Skip to main content
Log in

An Integrative Hypothesis of Brain Evolution

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The purpose of this article is to reconcile the hypotheses that: (1) brain evolution occurred due to a change in diet, and (2) it occurred due to pressures related to understanding more and more about the underlying causes, such as understanding increasingly complex manipulative and cooperative intentions on the part of the other, as well as understanding reality itself (and how to interact with it beyond group issues). I argue that the ingestion of fat, a highly energy-efficient food, would have unlocked the evolutionary process that culminated in the emergence of the practice of reasoning about underlying causes; and that the consolidation of such a practice resulted in a continuous pressure to increase cognition about “whys”; so that many explanations ended up imposing the need for additional ones, and with that came a high level of awareness and the need for the brain to evolve not only in terms of providing a higher level of cognition but also in size.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

Data sharing is not applicable to this article as no datasets were generated or analyzed during the current study.

Notes

  1. I am assuming the idea that phylogenesis proceeds from ontogenesis (see Gottlieb, 1992, p. 150, 2002), that is, that a certain change, be it a physical or behavioral characteristic, is established beforehand at the level of the individual before establishing itself at the genetic level and becoming, over evolutionary time, a common characteristic of the species. Gottlieb gathered a series of evidence that behaviors acquired by a non-human animal, such as cleaning the nest, can be transmitted genetically and become “natural” behavior patterns of its successors. It is worth noting that, according to the perspective I am ofering, if patterns of behavior are inherited, patterns of thiking are also inherited, which includes the type that allows elaborations and use of heuristics based on “whys”.

  2. This argument starts from the notion that “self-direction of attention comes to create self-awareness” (Barkley, 2012, p. 81).

  3. I agree with Pinker (2001, p. 208) that dealing with increasingly intelligent cheaters must not have been the only selection pressure responsible for triggering human intelligence. It is possible to imagine other ongoing pressures that increase the chance of survival, such as, for example, moving out of a lower status through the prestige route (see Fowers, 2015, p. 153), which depends on demonstrating more knowledge about the reality itself (and how to interact with it beyond group issues) than the other members of the group (if the other knows more and more, it is necessary to know even more to be considered superior); or even having to become a more skillful reader of positive intentions, in order to become a more skillful cooperator in the sense of being more able to help in the achievement of goals that depend on mutual effort to be achieved (especially objectives that increase the chance of survival when achieved) (Tomaselo, 2000).

References

  • Barkely, R. A. (2012). Executive functions: What they are, how they work, and why they evolved.New York:Guilford.

  • Bates, M. J. (2005). Information and knowledge: An evolutionary framework for information science.Information Research An international electronic journal,10(4).

  • Boyle, M. (2012). Essentially rational animals.InG. Abel, & J. Conant (Eds.), Rethinking Epistemology.Berlin:de Gruyter.

  • Byrne, R. W. (1997). Machiavellian intelligence.Evolutionary Anthropology,5,172–180.

  • Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1997). Evolutionary psychology: Aprimer. Center for Evolutionary Psychology, University of California, Santa Barbara. http://cogweb.ucla.edu/EP/EP-primer.html.

  • Dickinson, A., & Balleine, B. W. (2000). Causal cognition and goal-directed action. In C. Heyes, & L. Huber (Eds.), T (pp. 185–204). MIT Press.

  • Foley, R. (1995). Causes and consequences in human evolution.Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute,67–86.

  • Fowers, B. J. (2015). The Evolution of ethics: Human sociality and the emergence of ethical mindedness. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Gottlieb, G. (1992). Individual development and evolution: The genesis of novel behavior. Oxford University Press.

  • Gottlieb, G. (2002). Developmental–behavioral initiation of evolutionary change.Psychological Review,109(2),211–218.

  • Osmo, F. (2021). Basic evaluation process and some Associated Phenomena, such as emotions and reactive defense of beliefs. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science,1–30.

  • Osmo, F., Borri, M. M., & Falcão, M. (2022). True happiness as a shortcut to mental health: A new theory of psychopathology and psychotherapy based on Aristotle’s ethics and evolutionary science.InK. Fukao (Ed.), Counseling and therapy: Recent developments in theories and concepts.London:Intechopen.

  • Penn, D. C., Holyoak, K. J., & Povinelli, D. J. (2008). Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds.Behavioral and Brain Sciences,31(2),109–130.

  • Pinker, S. (2001). Como a mente funciona(L. T. Motta (Ed.), Trans.).São Paulo:Companhia das Letras(p.34).

  • Pinker, S. (2021). Rationality: What it is, why it seems scarce, why it matters.New York, NY:Viking(pp.151–161).

  • Povinelli, D. (2000). Folk physics for apes: The chimpanzee’s theory of how the world works.Oxford University Press(p.299).

  • Thompson, J. C., Carvalho, S., Marean, C., & Alemseged, Z. (2019). Origins of the human predatory pattern: The transition to large-animal exploitation by early hominins.Current Anthropology,60(1),1–23.

  • Tomasello, M. (2000). Two hypotheses about primate cognition.InC. Heyes, & L. Huber (Eds.), The evolution of cognition: Vienna series in theoretical biology(pp.165–183).Cambridge, MA:MIT Press.

  • Völter, C. J., & Call, J. (2017). Causal and inferential reasoning in animals.InJ. Call, G. M. Burghardt, I. M. Pepperberg, C. T. Snowdon, & T. Zentall (Eds.), APA handbook of comparative psychology Vol 2: Perception, learning, and cognition (pp.643–671).Washington, DC:American Psychological Association.

  • Winter, S. (1998). Evolution, categorization and values.Lund University Cognitive Studies,66,1–12.

Download references

Funding

This research received no specific grant from any funding agency in the public, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Flavio Osmo.

Ethics declarations

Ethical Approval

This article does not contain any studies with human participants performed by the author.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Osmo, F. An Integrative Hypothesis of Brain Evolution. Integr. psych. behav. 58, 462–466 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-023-09809-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-023-09809-5

Keywords

Navigation