Skip to main content
Log in

What Makes a Thing What It Is? Aristotle and Hegel on Identity

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The notion of identity is investigated through Aristotle and Hegel as supporters of two different ontological conceptions: pluralism of substances and relational holism. Through Aristotle, I examine both the thesis according to which the identity of an object is constituted by its properties and the difficulties which this thesis encounters (e.g., those raised by Max Black). Aristotle easily defines the identity in species, in genus, and in number; some problems arise regarding the identity of individuals: for these, it is not enough to indicate the definition and the proper qualities, but matter is needed. Matter cannot, however, be a criterion for identifying duplicate objects: in this case, it plays at most the role of a “weak individuator.” A weak individuator involves relations with other entities. The use of relations in determining the identity of an entity is extensively treated by Hegel, according to whom, in order to define the identity of an object a multiplicity of particular objects is required and, therefore, relations among entities. I conclude by proposing a notion of the object understood not as an independent, separate, and autonomous item, but as a portion of the world, which is given in a phenomenological context and identifies a dialectical context.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here, I left aside the discussion about referentially opaque contexts, which would make the logical identity much less obvious.

  2. Black himself hints at an objection of this sort at the end of his essay (cf. Black 1952, p. 163).

  3. The classic passages are Top. I 7; V 4; VII 1–2; Metaph. V 9; X 3.

  4. As remarked by Zadro (1974, p. 327).

  5. Aristotle, Top. I 7, 103a23–24; cf. also 103a9–10 (Engl. trans. by W. A. Pickard-Cambridge).

  6. Cf. Aristotle, Top. I 7, 103a10, 27. The same example is repeated in Metaph. IV 4, 1006b25–27: “For being one means this—being related as ‘raiment’ [lōpion] and ‘dress’ [himation] are, if their definition [logos] is one.” Cf. also Phys. I 2, 185b20.

  7. The concept of genus-matter is explained with great clarity by Stenzel (19593, pp. 131–140).

  8. As maintain Charlton (1994, p. 46) and Gill (1994, p. 57).

  9. We find it both in Metaph. VII 12 and in chapters thirteen and fourteen of the second book of the Posterior Analytics.

  10. Aristotle, Metaph. VII 12, 1038a19–20. For a detailed explanation of the matter cf. Cubeddu (2004, pp. 67 ff.); cf. also Balme (1987).

  11. As we have seen in chapter seven of the first book of the Topics, an analogous discourse can be made in reference to identity in genus.

  12. Ross (1949, p. 678). Cf. also the similar interpretation by Barnes (19942, p. 266), who observes, however, that Aristotle does not explain how we are to apprehend a universal. An answer ante litteram has been given by Wieland (1962, pp. 88 ff.): in his view, the individual “by its very nature stays always already in the light of a universality”; from the point of view of the single man, however, the error is always possible, that is why the research “then verifies whether it is in this case a genuine universality” (Wieland 1962, p. 95; cf. also pp. 98–99).

  13. Cf. Aristotle, De part. anim. I 4, 644a12 ff. (Engl. trans. by W. Ogle).

  14. Regarding this topic cf. Balme (1987, p. 72), Lennox (1987, pp. 340 ff., 346 ff., 358), and Carbone (2002, pp. 558–560).

  15. This eventuality is examined by Black (1952, p. 160) himself, who goes from here to postulate “a plane running clear through space, with everything that happens on one side of it always exactly duplicated at an equal distance in the other side,” like in a mirror, but he immediately abandons this hypothesis.

  16. Cf. Gill (1994, pp. 61–63). This interpretation, which refers to the passage of Metaph. VII 8 mentioned above, is supported also by Charlton (1994, p. 45).

  17. Cf. Gill (1994, pp. 65–66), who argues examining Phys. V 4.

  18. Cf. Gill (1994, p. 59); particular forms too may be considered as weak individuators (Gill 1994, pp. 69–70).

  19. “[…] those things are relatives for which being is the same as being somehow related to something” (Engl. trans. by J. L. Ackrill).

  20. The centrality of the relations with the other in Hegel has been emphasized by Theunissen (1978, p. 29): “Die gesamte Logik gründet Hegel auf die Hypothese, daß alles, was ist, nur in der Beziehung und letztlich nur als die Beziehung auf ›sein Anderes‹ es selbst sein könne.”

  21. Hegel, WdL, GW 21, p. 107; 2010a, p. 92. The English translation has been slightly modified.

  22. Cf. Hegel, WdL, GW 21, p. 115; 2010a, p. 99: “something has existence only in limit.”

  23. Hegel, Enz., § 92, Zus., p. 197; 2010b, p. 147; cf. also WdL, GW 21, p. 115; 2010a, p. 100: “something is what it is only in its limit.”

  24. The negative relation is the “puncticity” (Punctualität) of the thing, that is, the interpenetration, or intersection, of the matters with one another (cf. Carlson 2007, p. 358).

  25. Referring to these pages of the logic of reflection, Theunissen (1978, pp. 27 ff.) speaks about “Kritik der Verselbständigung.”

  26. I have dealt with this issue in Raspa (2008 and 2013, pp. 124 ff.).

  27. I assume here the definition of social objects given by Ferraris (2009, pp. 176, 183–184 and passim); cf. also Ferraris (2005, pp. 154 ff.). For more details on the idea outlined here in relation to social objects, cf. Raspa (2012).

  28. “Men can be distinguished from animals by consciousness, by religion or anything else you like. They themselves begin to distinguish themselves from animals as soon as they begin to produce their means of subsistence, a step which is conditioned by their physical organisation. By producing their means of subsistence, men are indirectly producing their actual material life” (Marx & Engels [1845–1846]/1958, p. 21; 1998, p. 37). “The second point is that the satisfaction of the first need (the action of satisfying, and the instrument of satisfaction which has been acquired) leads to new needs; and this production of new needs is the first historical act” (Marx & Engels [1845–1846]/1958, p. 28; 1998, p. 48).

  29. This is a revised and enlarged version of my essay “Che cosa fa di una cosa quella cosa. Aristotele e Hegel sull’identità,” published in Azzarà, S. G., Ercolani, P. & Susca, E. (Eds.). Dialettica, storia, conflitto: il proprio tempo appreso nel pensiero (pp. 73–93). Napoli: La scuola di Pitagora, 2011. Versions of this essay have been presented at the International Congress Identity: Ontological Perspectives (Amsterdam, 25th–27th May 2005), in a seminar held at the Department of Philosophy at the University of Turin on December 13, 2005, at the International Congress Metaphysics Today between a priori and a posteriori (Alghero, 8th–9th October 2010) and at the International Congress Dialectic, History and Conflict. The own Time grasped in Thought (Urbino, 18th–20th November 2011). Many thanks to those who intervened with questions and critical comments; a special thanks to Italo Cubeddu and Silvio Bozzi, who read and discussed with me this paper, and to Angus Dawson, for his help with translations.

References

  • Aristotelis Analytica Priora et Posteriora. Recensuit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit W. D. Ross, praefatione et appendice auxit L. Minio-Paluello, Oxonii: E Typographeo Clarendoniano, 19824 (19641).

  • Aristotelis Categoriae et Liber de Interpretatione. Recognovit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit L. Minio-Paluello, Oxonii: E Typographeo Clarendoniano, 19745 (19491).

  • Aristotelis De anima. Recensuit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit W. D. Ross, Oxonii: Clarendon, 19744 (19561).

  • Aristotelis Metaphysica. Recensuit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit W. Jaeger, Oxonii: E Typographeo Clarendoniano, 19694 (19571).

  • Aristotelis Physica. Recognovit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit W. D. Ross, Oxonii: E Typographeo Clarendoniano, 19735 (19501).

  • Aristotelis Topica et Sophistici Elenchi. Recensuit brevique adnotatione critica instruxit W. D. Ross, Oxonii: E Typographeo Clarendoniano, 19744 (19581).

  • Aristotle (1961). Parts of animals. With an english translation by A. L. Peck, London - Cambridge (Mass.): W. Heinemann-Harvard University Press, revised and reprinted (19371).

  • Aristotle (1984). The complete works of Aristotle. The revised Oxford Translation edited by J. Barnes, vols. I–II. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Balme, D. M. (1987). Aristotle’s use of division and differentiae. In A. Gotthelf & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 69–89). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, J. (19942). Aristotle, Posterior analytics. Translated with a Commentary by J. Barnes, 2nd ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press (19751).

  • Bergmann, G. (1967). Realism. A critique of Brentano and Meinong. Madison: The University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, M. (1952). The identity of indiscernibles. Mind, 61(242), 153–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbone, A. (2002). Aristotele, Le parti degli animali. Introd., trad. e note a cura di A. Carbone, Milano: Rizzoli.

  • Carlson, D. G. (2007). A commentary to Hegel’s Science of logic. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Charlton, W. (1994). Aristotle on identity. In T. Scaltsas, D. Charles, & M. L. Gill (Eds.), Unity, identity and explanation in Aristotle’s metaphysics (pp. 41–53). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cubeddu, I. (2004). Una certa scienza. Scritti su Aristotele e Kant. Urbino: Montefeltro.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drüe, H., Gethmann-Siefert, A., Hackenesch, Ch., Jaeschke, W., Neuser, W. & Schnädelbach, H. (2000). Hegels “Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften” (1830). Ein Kommentar zum Systemgrundriß. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main.

  • Ferraris, M. (2005). Dove sei? Ontologia del telefonino. Milano: Bompiani.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferraris, M. (2009). Documentalità. Perché è necessario lasciar tracce. Roma: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, M. L. (1994). Individuals and Individuation in Aristotle. In T. Scaltsas, D. Charles, & M. L. Gill (Eds.), Unity, identity and explanation in Aristotle’s metaphysics (pp. 55–71). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, N. (1957). Aristoteles und Hegel. In N. Hartmann, Kleinere Schriften (pp. 214–252). Berlin: de Gruyter.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1812–1813/1978). Wissenschaft der Logik. Erster Band: Die objektive Logik. Nürnberg: J. L. Schrag, 1812–1813. In Gesammelte Werke. In Verbindung mit der Forschungsgemeinschaft hrsg. von der Rheinisch-Westfälischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Bd. 11, hrsg. von F. Hogemann und W. Jaeschke, Hamburg: Meiner, 1978.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1832/1984). Wissenschaft der Logik. Erster Theil: Die objektive Logik. Erster Band: Die Lehre vom Seyn. Stuttgart und Tübingen: J. G. Cotta, 1832. In Gesammelte Werke. In Verbindung mit der Forschungsgemeinschaft hrsg. von der Rheinisch-Westfälischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Bd. 21, hrsg. von F. Hogemann und W. Jaeschke, Hamburg: Meiner, 1984.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (1840/1970). Encyclopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse. Th. 1: Die Logik . Hrsg. und nach Anleitung der vom Verf. gehaltenen Vorlesungen mit Erläuterungen und Zusätzen versehen von Dr. Leopold von Henning. In Werke. Vollständige Ausgabe durch einen Verein von Freunden des Verewigten: Ph. Marheineke, J. Schulze, Ed. Gans, Lp. v. Henning, H. Hotho, K. Michelet, F. Förster, Bd. 6, Berlin: Verlag von Duncker und Humblot, 1840; in Werke in zwanzig Bände. Bd. 8, hrsg. von E. Moldenhauer und K. M. Michel, Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 1970.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (2010a). The science of logic. Translated and edited by G. Di Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Hegel, G. W. F. (2010b). Encyclopedia of the philosophical sciences in basic outline. Part I: Science of logic. Translated and edited by K. Brinkmann and D. O. Dahlstrom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lennox, J. G. (1987). Kinds, forms of kinds, and the more and the less in Aristotle’s biology. In A. Gotthelf & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 339–359). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Marx, K. & Engels, F. ([1845–1846]/1958). Die Deutsche Ideologie. Kritik der neuesten deutschen Philosophie in ihren Repräsentanten, Feuerbach, B. Bauer und Stirner, und des deutschen Sozialismus in seinen verschiedenen Propheten. In Werke. Bd. 3, Berlin: Dietz, 1958 (im Auftrag des Marx-Engels-Lenin-Instituts Moskau hrsg. von V. V. Adoratskij, Wien - Berlin: Verlag für Literatur und Politik, 19321), pp. 9–530.

  • Marx, K. & Engels, F. (1998). The German Ideology including Theses on Feuerbach and Introduction to the critique of political economy. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books; URL: https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/download/Marx_The_German_Ideology.pdf.

  • Raspa, V. (2008). Individui e continui. Rivista di Estetica, 48(3), 189–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raspa, V. (2012). Descrizione e critica del mondo sociale: due compiti della documentalità. Rivista di Estetica, 52(2), 145–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raspa, V. (2013). The reality of lies. Filozofija i društvo (Philosophy and Society), 24(2), 105–131. URL: http://www.doiserbia.nb.rs/img/doi/0353-5738/2013/0353-57381302105R.pdf.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1949). Aristotle’s Prior and Posterior analytics. A revised text with introduction and commentary by W. D. Ross: Clarendon.

  • Ross, W. D. (1953). Aristotle’s Metaphysics. A revised Text with Introduction and Commentary by W. D. Ross, 2 vols., Oxford: Clarendon Press (19241).

  • Saunders, S. (2003). Physics and Leibniz’s principles. In K. Brading & E. Castellani (Eds.), Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflection (pp. 289–307). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stenzel, J. (19593). Zahl und Gestalt bei Platon und Aristoteles. 3. durchgesehene Aufl., Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft (19241).

  • Theunissen, M. (1978). Sein und Schein. Die kritische Funktion der Hegelschen Logik. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt a. M.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C., & Peschard, I. (2008). Identity over time: objectively, subjectively. Philosophical Quarterly, 58(230), 15–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wieland, W. (1962). Die aristotelische Physik. Untersuchungen über die Grundlegung der Naturwissenschaft und die sprachlichen Bedingungen der Prinzipienforschung bei Aristoteles. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zadro, A. (1974). Aristotele, I Topici. Trad., introd. e commento a cura di A. Zadro, Napoli: Loffredo.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Venanzio Raspa.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Raspa, V. What Makes a Thing What It Is? Aristotle and Hegel on Identity. Acta Anal 31, 345–361 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-016-0287-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-016-0287-y

Keywords

Navigation