Skip to main content
Log in

Thinking with Others: A Radically Externalist Internalism

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper is ambitious: it begins with mixing externalism in philosophy of mind with internalism in epistemology, and it ends with instructive insights from social and feminist thought. In the first stage, I argue that one can consistently combine two theses that appear, at first glance, incompatible: cognitive externalism—the thesis that one’s mental states/processing can extend past one’s biological boundaries—and mentalism in epistemology—i.e., that epistemic justification supervenes on one’s mental states. This yields the perhaps startling or strange view that the loci of epistemic justification are both mental states and (can be) located externally to one’s skull and skin. This motivates the second stage: I aim to ease that strangeness by suggesting that most discussions of cognitive externalism and epistemology too often focus exclusively on extending epistemically reliable abilities, faculties, dispositions, etc. to artifacts (e.g., notebooks, computers) in one’s environment. Instead, we should think of this combination as informed by feminist epistemologists’ insistence of our thinking’s irreducible and radical sociality. Epistemic communities shape and are shaped by our cognition—echoing the dynamic, interactive integration at the heart of cognitive externalism. Thus, just as I am part of an epistemic community, it is also a part of me (literally). Thus, I think with others: not merely as an artifact but as constituent elements of my cognition itself; resulting in a robust socially extended internalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Other terms for the same view dot the literature: vehicle externalism, active externalism (Clark and Chalmers 1998), locational externalism (Wilson 2000, 2004), and environmentalism (Rowlands 1999) are some others.

  2. Though I will use the term “justification,” I do not mean this to exclude other epistemic honorifics like “positive epistemic status,” “rationality,” and “warrant.” A robust internalist should understand all of these terms in something like the way I describe for justification.

  3. Technically, this is only one of two principles by which Feldman and Conee define mentalism. The other is (M)—“If any two possible individuals are exactly alike mentally, then they are exactly alike justificationally, e.g., the same beliefs are justified for them to the same extent” (2001, 2). But, since (M) merely “spells out a principal implication” of [Mentalism], we may ignore it here.

  4. Brent Madison (2010, 845) gives the example of a direct realist model of perception. On this view, one is directly aware of the world itself in perception, which need not be a mental state.

  5. This, though, is unfair. Some have suggested that we can, in fact, combine these two theses. See Jarvis (2015); Wikforss (2014); Carter and Palermos (2015). In what follows I want to offer a more sustained defense of this conjunction and, more importantly, sketch a more constructive proposal on what that conjunction could look like beyond mere consistency.

  6. Semantic externalism takes the content of intentional mental states to extend to external or extra-cranial features (e.g., one’s physical or socio-linguistic environment). See Putnam (1975) and Burge (1979) for landmark works on sematic externalism.

  7. In fact, if John McDowell is to be believed, the same considerations that drive some arguments for semantic externalism work in an exactly similar way for cognitive externalism: “…the ‘isolationist’ conception of language that Putnam objects to is all of a piece with a similarly ‘isolationist’ conception of the mind - at least of the mind as it is in itself” (McDowell 1992, 42).

  8. Removing (4) should not be all that surprising. Clark and Chalmers are explicitly ambivalent about its status along with the rest in their original (1998) piece.

  9. Again, he’s explicit on this point: “[t]he fundamental internalist idea is just that justification is internal to us. It seems extra to imply that our innards have any particular psychology. It also seems extra to imply that knowledge of our innards is definitely available to us” (2007, 56). I see no reason to be “extra” here, absent other considerations.

  10. Going by the lines above, it reads like Conee’s main anti-internalist positions are epistemological reliabilism or relativism, rather than semantic—or cognitive—externalism.

  11. Process reliabilism is the view that justifiers are reliable belief-forming processes. Since these processes must be reliable or truth-conductive and that relation is one that does not supervene on mental states (and is not in principle accessible), process reliabilism will necessarily fall on the externalist side of epistemic justification.

  12. Let us say that a theory is virtue reliabilist just in case it sees reliable or truth-conductive epistemic virtues as necessary for knowledge. These theories are externalist for precisely the same reasons as process reliabilism discussed in footnote 10.

  13. Thus, one might see this paper as one attempt to fill in a lacuna in theorizing about how epistemology and cognitive externalism might interconnect.

  14. Barnier et al. (2008) give an illuminating list of popular extension bases:

    Often-cited examples of distributed cognition include studies of the instruments and procedures involved in navigation; the physical objects and epistemic tools used in processing orders in a cafe´; the tangle of notes and records with which an academic paper is written; the way skilled bartenders employ unique glasses to remember cocktail orders; or the sketchpads without which abstract artists cannot iteratively re-imagine and create an artwork. (34)

    Note the types of things used as examples—instruments, tools, notes, sketchpads, and skills—only one does not directly refer to some object as a putative extension base (the skill of the bartender). I find this preponderance of artifacts in the literature as paradigms of extension bases striking.

  15. “Distributed cognition” is another term for the same notion that putative extension bases could be other people.

  16. Maybe a way to put my worry is that this approach may count as a collective epistemology, but I am dubious that it’s well-described as a social epistemology.

  17. As mentioned in 1.3, a central hallmark of [Cognitive Externalism] is Clark’s “continuous reciprocal causation.” The overlap of “reciprocity” there and in much feminist work I find striking and illuminates how both approaches are ripe for engaged dialogue; one this paper hopes to make promising.

  18. As mentioned earlier, my point here just follows the letter of Clark and Chalmers’ original way of framing how cognitive externalism can go social.

  19. Tollefsen et al. (2013) also examine transactive memory systems to defend a “socially extended memory system” (54). A with Battaly, I agree with their claims there, yet my thesis will also go further than this in its sociality.

  20. Tollefsen also defends collective epistemology in other works (e.g., Tollefsen (2004) and (2007)) but without the explicit use of [Cognitive Externalism] in general or Clark and Chalmers more specifically.

  21. If cognition extends beyond one’s skull and skin, then one faces the question of where such extension ends. The cognitive bloat worry is that such ending points will be too far—i.e., that [Cognitive Externalism] will extend too far. It would those over-cognize elements of the world that are, intuitively, not parts of one’s cognitive system.

References

  • Alcoff, L. M. (2010). Epistemic identities. Episteme, 7(2), 128–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antony, L. M. (2002). Embodiment and epistemology. In P. K. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 463–478). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnier, A. J., Sutton, J., Harris, C. B., & Wilson, R. A. (2008). A conceptual and empirical framework for the social distribution of cognition: the case of memory. Cognitive Systems Research, 9(1–2), 33–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battaly, H. (2008). Virtue epistemology. Philosophy Compass, 3(4), 639–663.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battaly, H. (2015). Virtue. Malden: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Battaly, H. (2018). Extending epistemic virtue: extended cognition meets virtue-responsibilism. In J. A. Carter, A. Clark, J. Kallestrup, & S. O. Palermos (Eds.), Extended epistemology (pp. 195–220). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. (2007). Externalism in mind and epistemology. In S. Goldberg (Ed.), Internalism and externalism in semantics and epistemology (pp. 13–34). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4(1), 73–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butts, E. (2012). Mentalism is not epistemic ur-internalism. Philosophical Explorations, 15(2), 233–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. A., & Palermos, S. O. (2015). Active externalism and epistemic internalism. Erkenntnis, 80(4), 753–772.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, A., Kallestrup, J., Palermos, S. O., & Pritchard, D. (2014). Varieties of externalism. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 63–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cash, M. (2010). Extended cognition, personal responsibility, and relational autonomy. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 645–671.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cash, M. (2013). Cognition without borders: “third wave” socially distributed cognition and relational autonomy. Cognitive Systems Research, 25-26, 61–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1998a). Being there: putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1998b). Magic words: how language augments human computation. In P. Carruthers & J. Boucher (Eds.), Language and thought: interdisciplinary themes (pp. 162–183). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2010). Memento’s revenge: the extended mind, extended. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 43–66). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Code, L. (1987). Epistemic responsibility. Hanover: University Press of New England.

    Google Scholar 

  • Code, L. (1991). What can she know? Feminist theory and the construction of knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Code, L. (1993). Taking subjectivity into account. In L. Alcoff & E. Potter (Eds.), Feminist epistemologies (pp. 15–48). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Code, L. (2006). Ecological thinking. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conee, E. (2007). Externally enhanced internalism. In S. Goldberg (Ed.), Internalism and externalism in semantics and epistemology (pp. 51–67). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R., & Conee, E. (2001). Internalism defended. American Philosophical Quarterly, 38(1), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2018). The extended mind: state of the question. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 56(4), 421–447.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Crisafi, A. (2009). Mental insitutions. Topoi, 28(1), 45–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, A. (2012). Extending the credit theory of knowledge. Philosophical Explorations, 15(2), 121–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hetherington, S. (2012). The extended knower. Philosophical Explorations, 15(2), 207–218.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jarvis, B. (2015). Epistemology and radically extended cognition. Episteme, 12(4), 459–478.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2013). Extended cognition and robust virtue epistemology. Erkenntnis, 78(2), 245–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2014). Epistemology extended. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 230–252.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2011). Extended cognition and the space of social interaction. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(3), 643–657.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1993). Subjects, power and knowledge: description and prescription in feminist philosophies of science. In L. Alcoff & E. Potter (Eds.), Feminist Epistemologies (pp. 101–120). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1994). In search of feminist epistemology. The Monist, 77(4), 472–485.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1999). Feminist epistemology. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 327–353). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madison, B. J. C. (2010). Epistemic internalism. Philosophy Compass, 5(10), 840–853.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1992). Putnam on mind and meaning. Philosophical Topics, 20(1), 35–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: mind and cognition unbounded. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2012). Cognitive practices and cognitive character. Philosophical Explorations, 15(2), 147–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2013). Cognitive integration, encultured cognition and the socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 25, 26–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelian, K. (2014). JFGI: from distributed cognition to distributed reliabilism. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 314–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, S. O. (2011). Belief-forming processes, extended. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(4), 741–765.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, S. O. (2015). Active externalism, virtue reliabilism and scientific knowledge. Synthese, 192(9), 2955–2986.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, S. O. (2016). Spreading the credit: virtue reliabilism and weak epistemic anti-individualism. Erkenntnis, 81(2), 305–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, S. O., & Pritchard, D. (2013). Extended knowledge and social epistemology. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 2(8), 105–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2010). Cognitive ability and the extended cognition thesis. Synthese, 175(1), 133–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. Midwest Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 131–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: understanding cognitive processes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D. (2004). Collective epistemic agency. Southwest Philosophy Review, 20(1), 55–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D. (2006). From extended mind to collective mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 7, 140–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D. (2007). Collective epistemic agency and the need for collective epistemology. In N. Psarros & K. Schulte-Ostermann (Eds.), Facets of sociality (pp. 309–329). Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D., Dale, R., & Paxton, A. (2013). Alignment, transactive memory, and collective cognitive systems. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4(1), 49–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wikforss, Å. (2014). Extended belief and extended knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 460–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2000). The mind beyond itself. In D. Sperber (Ed.), Misrepresentations: a multidisciplinary perspective (pp. 31–52). Oxford: Oxford University Pres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: the individual in the fragile sciences: cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Wilson, R. A., & Clark, A. (2009). How to situate cognition: letting nature take its course. In M. Aydede & P. Robbins (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 55–77). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. and Foglia, L. (2017). Embodied cognition. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/embodied-cognition/>. Accessed 21 April 2019.

  • Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the mind: an inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Rodrigo Borges, Eli Chudnoff, Richard Combes, Kevin DeLapp, Matt Frise, Jonathan Matheson, Kevin McCain, Andrew Moon, Ted Poston, Mike Veber, Chase Wrenn, Sarah Wright, an anonymous referee for this journal, and an audience at the 2019 Bled Philosophical Conference for comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Benjamin W. McCraw.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

McCraw, B.W. Thinking with Others: A Radically Externalist Internalism. Acta Anal 35, 351–371 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-020-00430-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-020-00430-4

Keywords

Navigation