Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Spirit

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many religions and religious philosophies say that ultimate reality is a kind of primal energy (such as qi, mana, manitou, teotl, pneuma, and so on). This energy is often described as a vital power animating living things, as a spiritual force directing the organization of matter, or as a divine creative power which generates all things. By refuting older conceptions of primal energy, modern science opens the door to new and more precise conceptions. Primal energy is referred to here as ‘spirit’. But spirit is a natural power. A naturalistic theory of spirit is developed using ideas from information theory and thermodynamics, such as the maximum entropy production principle. Spirit drives the evolution of complexity at all levels of existence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Primal energies include Polynesian mana, Shinto musubi, Daoist qi (or ch’i), Stoic pneuma, Aztec teotl, Algonquian manitou, and so on. These concepts share the idea of life force generalized into an ultimate energy animating all things.

  2. Religious naturalists like Peters regard God as an impersonal energy or force (2002: chaps. 1 and 5). According to the Pew Forum (2008: 5), one in four Americans who believe in God also believe that God is an impersonal force.

  3. Subtle energy is common in New Age spiritualities (Albanese 1999). Along with these New Age and Eastern beliefs, one quarter of Americans affirm that physical things contain spiritual energy (Pew Forum 2009: 3).

  4. Hobbes thinks of spirit naturalistically as subtle matter (Answer to Bramhall, 309; The Elements of Law Natural and Politic, 1.XI.4). Descartes also says spirit is subtle matter (The Passions of the Soul, art. 10). At the end of the General Scholium, Newton uses the term ‘spirit’ to refer to a natural force which may be electricity. Henry More and Ralph Cudworth posited a spirit of nature which was spatially extended and which drove matter to organize itself into more complex forms. Hegel asserted that spirit drives the evolution of nature through historical phases of ever increasing complexity.

  5. The complexity of an organism has been defined as its number of distinct cell types (Bower 1988) or as its ratio of its non-protein-coding-DNA to its total DNA (Taft, Pheasant, and Mattick 2007). Both ways are consistent with each other and with physical complexity as energy-rate density.

  6. The activity of spirit in living things does not entail orthogenesis; on the contrary, it is entirely consistent with the neo-Darwinian synthesis. Spirit is not a substance; it must be understood in terms of the mathematical dynamics of complexity.

  7. It has been argued that Teilhard’s radial energy should be understood in thermodynamic terms as Gibbs free energy (Morowitz et al. 2005). Likewise Bergson’s élan vital should be understood in thermodynamic terms (DiFrisco 2015).

  8. Entropic forces (like all forces) are measured in newtons.

  9. As the universe approaches equilibrium, it will be a bunch of black holes. These may fuse into a single black hole or they may evaporate through Hawking radiation. So there will probably be later states closer to equilibrium. But the arguments made here depend only on the second law of thermodynamics; they do not depend on any further specific assumptions about the ultimate equilibrium state.

  10. Clausius formulated the second law like this: ‘Die Entropie der Welt strebt einem Maximum zu’—the entropy of the world strives to a maximum (see Prigogine and Stengers 1984: 119). This striving lies behind the MEPP and the claim that under certain conditions physical systems strive to increase their complexities.

  11. This argument has been used to explain the evolution of the earthly geochemical system (Kleidon 2010); the evolution of the earthly ecosystem (Vallino 2010); the evolution of plants (Dewar 2010); the evolution of cellular metabolic networks (Unrean and Srienc 2011). It explains the self-assembly of molecular structures (Belkin et al. 2015). Further examples in physics, chemistry, and biology are easy to find.

  12. On the third hypothesis, spirit is an extropic force derived from the MEPP; since the MEPP is a consequence of the second law, any extropic force is an entropic force. So the physical features of spirit resemble those of other entropic forces (such as depletion forces or elastic forces). Many depletion forces acting on molecules and molecular assemblies have strengths of a few kT per nanometer, thus producing forces in the piconewton range (Marenduzzo et al. 2006). So spirit acts with similar strengths. It changes the microstates of systems. But changes in microstates scale up to become changes in macrostates. So spirit acts at larger scales.

  13. The depth of an object (such as a bit string) is the amount of computational work needed to produce it (see Bennett 1988; Machta 2011).

  14. For a review of the writers who argue that historically accumulated order is intrinsic value, see Steinhart (2014: secs. 72–74).

  15. It seems to imply the existence of the best of all possible universes; but no such universe exists. It seems to maximize the number of things, but this maximization of the number of things conflicts with the maximization of value.

  16. Leibniz thought of these possibilities as bit strings (Rescher 1991: 191; Strickland 2006: 21–25). But bit strings are equivalent to pure sets. Thus, spirit ultimately flows through the arrows in the graph of the membership relation.

  17. Leibniz says that every possible strives for actuality; every essence strives for existence (1697: 86). He says that ‘Everything possible demands that it should exist’ (Leibniz, in Rescher 1991: 171). Here, every form strives to be instantiated.

  18. Leibniz says ‘Everything possible demands that it should exist, and hence will exist unless something else prevents it, which also demands that it should exist and is incompatible with the former’ (Leibniz, in Rescher 1991: 171).

  19. Leibniz says each potential has a tendency to actuality and that ‘the degree of this tendency [is] proportionate to the quantity of essence or reality, that is, to the degree of perfection of the possible involved’ (1697: 86). And again ‘the possible demands existence in its own nature, and indeed in proportion to its possibility or according to the degree of its essence’ (Leibniz, in Rescher 1991: 171–172; see also 206).

  20. The Ontological Argument for Spirit is inspired by the ontological arguments of Millican (2004) and Steinhart (2014: sec. 127).

  21. An improvement of a whole composed of parts is a whole composed of improvements of the parts. Suppose universe U contains parts A and B. The ways to improve A are A1 and A2 while the ways to improve B are B1 and B2. So the ways to improve U are {A, B1}, {A, B2}, {A1, B}, {A1, B1}, {A1, B2}, {A2, B}, {A2, B1}, {A2, B2}.

  22. For Plotinus, evil has no reality of its own; it is the privation of the good. Plotinus says it emerges from the conflicts among goods (Enneads, 4.4.32). And yet, since nature is animated by conflict, even this conflict is good (Enneads, 2.3.16). Evil is in the parts but the whole of reality is good (Enneads, 3.2.3, 3.2.11, 3.2.17, 4.4.32).

  23. It has been argued that the MEPP drives self-organizing systems into critical states (Dewar 2006). The MEPP is similar to the free-energy principle (Friston 2010), which has been extensively applied in neuroscience.

References

  • Albanese, C. (1999). The subtle energies of spirit: explorations in metaphysical and New Age spirituality. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 67(2), 305–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Annila, A., & Kuismanen, E. (2007). Natural hierarchy emerges from energy dispersal. BioSystems, 95, 227–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asakura, S., & Oosawa, F. (1958). Interaction between particles suspended in solutions of macromolecules. Journal of Polymer Science, 33, 183–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. (1998). Philosophical content and method of artificial life. In T. Bynum & J. Moor (Eds.), The digital phoenix: how computers are changing philosophy (pp. 135–152). Malden: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belkin, A., Hubler, A., & Bezryadin, A. (2015). Self-assembled wiggling nano-structures and the principle of maximum entropy production. Scientific Reports, 5(8323), 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, C. (1988). Logical depth and physical complexity. In R. Herken (Ed.), The Universal Turing Machine (pp. 227–257). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumenfeld, D. (1981). Leibniz’s theory of the striving possibles. In R. Woolhouse (Ed.), Leibniz: metaphysics and philosophy of science (pp. 77–88). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bower, J. (1988). The evolution of complexity by means of natural selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carhart-Harris, R., et al. (2014). The entropic brain: a theory of conscious states informed by neuroimaging research with psychedelic drugs. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 8(Article 20), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caroll, R. (2003). Entry on “energy”. In The Skeptic’s Dictionary (p. 119). Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons.

  • Chaisson, E. (2001). Cosmic evolution: the rise of complexity in nature. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dewar, R. (2006). Maximum entropy production and non-equilibrium statistical mechanics. In A. Kleidon & R. Lorenz (Eds.), Non-equilibrium thermodynamics and the production of entropy (pp. 41–55). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewar, R. (2010). Maximum entropy production and plant optimization theories. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 365, 1429–1435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiFrisco, J. (2015). Elan vital revisited: Bergson and the thermodynamic paradigm. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53(1), 54–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Filler, J. (2009). Newtonian forces and evolutionary biology: a problem and solution for extending the force interpretation. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 774–783.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: a unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, 127–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, B. (2005). The fabric of the cosmos. New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, J., & Gross, T. (2014). Self-organized criticality as a fundamental property of neural systems. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 8(Article 166), 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hidalgo, J., et al. (2014). Information-based fitness and the emergence of criticality in living systems. PNAS, 111(28), 10095–10100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1779/1990) Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. New York: Penguin.

  • Kang, L., et al. (2016). Entropic forces stabilize diverse emergent structures in colloidal membranes. Soft Matter, 12(2), 386–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (1995). At home in the universe: the search for the laws of self-organization and complexity. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kleidon, A. (2010). Non-equilibrium thermodynamics, maximum entropy production, and earth-system evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A, 368, 181–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. W. (1697). On the ultimate origination of the universe. In P. Schrecker & A. Schrecker (Eds.), (1988) Leibniz: Monadology and other philosophical essays (pp. 84–94). New York: Macmillan Publishing.

  • Lincoln, T., & Joyce, G. (2009). Self-sustained replication of an RNA enzyme. Science, 323(5918), 1229–1232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lineweaver, C. (2006). Cosmological and biological reproducibility: limits on the maximum entropy production principle. In A. Kleidon & R. Lorenz (Eds.), Non-equilibrium thermodynamics and the production of entropy (pp. 67–77). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machta, J. (2011). Natural complexity, computational complexity, and depth. Chaos, 21, 0371111–0371118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marenduzzo, D., Finan, K., & Cook, P. (2006). The depletion attraction: an underappreciated force driving cellular organization. Journal of Cell Biology, 175(5), 681–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martyushev, L., & Seleznev, V. (2006). Maximum entropy production principle in physics, chemistry, and biology. Physics Reports, 426, 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massobrio, P., et al. (2015). Criticality as a signature of healthy neural systems. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 9(Article 22), 1–3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millican, P. (2004). The one fatal flaw in Anselm’s argument. Mind, 113, 451–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mora, T., & Bialek, W. (2011). Are biological systems poised at criticality? Journal of Statistical Physics, 144, 268–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morowitz, H., Schmitz-Moormann, N., & Salmon, J. (2005). Teilhard’s two energies. Zygon, 40(3), 721–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, I. (2007). A history of thermodynamics: the doctrine of energy and entropy. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, K. (2002). Dancing with the sacred: evolution, ecology, and God. Harrisburg: Trinity Press International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pew Forum. (2008). U.S. religious landscape survey: religious beliefs and practices. Washington, DC: The Pew Forum on Religion & Public Life.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pew Forum. (2009). Many Americans mix multiple faiths: Eastern, New Age beliefs widespread. Washington, DC: The Pew Forum on Religion & Public Life.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1984). Order out of chaos. New York: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1991). G. W. Leibniz’s monadology: an edition for students. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (2010). Axiogenesis: an essay in metaphysical optimalism. New York: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roos, N. (2014). Entropic forces in Brownian motion. American Journal of Physics, 82(12), 1161–1166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharp, P. (2011). Buddhist enlightenment and the destruction of attractor networks. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 18(3–4), 137–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shew, W., & Plenz, D. (2012). The functional benefits of criticality in the cortex. The Neuroscientist, 19(1), 88–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1984). The nature of selection: evolutionary theory in philosophical focus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinhart, E. (2014). Your digital afterlives: computational theories of life after death. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stenger, V. (2001). The breath of God: identifying spiritual energy. In P. Kurtz (Ed.), Skeptical odysseys (pp. 363–374). Amherst: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephens, C. (2004). Selection, drift, and the ‘forces’ of evolution. Philosophy of Science, 71(4), 550–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strickland, L. (2006). Leibniz reinterpreted. New York: Continuum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swenson, R. (1997). Evolutionary theory developing: the problem(s) with Darwin’s dangerous idea. Ecological Psychology, 9(1), 47–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swenson, R. (2006). Spontaneous order, autocatakinetic closure, and the development of space-time. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 901, 311–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swenson, R. (2009). The fourth law of thermodynamics or the law of maximum entropy production (LMEP). Chemistry, 18(1), 333–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taft, R., Pheasant, M., & Mattick, J. (2007). The relationship between non-protein-coding DNA and eukaryotic complexity. BioEssays, 29(3), 288–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Unrean, P., & Srienc, F. (2011). Metabolic networks evolve towards states of maximum entropy production. Metabolic Engineering, 13(6), 666–673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vallino, J. (2010). Ecosystem biogeochemistry considered as a distributed metabolic network ordered by maximum entropy production. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 365, 1417–1427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wissner-Gross, A., & Freer, C. (2013). Causal entropic forces. Physics Review Letters, 110, 168702.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D. (2013). Information width: a way for the second law to increase complexity. In C. Lineweaver, P. Davies, & M. Ruse (Eds.), Complexity and the arrow of time (pp. 246–276). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Steinhart.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Steinhart, E. Spirit. SOPHIA 56, 557–571 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-017-0573-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-017-0573-1

Keywords

Navigation