Skip to main content
Log in

What Mary’s Aboutness Is About

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to reinforce anti-physicalism by extending the “hard problem” to a specific kind of intentional states. For reaching this target, I investigate the mental content of the new intentional states of Jackson’s Mary. I proceed in the following way: I start analyzing the knowledge argument, which highlights the “hard problem” tied to phenomenal consciousness. In a second step, I investigate a powerful physicalist reply to this argument: the phenomenal concept strategy. In a third step, I propose a constitutional account of phenomenal concepts that captures the Mary scenario adequately, but implies anti-physicalist referents. In a last step, I point at the ramifications constitutional phenomenal concepts have on the constitution of Mary’s new intentional states. Therefore, by focusing the attention on phenomenal concepts, the so-called “hard problem” of consciousness will be carried over to the alleged “easy problem” of intentional states as well.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. More precisely, the easy problems according to Chalmers “(...) concern the explanation of cognitive abilities and functions. To explain a cognitive function, we need only specify a mechanism that can perform the function” (Chalmers 1996, 202). In the following, I will investigate the cognitive function of phenomenal concepts and mental content of conscious intentional states.

  2. For various ways of formulating the knowledge argument, see Nida-Rümelin (2009) and Ludlow et al. (2004).

  3. For this label and a critical discussion, see Alter (2008).

  4. For a possible way of dealing with this problem, see, for example, Papineau (2002). Notably, in his (2007) Papineau also refrained from the idea that there is a demonstrative aspect build into phenomenal concepts.

  5. I want to use the notion “phenomenal experiences” here in a neutral sense. At this point I leave it open, if phenomenal experiences are ontologically physical or non-physical states.

  6. The following objection might be raised against every constitutional account of phenomenal concepts: If the experience is a constitutive part of the phenomenal concept, how can proponents of this thesis account for Mary’s true thought involving a phenomenal concept that she is currently not having a red experience? In answering this question a distinction is often made between basic and derivative (applications of) phenomenal concepts (Balog 2009; Papineau 2007), where the latter do not imply an occurring experience and are used in the true thought above. I will not pursue this issue here, since for my present argumentation it suffices to have some phenomenal concepts (often called “basic applications” of phenomenal concepts) to be constituted by occurring experiences.

  7. The reason for this demand is that just some co-occurrence of the mode of presentation and the concept would not suffice for the concept itself to carry the necessary information. Therefore, a constitutive link is required.

  8. For the claim that in the case of phenomenal states appearance and reality collapse, see, for example, Kripke (1972).

  9. The issue of phenomenal intentionality [see, for example, Kriegel and Horgan (forthcoming, paper is available at http://uriahkriegel.com/downloads/PIRP)] has received much discussion recently. In most cases it is argued that qualia have an impact on intentional states by focusing on the attitude type of intentional states (for example, Strawson (1994). Horgan and Tienson (2002) and Pitt (2004) explicitly hold that the attitude type of intentional states is partly constituted by its phenomenal character. Even if I take the attitude type to be partly constituted by qualia as well (Fürst 2008), my concern here will be the mental content of intentional states involving phenomenal concepts.

  10. The term “intentionality” is of scholastic origin, but was made explicit in the writings of Franz Brentano (1874). Focusing on the particularity of intentionality that mental states can be directed at nonexistent objects, Brentano’s scholar Kazimiersz Twardowski (1894) famously introduced a distinction between the intentional object at which the state (or act) is directed and the mental content of an intentional state.

  11. A clarification: I do not deny that a causal environmental chain leads to a phenomenal experience, but I claim that the experience itself is not constituted by externalist causes. [For a similar view see Horgan and Tienson (2002).] Since phenomenal concepts are constituted by phenomenal experiences and the inner constitution determines their reference, they resist externalist treatments.

References

  • Alter, T. (2008). Phenomenal knowledge without experience. In E. Wright (Ed.), The case for qualia (pp. 247–268). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balog, K. (2009). Phenomenal concepts. In B. Mclanghlin et al. (Eds.), Oxford Handbook in the philosophy of mind (pp. 292–312). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Block, N. (1980). Are absent qualia impossible? The Philosophical Review, 89, 257–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2002). The harder problem of consciousness. Journal of Philosophy, 99, 391–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt, Bd.1. Leipzig: Duncker&Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. In P. French et al. (Eds.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy, IV, 73–121.

  • Chalmers, D. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(3), 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2002). Does conceivability entail possibility? In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 145–200). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2004). Phenomenal concepts and the knowledge argument. In P. Ludlow et al. (Eds.), There’s something about Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument (pp. 269–298). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (1989). Knowing qualia. A reply to Jackson. In A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of mind and the structure of science (pp. 67–76). Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Dennett, D. C. (1984). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little, Brown, & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2007). What RoboMary knows. In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge (pp. 15–31). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, H. (1967). The “Mental” and the “Physical”. The Essay and a Postscript. Minneapolis: Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100, 25–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1993). Logische Untersuchungen. G. Patzig (Ed.), Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.

  • Fürst, M. (2008). The qualia of conscious intentionality. In H. Bohse & S. Walter (Eds.), Selected papers contributed to the sections of GAP.6 (pp. 374–385). Paderborn: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fürst, M. (2009). The dilemma of Papineau’s account of phenomenal concepts. In M. Gabbay (Ed.), Proceedings of the 13th Annual Conference of the British Postgraduate Philosophy Association (pp. 37–47).

  • Horgan, T. (1984). Jackson on physical information. Philosophical Quarterly, 34, 147–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind. Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 520–534). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1982). Epiphenomenal qualia. Philosophical Quarterly, 32, 127–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (2006). Consciousness, representation and knowledge. In U. Kriegel & K. Williford (Eds.), Self-representational approaches to consciousness (pp. 409–420). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (2011). What Intentionality Is Like. In M. Fürst & G. Melchior (Eds.), Intentionality and Experience. Special Issue of Acta Analytica.

  • Levin, J. (2007). What is a phenomenal concept? In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge (pp. 87–111). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze. The puzzle of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1929). Mind and the world order: Outline of a theory of knowledge. New York: Charles Scribners.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1966). An argument for the identity theory. Journal of Philosophy, 63, 17–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50, 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1988). What experience teaches. Proceedings of the Russellian Society, 13, 29–57.

  • Loar, B. (1990). Phenomenal states. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 81–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. (1997). Phenomenal states (2nd ed). In N. Block et al. (Eds.), The nature of consciousness (pp. 597–616). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow, P. et al. (Eds.) (2004). There’s something about Mary: Essays on phenomenal consciousness and Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought and other biological categories. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat? The Philosophical Review, 83, 435–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nemirow, L. (2007). So this is what it’s like: A defense of the ability hypothesis. In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge (pp. 32–51). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nida-Rümelin, M. (2009). Qualia: The knowledge argument. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2009 Edition). URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2009/entries/qualia-knowledge/>.

  • Papineau, D. (2002). Thinking about consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2007). Phenomenal and perceptual concepts. In T. Alter & S. Walter (Eds.), Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge (pp. 111–145). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (2001). Knowledge, possibility and consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. (2004). The phenomenology of cognition or what is it like to think that p? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 69, 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Place, U. T. (1956). Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology, 47, 44–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). The nature of mental states. In W. H. Capitan & D. D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘Meaning’. In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Language, mind and knowledge. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, VII (pp. 131–193). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raffman, D. (1995). On the persistence of phenomenology. In T. Metzinger (Ed.), Conscious experience (pp. 293–308). Paderborn: Schöningh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1981). Some varieties of functionalism. Philosophical Topics, 12(1), 83–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68, 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2005). Physicalism and phenomenal concepts. Mind and Language, 20(5), 469–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (1994). Mental reality. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Twardowski, K. (1894/1982). Zur Lehre vom Inhalt und Gegenstand der Vorstellungen. München: Philosophia.

  • Tye, M. (2003). A theory of phenomenal concepts. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Minds and Persons (pp. 91–106). Cambridge: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the participants of the workshop “Intentionality,” which was held at the University of Graz in October 2009, for helpful comments and fruitful discussions. I am particularly grateful to Guido Melchior for extensive discussions and helpful criticism on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martina Fürst.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Fürst, M. What Mary’s Aboutness Is About. Acta Anal 26, 63–74 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-010-0120-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-010-0120-y

Keywords

Navigation