Many explanations for the adoption of hybridised processes to tackle essentially criminal behaviour have been advanced (for discussion in relation to ASBOs, see Ashworth and Zedner 2014: 78ff). First, it has been suggested that the criminal law alone is inadequate in tackling certain forms of harm. A second, related, explanation is that there can be evidential benefits in resorting to civil processes, for example, the avoidance of the strict application of the hearsay rule in criminal proceedings.Footnote 22 Ashworth and Zedner (2014: 80) draw attention to a third, more political, account: they note that many countries ‘have seen a strain of penal populism in government statements and in legislative initiatives that are often presented as measures of public protection’ (see Dzur 2012: 116). A fourth explanation concerns policy transfer: civil measures have been used both in other jurisdictions and in other areas of domestic law (Ashworth and Zedner 2014: 81–82). Uniting all of this reasoning, however, is a sense of expediency—increasingly more common both within and outwith the UK, procedural hybrids are being first introduced and then employed with evident instrumentality. This paper not only queries the general legitimacy of such measures but uses the case study of civil recovery to illustrate their challenge to those rule of law standards already discussed.Footnote 23
The controversial civil recovery powers under Part 5 of POCA stemmed from concern that those engaged in organised criminal activity (so-called ‘Mr Bigs’) were beyond the reach of the criminal law; it was thought that the conventional approach of investigation, prosecution, conviction, punishment was not working. The ‘solution’ was this civil approach to seizing ‘criminal’ property without the need for criminal conviction and on the civil standard of proof—the balance of probabilities. There are many arguments advanced in favour of using a non-conviction based approach to seizing assets, including (1) to take the profit out of crime; (2) to disgorge property acquired through criminal acts; (3) to act as a deterrent; (4) to deprive wrongdoers of financial resources for future criminal activity, thereby acting as a form of prevention; (5) to disrupt criminal organisations; (6) to enable property to be restored to victims of crime; (7) to protect the community and to demonstrate that law enforcement is making efforts to tackle crime; and (8) to encourage cooperation between different law enforcement agencies (primarily through ‘equitable sharing’ or ‘incentivisation’) (see Cassella 2013: 99). Proponents of civil recovery contend that it is a civil process and, as such, does not require criminal procedural protections, that civil recovery operates in rem (against the property) rather than in personam (against the individual). Proponents also claim that civil recovery represents a necessary, proportionate response to growth in organised crime. It is often claimed that civil recovery abides by all human rights norms and, furthermore, that there are in-built safeguards to offer protection against abuse (see, for example, Cassella 2013, 2008; Cassidy 2009; Simser 2009; Kennedy 2005).Footnote 24 As we will argue, the courts have been overly acquiescent in accepting such claims.
The adoption of civil recovery in the UK followed in the footsteps of other jurisdictions that already had similar powers (see Kennedy 2006), but resort to civil law tools to tackle criminal activity was not a new phenomenon in the UK—as outlined at the outset of this article, the UK government has a long history of using civil tools in this manner. Zedner (2009: 81) discusses civil preventive measures which ‘circumvent the protections of the criminal process by operating in parallel systems of questionable justice: according to the less exacting requirements of the civil process or enforced via hybrid systems in which breach of civil orders result in criminal sanctions’. Although her discussion concerned civil orders such as ASBOs, control orders, and serious crime prevention orders,Footnote 25 a similar complaint can be made in relation to civil recovery under POCA. While there is no threat of imprisonment, civil recovery orders permit deprivation of property in civil proceedings on the grounds that that property constitutes proceeds of crime—another example of a ‘parallel system […] of questionable justice’ to circumvent criminal procedural protections.
Civil Recovery and POCA 2002
POCA 2002 was introduced specifically to remedy perceived failures of existing criminal justice processes in tackling serious and organised crime. Most problematic in this regard is the supposedly hierarchical structureFootnote 26 of such criminal activity, where:
[M]any major criminal figures have become untouchable by criminal prosecution. They organise or finance the criminal activity of others and profit from the results, but remain remote from the commission of particular crimes. That often makes it impossible for law enforcement authorities to build a case against them. (Proceeds of Crime Bill, HC Deb, 30 October 2001, vol. 373, c. 760, per Minister Denham)
It is this remoteness from the ‘coal-face’ that causes most difficulties for conventional law enforcement. Where organised crime syndicates do operate hierarchically, the main beneficiaries (i.e., the ‘organisers’) of their activities are said to be insulated against successful police investigation, prosecution, and conviction. What is highlighted here are the perceived inadequacies of conventional criminal justice tools in coping with hierarchically organised criminal activity, and the extent of the problems allegedlyFootnote 27 faced by law enforcement. Indeed, when one considers that it is the primary function of the legal system to ‘establish and stabilize societal expectations through the handling of disappointment’ (Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos 2010: 71; Luhmann 1985, 2004) and thus to provide constancy within society, this supposed ‘failure’ of the criminal law has the same effect as a genuine failure. What, then, is the legal system to do in such a situation? The options available are made clearer by considering further the idea of legal-systemic expectations.
The legal system relies upon expectations as a means of controlling normativity, reducing complexity, and eliminating contingency. Expectations are generated on the basis of norms that, even in the event of their disappointment, remain unaffected—in this manner, existing normative expectations are stabilised on a counterfactual basis. This is a particularly familiar situation within the field of criminal law where, for example, criminal behaviour ought to be subject to legal sanction, wrongdoers ought to be punished, crime should not pay, and so on. In spite of their repeated disappointment, these normative expectations stay stable, and illegal conduct remains exactly that. Although necessary in terms of reducing complexity by limiting the number of possible selections generated by conditions of uncertainty, the effect of this systemic normative closure is that disappointments do not lead to the legal system learning from its previous operations. For systemic learning to occur, the legal system is instead reliant on its cognitive expectations, which is to say, on its openness to changing factual conditions within society. It is through this cognitive openness that the law is able to adapt—the legal system’s programming adjusts both to deal with changes in its environment and to become more successful in the realisation of its primary function. Such programming is guidance for the operation of the system’s binary coding; it stipulates the conditions under which the coding lawful/unlawful can be applied, and is the means by which the legal system modifies itself to recognise that, for example, something that was lawful is now unlawful, or vice versa.
In this regard, the introduction of these hybrid civil recovery powers can be understood as an endeavour to stabilise the normative expectation that the legal system will counteract and ‘punish’Footnote 28 criminal and thus illegal activity within society. At the same time, however, and through the new procedures introduced, the legislation adjusts the system-internal programming that guides the lawful/unlawful distinction. This situation results directly from the criminal law’s perceived inadequacy to deal with the particular challenges of serious and organised crime: the importance of this attrition in terms of the law’s self-regulation cannot be overstated. This alleged failure of law, this apparently continuing disappointment of its normative expectation over time, was what gave rise to these wholesale procedural changes. In its adoption of such a hybrid approach, we see the supposed failure of law being concretised through procedure (Hendry and King 2015).
The next section scrutinises the jurisprudence of civil recovery and analyses the effects of these in rem measures. At this juncture, however, it is worth emphasising the following: as a criminal justice strategy, civil recovery is overtly normative in its stance that criminal activity should not pay, is instrumentally engaged in undermining the profit incentive of organised criminal behaviour, and—by using civil rather than criminal procedures—deliberately prioritises this motive over compliance with procedural safeguards inherent to the criminal process in the UK.
Civil Recovery in the Courts
As the primary legislation providing for asset recovery, POCA makes provision for both post-conviction confiscation of assets (POCA, Parts 2–4) and non-conviction based confiscation of the proceeds of unlawful conduct, labelled ‘civil recovery’ (Part 5).Footnote 29 Despite our focus resting upon the latter, distinguishing the two forms is vital: while actions under civil recovery (POCA, Part 5) do not require a criminal conviction, it is only subsequent to a conviction that a confiscation order (POCA, Parts 2–4) can be made. With such a post-conviction confiscation order, all of the enhanced procedural protections of the criminal process apply at the criminal trial, including the presumption of innocence, the standard of proof beyond reasonable doubt, and exclusionary rules of evidence, for example, the rule against hearsay. It is only post-conviction, at the confiscation hearing, that the standard of proof employed is the civil one—the balance of probabilities—and there the rules of evidence are akin to those in a sentencing hearing (Alldridge 2014a: 173–174). By contrast, a civil recovery order can be granted even in the absence of criminal conviction, and ‘whether or not any proceedings have been brought for an offence in connection with the property’ (POCA, s. 240(2)), including instances where defendants have been acquitted in criminal proceedings (Taher 2006)Footnote 30 or even where a conviction has been quashed (Olden 2010). The civil rules of evidence apply, meaning that both character and hearsay evidence can be admitted, as can evidence obtained by improper means (Olden 2010), and the standard of proof is on a balance of probabilities (POCA, s. 241(3)). Finally, a confiscation order operates in personam, while a civil recovery order operates in rem.
Part 5 of POCA enables the ‘enforcement authority’ to recover, in civil proceedings, property that is, or represents, property obtained through unlawful conduct (POCA, s. 240).Footnote 31 Given the perceived inadequacies of existing criminal legal processes and the attendant difficulties in securing criminal conviction, post-conviction confiscation was often impossible—the result of this was that the benefits of non-conviction-based approaches in this purely instrumental regard were increasingly proclaimed. Nevertheless, and although these processes have made strides in terms of efficacy, it is hard not to rue their introduction as a privileging of instrumentality over considerations of due process, not least because there are manifest reasons for the enhanced procedural safeguards inherent in the criminal process. As Roberts and Zuckerman (2010: 247) articulate in relation to the heightened standard of proof, ‘[t]his asymmetrical standard is not a natural or inevitable incident of allocating probative burdens; it is, rather, an additional commitment, over and above requiring the prosecution to prove guilt, to the presumption of innocence and its animating liberal philosophy of respect for persons’. By requiring this elevated standard of proof, the criminal process establishes itself as innately risk-averse,Footnote 32 with a wrongful conviction being perceived as far worse than a wrongful acquittal.Footnote 33 Criminal law’s ‘asymmetric standard’ can be considered, therefore, as a prophylactic measure against an erroneous trial outcome (i.e., a false conviction) or, in systems-theoretical language, a ‘bulwark’ against systemic excess.Footnote 34 We consider this, first, concerning the ‘civil’ nature of the proceedings under Part 5 of POCA and, second, in relation to those due process concerns that arise as a result of this kind of hybridised procedure.
‘Civil’ and ‘criminal’ processes have traditionally been distinguished on the basis of a variety of factors, including inter alia: subjective/objective culpability, harm, the role of a prosecution authority, the extent of investigatory powers available to the State, evidential rules, punishment, and stigma (see Hall 1943; Ashworth 2000). Far from being a mere semantic distinction, in practice it means that while ‘civil’ processes operate under lesser burdens, processes designated as ‘criminal’ attract for the accused enhanced procedural protections as additional commitments. Civil recovery, as the name suggests, purports to be a civil process and, importantly, has been held not to be of a criminal characterFootnote 35 in spite of its ‘potential for use as an uneasy and unsatisfactory substitute for the criminal process’ (Rees et al. 2011: para. 6.13). Indeed, the courts have been consistent on this position. Perhaps the leading case on this issue is Walsh where, on considering whether such proceedings are criminal for the purposes of Article 6 of the ECHR,Footnote 36 both Coghlin J (Re the Director of the Assets Recovery Agency, 2004) and the Court of Appeal (Walsh 2005) concluded that civil recovery proceedings under Part 5 of POCA should be classified as civil proceedings.Footnote 37 The three criteria established by the Strasbourg Court in Engel (1979–80) were: the domestic classification of the proceedings at issue, the nature of the offence in question, and the nature and severity of the penalty that may be imposed. Applying these criteria, it was held that:
[A]ll the available indicators point strongly to this case being classified in the national law as a form of civil proceeding. The appellant is not charged with a crime. Although it must be shown that he was guilty of unlawful conduct in the sense that he has acted contrary to the criminal law, this is not for the purpose of making him amenable as he would be if he had been convicted of crime. He is not liable to imprisonment or fine if the recovery action succeeds. There is no indictment and no verdict. The primary purpose of the legislation is restitutionary rather than penal. (Walsh 2005: para. 27 (per Kerr LCJ delivering the judgment of the court))
Similar considerations applied in relation to the second Engel criterion, with Kerr LCJ stating:
The allegation made against the appellant does not impute guilt of a specific offence; the proceedings do not seek to impose a penalty other than the recovery of assets acquired through criminal conduct; and they are initiated by the director of an agency, which, although it is a public authority, has no prosecutorial function or competence. (ibid: para. 29)
The final criterion was also dealt with rather dismissively, with civil recovery being described as a preventative measure: ‘After all, the person who is required to yield up the assets does no more than return what he obtained illegally.’ (ibid: para. 38) Kerr LCJ also dismissed the argument that, viewed cumulatively, the Engel criteria ought to result in civil recovery being held as criminal in character:
The essence of Art 6 in its criminal dimension is the charging of a person with a criminal offence for the purpose of securing a conviction with a view to exposing that person to criminal sanction. These proceedings are obviously and significantly different from that type of application. They are not directed towards him in the sense that they seek to inflict punishment beyond the recovery of assets that do not lawfully belong to him. As such, while they will obviously have an impact on the appellant, these are predominantly proceedings in rem. They are designed to recover the proceeds of crime, rather than to establish, in the context of criminal proceedings, guilt of specific offences. The cumulative effect of the application of the tests in Engel is to identify these clearly as civil proceedings. (ibid: para. 41)
The robustness of this judicial position is disconcerting, however, not least because, in spite of civil recovery’s adoption of civil processes, it is still evidently concerned with allegations of criminal wrongdoing.Footnote 38 We say ‘evidently’ because, revisiting the underlying policy, the stated aim in introducing civil recovery was for it to be a more effective tool in dealing with ‘criminal Mr Bigs’ (Proceeds of Crime Bill, HC Deb, 30 October 2001, vol. 373, c. 803, per Mr McCabe). That there was a clear punitive purpose underpinning this draconian power is simply undeniable.Footnote 39 In applying the Engel criteria to civil recovery under Part 5 of POCA, the UK courts appear to have failed to recognise what civil recovery actually is, which is to say, a wholly instrumental approach conceived to employ civil law processes in pursuing criminal law objectives, and to circumvent those procedural safeguards that inhere in a criminal trial. This is deeply unsatisfactory on two counts. First, the courts over-rely upon the first limb of the Engel test, itself not decisive—however much the legislative intent was to design a civil procedure, this alone is insufficient (Özturk 1984; also Trechsel 2005: 18). We must instead consider what was actually created: intention does not dictate substance (King 2012: 347). In their overly deferential stance regarding the legislative label ‘civil,’ the courts have clearly failed to ensure the adequate protection of individual rights. Second, it is the duty of the courts to scrutinise the behaviour of Parliament and prevent the excessive exercise of political power. We submit that the application of a civil label to a criminal procedure, and the resultant erosion of due process rights and standards that would apply in the event that ‘civil’ recovery were to be properly regarded as a criminal procedure, constitutes such an excessive exercise of power. Furthermore, this can be framed specifically in terms of the rule of law: as Lord Woolf (1995: 68) stated, ‘ultimately there are limits on the supremacy of Parliament which it is the courts’ inalienable responsibility to identify and uphold’. Due process rights safeguard against systemic excess, and their maintenance and application is the task of the courts; this critique is elaborated upon in the final section.
The second and third Engel criteria provide further avenues for critique. Kerr LCJ is correct to say in terms of the second criterion that civil recovery proceedings do ‘not impute guilt of a specific offence’ (Walsh 2005: para. 29). They do, however, allow the State to make general allegations of criminality,Footnote 40 a lack of specificity that simply would not suffice in criminal proceedings. As for the third and final limb, and in spite of the emphasis resting on the ‘proceeds of crime,’ while civil recovery is presented as recouping ill-gotten gains, in essence it operates as a sanction on criminal wrongdoing. Focusing merely on the return of illegal gains without recognising the full implications of the civil recovery order is trite—an individual subject to such an order will not only suffer deprivation of his/her assets but the label and stigma of being a ‘criminal,’ if not in law, then at least in the eyes of his/her fellow citizens.Footnote 41 To suggest that under such circumstances the individual is not being punished, that there is no imputation of criminal liability, and that in rem civil recovery proceedings concentrate solely on property, is to be entirely disingenuous about what civil recovery entails.Footnote 42
The Utility of a Systems-Theoretical Perspective
While the designation of the civil recovery hybrid procedure as either criminal or civil is, as we have argued, a problematic one for the UK courts, systems theory encounters no such problems; on the contrary, it accommodates this distinction with ease. This can be credited to the manner by which the legal system’s binary code ascertains the relevance or otherwise of societal communications and distinguishes them system-internally. The civil/criminal dichotomy is encompassed by the systemic code lawful/unlawful, and thus is included within the unity of the legal system—it is only once the communication has been deemed of relevance to the legal system that further systemic programmes are required to distinguish between these values. As Luhmann explains: ‘Since the values legal and illegal are not in themselves criteria for the decision between legal and illegal, there must be further points of view that indicate whether or not and how the values of a code are to be allocated, rightly or wrongly’ (Luhmann 2004: 192). Programmes, as system-internal semantic elements, are the ‘vehicles of connection between the code and the world-at-large’ (Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos 2010: 74), and operate by linking self-reference with external reference.
It is within such programmes that rules of procedure are situated in the legal system. Their charge in this regard is the recursive application of norms to the application of norms (Luhmann 2004: 158), with all of these operations being undertaken to realise the legal system’s primary function, that is, the stabilisation of normative expectations over time. This can be articulated in terms of our case study: when existing strategies of criminal law enforcement were deemed unfit for the purpose of tackling the complexities of organised crime, the introduction of civil recovery via POCA 2002 was a direct reaction to the disappointment of the normative expectation that crime should not pay. That is not to say that the autopoietic legal system engages at any point with issues of either the moral content of the law or the policy motivations for legislative change—there is no consideration, for example, of the crime control ideology underpinning ‘follow-the-money’ approaches, or the overt political and normative instrumentality of civil recovery, indeed there could not be. No, where civil recovery has brought about a restructuring of legal systemic programming and, in turn, a reorientation of its rules of criminal and civil procedure, the system itself is only aware of these as system-internal reactions to the repeated disappointment of its normative expectations. Moreover, by virtue of its inclusion within the unity of the legal system, civil recovery accords to the systemic eigen-value of validity.
It is, however, not about the legal validity of a practice that sees a civil standard of proof employed within a criminal mechanism that we have reservations. Rather, we query the legitimacy of civil recovery with specific reference to those procedural standards contained within the rule of law that, we argue, are being eroded by the disastrous combination of legislative excess in implementing POCA and the subsequent judicial failure to protect individual due process rights in the courts.