Skip to main content
Log in

Adam Smith’s Non-foundationalism

  • Symposium: Understanding Happiness
  • Published:
Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article is part of a symposium (in Society) on a target article by Amitai Etzioni. Using that article as a point of departure, I take the opportunity to elaborate a reading of Adam Smith’s moral philosophy that sees it as quite non-foundationalist. Whereas foundationalism’s metaphor is a block or pillar, as non-foundationalism’s metaphor I suggest a spiral. I claim that non-foundationalism and Smithian liberalism dovetail.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The expression “doing-duty” seems apt for the motivation highlighted by Amitai. He describes it as “the sense one has after doing something considered to be a moral duty,” and “attempting to live up to moral commitments.” He proceeds to give as appellation for such motivation “affirmation.” It seems to me that doing one’s duty, avoiding disappointment, is what Amitai describes; it would be yet another step (though, admittedly, a small, natural step) to reflecting on one’s duty and doing-duty to experience affirmation (see Klein 2012, 270–271). So I refrain from using Amitai’s appellation (“affirmation”) and instead use “doing-duty.”

  2. Paul Simon, “You Can Call Me Al,” 1986.

  3. Numerous 18th and 19th century commentaries on TMS are contained in Reeder (1997), and several make “relativism”-related criticisms, including Thomas Reid (81–82, 87), Thomas Brown (152–156), James Mackintosh (164–166), Theodore Jouffroy (177, 180, 190, 198, 200), and James Anson Farrer (219–230). Cropsey (2001) holds that “Adam Smith’s explicit doctrine is that each man will act virtuously when he wins the approbation of his conscience, of ‘the man within the breast’” (21), which is wrong, I think. Similarly, see Prior (1949, 91), who seizes upon a passage in Smith (at 117.7, “Nature…what he himself approves of in other men”) that does, alas, lend itself to the interpretation that Prior gives it. Melzer (2001) criticizes Smith’s antifoundationalism, saying that Smith’s theory “tries to use the principle of manners to explain morals” (153).

  4. Smith writes of life in society as “the great school of self-command” at TMS 145.22 and 146.25.

  5. On the idea that the word should evolved from (or with), and may be understood as, (would) have been schooled to, and likewise for ought and owed, see Klein 2014.

  6. Smith affirms the organon at 17.3, n* on 46; 110.2 (“some secret reference”), 163-65.4-5, 193.12 (final sentence), 306.21 (final sentence), 325.14 (last three sentences). He also does so in the Correspondence, p. 49.

  7. For discussion on lexical ordering, see Griswold (1999, 82) and Forman-Barzilai (2010, 172, 174).

  8. On the wonder, surprise, and admiration evoked by those who impress us by the “uncommon and unexpected acuteness and comprehensiveness” of their sentiments, and the emulation of such exemplars, see 20.3, 75.3,114.3,192.11, 323.10, and 336.24.

  9. See entries in the Oxford English Dictionary, but the Online Etymological Dictionary suffices (http://www.etymonline.com/). The common roots of holy and whole remain clear in Swedish today: One would translate “the holiness of the whole” as heligheten av det hela or helhetens helighet.

  10. Going beyond humankind certainly makes sense; Smith speaks of “all rational and sensible beings” (237.6).

  11. Smith speaks of an impartial spectator being well informed at 130.32 and 294.94.

  12. I think that a subtle way in which Joy differs from any human being is that, outside of her interests deriving from the pleasures she finds in our good living, she has no other interests, or, if she does, they would have to pertain to matters off on another planet, as it were, with no connection to our good living. The following quotation about the Deity would, it seems to me, go also for Joy: “Benevolence may, perhaps, be the sole principle of action in the Deity, and there are several, not improbable, arguments which tend to persuade us that it is so” (305.18). But man, even when he is as virtuous as Adam Smith, “must often act from many other motives.”

  13. Incidentally, there is a curious feature of Part IV of TMS. Smith represents Hume as holding that “our whole approbation of virtue” comes from “the appearance of utility” (188.3, see also 179.2, 188.5, 327.17, as well as the title of Part IV, and of its chapters). Hume, however, in An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, distinguishes between utility and agreeableness—utility meaning useful to some further aim, agreeableness meaning immediately pleasurable (like in eating chocolate ice cream)—and Hume plainly, schematically holds that both utility and agreeableness go into moral approval, not just utility. (I should note that at 188.3 there is one sentence in which Smith indicates that agreeableness, too, is part of Hume’s theory.)

  14. I write overall propriety because, it seems to me, Smith uses propriety both with respect to an aspect of one’s conduct and with respect all aspects considered more holistically. The latter, described by Smith at 202.5, is what I mean by overall propriety, and it seems to be the sense Smith means in Part IV.

Further Reading

  • Burke, E. 1990. In A. Phillips (Ed.), A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coase, R. 1960. The Problem of Social Cost. Journal of Law and Economics, 3(October), 1–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cropsey, J. 2001. Polity and Economy: With Further Thoughts on the Principles of Adam Smith. South Bend: St. Augustine’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. 1915. The Elementary Forms of Religious Life. Trans. J.W. Swain. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, A. 2015. Happiness Is the Wrong Metric.

  • Fleischacker, S. 2004. On Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forman-Barzilai, F. 2010. Adam Smith and the Circles of Sympathy: Cosmopolitanism and Moral Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griswold, C. 1999. Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haakonssen, K. 1981. The Science of a Legislator: The Natural Jurisprudence of David Hume and Adam Smith. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. 1989. The Pretence of Knowledge. American Economic Review, 79(6), 3–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1998. In T. L. Beauchamp (Ed.), An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, D. B. 2012. Knowledge and Coordination: A Liberal Interpretation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, D. B. 2014. Ought as an Is: On the Positive-Normative Distinction. Studies in Emergent Order, 7, 56–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, D. B. 2015. Virtues, Layers, and Lens in Adam Smith’s The Theory of Moral Sentiments. GMU Working Paper in Economics No.15-06.

  • Matson, E. 2016. Ms. Humean Reason is a Calm Passion.

  • Melzer, A. M. 2001. Anti-anti-Foundationalism: Is a Theory of Moral Sentiments Possible? Perspectives on Political Science, 30(3), 151–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. 1949. Logic and the Basis of Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raphael, D. D., & Macfie, A. L. 1976. Introduction to The Theory of Moral Sentiments. In Raphael & Macfie (Eds.), Adam Smith’s The Theory of Moral Sentiments (pp. 1–52). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeder, J. (Ed.). 1997. On Moral Sentiments: Contemporary Responses to Adam Smith. Bristol: Thoemmes Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothschild, E. 2004. Dignity or Meanness. The Adam Smith Review, 1, 150–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. 1976a. In D. D. Raphael & A. L. Macfie (Eds.), The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. 1976b. In R. H. Campbell & A. S. Skinner (Eds.), The Wealth of Nations (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel B. Klein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Klein, D.B. Adam Smith’s Non-foundationalism. Soc 53, 278–286 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12115-016-0012-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12115-016-0012-x

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation