. This implies that the mutual understanding between software applications is anchored to ISOsâ contents in terms of [6], whereas the mutual understanding between human beings can refer to both ISOsâ contents and to the correspondence between ISOsâ contents and the real world. In other words, human beings are in the position to address external questions.
3 ISO Integrations
The mutual understanding mentioned in [9] is strictly intertwined with the notion of ISO integration. More precisely, Goy and Magro maintain that the possibility for software applications of understanding ISOsâ contents enables data integration on the Web. What is ISO integration, then? Broadly speaking,
-
[10]
ISO integration is the process by which ISOs can semantically combine data from multiple heterogeneous information systems.Footnote 7
Such a process is related to the general aims of ISOs including the description of semantic heterogeneity in different information sources and the formulation of unambiguous definitions and identifications for their entities.
Now, if Smith is right in endorsing the analogy between fictional and ISOs entities, we might ask, as fiction theory does:
-
[11]
how and to what extent are we entitled to integrate ISOs' contents?
A possible answer to [11] could result from [3Ë4]: if only those entities exist which are represented in an ISO and such entities only possess the properties that the ISO itself recognizes, then integrations are not possible. Another answer may derive from [6Ë10], according to which, if ISOs can semantically combine data from multiple information systems, then ISOsâ contents may be integrated with data coming from other information systemsâdata that, according to [6], are in turn denatured surrogates.
However, fiction theory does not see things in the same way. It is not just the integration from other fictions to be interestingâthat is, applying [10] to fiction theory. Rather, it is
-
[12]
the possibility to integrate what it is explicitly stipulated in a fiction with what might legitimately be considered to be true within that fiction.
How to do that? For example, we could follow the reality principle [RP] and the mutual belief principle [MBP].
RP says that a fictional world is as much as like the real world as the explicitly stipulated fictional truths permit.
MBP says that it is not reality that licenses integrations, but the common beliefs shared at the time the fiction has been written.Footnote 8
Now, without taking into account any criticism of such principles, there are at least four different reasons that make the introduction of RP and MBP in the debate on ISO integration problematic, namely: [1], [3Ë4], [6Ë10], and [2Ë3].
[1] is specifically directed against RP: if ISOs do not deal with reality, why integrate ISOs' contents with the real world? [3Ë4], [6Ë10], and [2Ë3] are instead addressed against both RP and MBP. [3Ë4] excludes any integration, including those from RP and MBP. [6Ë10] allows only integrations from information systems. Finally, while both RP and MBP seem to presuppose, according to [12] that a (fictional) world might be more crowded compared to what has been explicitly stipulated, [2Ë3] seems to say otherwise.
4 Integrations and External Questions
But then, why should we introduce RP and MBP in the debate on ISO integration? Because of external questions, which, I suggest, could enrich the possibilities of ISO integration.
Letâs take [7] again, specifying that
-
[13]
it only represents all the countries in the world,
-
[14]
it does not recognize the property âhas as capital.â
Based on [3Ë13], we can say that only all the countries of the world exist in [7]; based on [5Ë6] that those countries are not the real countries but their denatured surrogates; based on [4Ë14] that those denatured surrogates do not possess the property âhas as capitalââalthough the real countries possess such a property.
Now, according to Parsons (1980) for fiction entities and to Smith for ISOsâ ones (see [6.2]), we should maintain that, as regards to the property âhas as capital,â [7]âs countries are indeterminate. However, I suggest, such an indeterminacy improperly refers to [7]âs countries, given that [7] itself does not take into account the property âhas as capital.â Rather, [7]âs countries are indeterminate about the property âhas as capitalâ if compared to the real world whose countries possess such a property.
Accepting such a line of reasoning means that
-
[15]
the indeterminacy mentioned in [6.2] implies a relation between ISOs' contents and the world represented by the ISOs.
If so, a chance to make [7]âs entities determinate about the property âhas as capitalâ might consist in integrating [7]âs entities with the property âhas as capitalâ that the real countries possess, but then, integrations from the (external) world represented by [7] would be, at least in principle, possible. To what extent? The analogy between fictional and ISOs entities might suggest to follow, for example, RP or MBP, that isâas explicitly stipulated in [7]âintegrating [7]âs contents with, for example, the real world, or with the real world at the time [7] has been created, or with the beliefs shared by the ontologists who wrote [7] at the time [7] has been created, and so forth, and this is how and to what extent external questions enrich the possibilities of ISO integration.
Accordingly, facing [11] requires to specify whether answering
-
[16]
by the (internal) resources provided by ISOs,
-
[17]
by the (external) world represented in ISOs by denatured surrogates.
Outlining such alternatives does not imply that human beings and software applications could integrate ISOsâ contents in the same way. As it happens with [9], the difference refers to the fact that human beings have access to the external world represented in the ISOs by denatured surrogates whereas software applications have not. Therefore, we might conclude by observing that, while for software applications ISO integrations are tied to [16], human beings can integrate ISOsâ contents in terms of [16] and [17]. This might also explain why when we look at ISOsâ contents we, as human beings, do not see just denatured surrogates but also the entities represented in the ISOs.
Notes
Lowe (2006).
Guarino et al. (2009).
Couclelis (2019).
Laurini (2017).
While by discussing Smithâs proposal in terms of ISOsâ completeness (see [2]) and analogy between fictional and ISOsâ entities, this paper can be interpreted as an analysis of the consequences of such a proposal, it should also be noted that both [2] and the analogy are not accepted by the entire community of computer scientists. Indeed, with regard to [2], some IT/computer approaches assume the incompleteness of ISOsâ conceptualizationsâespecially for the ISOs within the Web environment. More precisely, for those ISOs, the incompleteness is formally stated as the Open-world assumption, according to which everything that cannot be inferred as false from an ISO must be considered unknown. This means that, for these cases, [2] does not hold and, consequently, [3] and [4] should be retracted. As regards to the analogy between fictional and ISOsâ entities, some IT/computer scientists refuse such an analogy, and consider ISOsâ entities as symbolic representations of conceptualizations of world fragments. According to this perspective, ISOsâ entities are still denatured surrogates but also abstractions that can be refined by means of integration (see § 3). Therefore, if it may be a non-sense to wonder about Hamletâs hair; it does make sense to integrate ISOsâ contents with contents coming from other ISOsâpossibly, through a refinement of the abstractions provided by their conceptualizations.
Lewis (1978).
Li et al. (2018).
Walton (1990).
References
Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4, 20â40.
Couclelis, H. (2019). Unpacking the âIâ in GIS: Information, ontology, and the geographic world. In T. Tambassi (Ed.), The Philosophy of GIS. (pp. 3â24). Springer.
Goy, A., Magro, D. (2015). What are ontologies useful for? In M. Khosrow-Pour (ed.), Encyclopedia of information science and technology. IGI Global, 7456â64.
Guarino, N., Oberle, D., & Staab, S. (2009). What Is an Ontology? In S. Staab & R. Studer (Eds.), Handbook on Ontologies. (pp. 1â17). Springer.
Laurini, R. (2017). Geographic knowledge infrastructure: Applications to territorial intelligence and smart cities. ISTE-Elsevier.
Lewis, D. (1978). Truth in fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(1), 37â46.
Li, X., Wu, Z., Goh, M., & Qiu, S. (2018). Ontological knowledge integration and sharing for collaborative product development. International Journal of Computer Integrated Manufacturing, 31(3), 275â288.
Lowe, E. J. (2006). The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Clarendon Press.
Parsons, T. (1980). Nonexistent Objects. Yale University Press.
Smith, B. (2003). Ontology. In L. Floridi (Ed.), Blackwell guide to the philosophy of computing and information. (pp. 155â166). Blackwell.
Varzi, A. (2009). Metafisica: classici contemporanei. (p. 2018). Laterza.
Walton, K. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Harvard University Press.
Funding
Open access funding provided by Università degli Studi di Salerno within the CRUI-CARE Agreement.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Ethics declarations
Competing Interests
The authors declare no competing interests.
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
About this article
Cite this article
Tambassi, T. On the Content of Information Systems Ontologies. Acta Anal 36, 615â621 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-021-00464-2
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-021-00464-2
Keywords
- Information systems ontologies
- Mutual understanding
- Ontological integration