Skip to main content
Log in

Blum’s Puzzle and the Analiticity of Kripkean Identity Statements

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We rely on a recent puzzle by Alex Blum to offer a new argument for the old Fitch’s thesis that what we learn a posteriori in Kripkean identity statements like ‘Tully is Cicero’ is contingent and what is not contingent in such statements is analytical, hence hardly a posteriori.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Neither ‘proposition’ nor ‘is about’ are absolutely definite terms; however, we doubt very much the present discussion can be carried on without reference to propositions or other objects no better defined (e.g., truth-makers). In any case, we believe those terms are definite enough to make this discussion meaningful. Similarly, arithmetical truth is nowhere formally defined; however, it is definite enough for the claim to make sense that Gödel showed no formal system encapsulates it.

  2. Surely, not all rigid designators are direct designators; consider ‘7 + 5’.

  3. The assumption is plausible for S as defined but not for identity statements involving non-direct designators: the proposition contained in ‘7 + 5 = 12’ need not be either the trivial proposition that 12 = 12 or the linguistic proposition that 7 + 5=R12; identity statements involving non-direct designators seem to admit a non trivial de re reading which statements like S seem to lack (see below).

  4. This derivation is Blum’s own puzzling argument: as he accepts that ‘T’ and ‘C’ refer rigidly, and he accepts (1) and (K) but finds the conclusion implausible, he expresses his puzzlement by bringing into question the possibility that ‘T’ and ‘C’ exist such that T = C.

  5. Fitch 1976 argues from this plausible principle: “If S is a sentence containing a rigid designator α and S is a sentence obtained from S by substituting a rigid designator β for α in S, and α and β designate the same object, then S and S express the same proposition” (p. 244); as ‘Hesperus is Phosphorus’ is obtained in that way from ‘Venus is Venus,’ it would express the same proposition as the latter.

References

  • Blum, A. (2017). Can it be that Tully = Cicero? Symposium, 4(2), 149–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, G. W. (1976). Are there necessary a posteriori truths? Philosophical Studies, 30, 243–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch, G. W. (2004). On Kripke and statements. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 28(1), 295–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1971). Identity and necessity. In M. Munitz, (Ed.), Identity and individuation (pp. 135–164). New York: New York University Press.

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press.

  • Salmon, N. (1986). Frege’s puzzle., Cambridge (MA): The MIT Press.

  • Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity: the unfinished semantic agenda of naming and necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank Alex Blum for his comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Laureano Luna.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Luna, L. Blum’s Puzzle and the Analiticity of Kripkean Identity Statements. Acta Anal 34, 9–14 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-018-0346-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-018-0346-7

Keywords

Navigation