Skip to main content
Log in

A Pilgrimage Through John Martin Fischer’s Deep Control: Essays on Free Will and Value

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

John Martin Fischer’s most recent collection of essays, Deep Control: Essays on Free Will and Value, is both incredibly wide-ranging and impressively detailed. Fischer manages to cover a staggering amount of ground in the free will debate, while also providing insightful and articulate analyses of many of the positions defended in the field. In this collection, Fischer focuses on the relationship between free will and moral responsibility. In the first section of his book, Fischer defends Frankfurt cases as an important and useful tool in rejecting the necessity of regulative control for moral responsibility. In the second section, Fischer turns his attention to his own account of guidance control. In this essay, I first focus on Fischer’s defense of Frankfurt cases, specifically his response to the argument that the assumption of determinism in such cases is question-begging. I then analyze two objections to Fischer’s account of guidance control. Finally, I conclude with a brief discussion of the metaphor of the pilgrimage, which Fischer introduces in the opening essay of his collection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some philosophers also accept an autonomy or authenticity condition where, in order for an agent to be responsible for her behavior, she must in some way be the authentic source of her actions. For an account of such an authenticity condition, see Daniel Dennett’s Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting (1984). Many philosophers also argue that there is a tracing component to moral responsibility. By tracing back to a time when an agent fulfills the epistemic and control conditions, we can understand how an individual can be responsible for a given act even though she doesn’t fulfill the epistemic or control conditions at the time she commits the act. Fischer, along with co-author Neal Tognazzini, tackles this issue in the essay, “The Triumph of Tracing” (Fischer 2012, 206–233).

  2. One could also defend a weaker epistemic condition, one that requires agents to justifiably believe that they are performing a certain act in order to be responsible for that act.

  3. The original version of this case can be found in Fischer (1982).

  4. Though many compatibilists maintain the two are compatible. See Lehrer (1976), Horgan (1979), Lewis (1981), Campbell (1997), and Vihvelin (2000).

  5. Though Frankfurt does not include a prior sign in his original case, he does note the possibility of doing so in a footnote: “We can imagine that Jones4 has often confronted the alternatives—A and B—that he now confronts, and that his face has invariably twitched when he was about to decide to do A and never when he was about to decide to do B. Knowing this, and observing the twitch, Black would have a basis for his prediction” (Frankfurt 1969, 835).

  6. See Ginet (1996), Kane (1996), and Widerker (1995).

  7. For examples of those who take on the second horn of the Dilemma Defense, see Hunt (2000), McKenna (2003), and Mele and Robb (1998).

  8. Furthermore, there are some compatibilists who contend that we cannot be morally responsible unless determinism is true or, less demandingly, unless deterministic causal relations can obtain. For example: Ayer (1954), Hobart (1934), Nowell-Smith (1948), and Smart (1961). These theorists in particular must be able to respond to the first horn of the Dilemma Defense.

  9. Fischer argues that this case would be similar to David Hunt and Derk Pereboom’s “Buffer Zone” cases, which are presented in response to the indeterministic horn of the Dilemma Defense (Hunt 2000; Pereboom 2001).

  10. Vihvelin’s full case can be found in Deep Control on p. 56 and in Vihvelin (2000).

  11. If this were to occur, then Black would have a false belief about the coin flip. Fischer grants that Black can have knowledge about the future, but this does not mean that Black is infallible. If he were incapable of having false beliefs, then this would call into question whether the coin really could have come up tails. Rather, Black has human foreknowledge, as opposed to divine foreknowledge. He can know contingent propositions; this doesn’t make these propositions necessary. Fischer clarifies: “Although the conditional ‘If Black knows that p, then p is true’ can be necessary, this necessity does not attach to the consequent of the conditional, even given the truth of the antecedent” (Fischer 2012, 59).

  12. Fischer also responds to arguments for premise 3 of the dilemma defended by Ishtiyaque Haji, Robert Kane, and Alfred Mele (Fischer 2012, 99–101). Though it is beyond the scope of this review essay to discuss the specifics of these objections and replies, Fischer provides an excellent and comprehensive discussion of the problem of luck.

  13. Where a “mechanism” is to be understood as a process or way of making decisions and producing actions (Fischer 2012, 186).

  14. Of course, Fischer importantly does not require agents to be able to do otherwise in order to be morally responsible. So, this sentence is best interpreted as the claim that Schmidt’s voting mechanism wouldn’t have the capacity to properly weigh such information in that time.

  15. Indeed, Fischer grants that the agoraphobe is reasons-responsive. And though Fischer argues that the agoraphobe is insufficiently reasons-responsive to warrant attributions of responsibility, this is because he is responsive to very few reasons, which is presumably not the case with Schmidt.

References

  • Ayer, A.J. 1954. “Freedom and Necessity,” in A.J. Ayer, Philosophical Essays. New York: St. Martin’s Press: 3–20.

  • Borges, J. 1944. "The Garden of Forking Paths," Fictions. London: Calder and Boyars: 81–92.

  • Campbell, J. 1997. “A Compatibilist Theory of Alternative Possibilities,” Philosophical Studies 88: 319–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 1984. Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1986. Harm to Self. Volume Three: The Moral Limits of the Law. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Fischer, J.M. 2012. Deep Control: Essays on Free Will and Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J.M. 2004. “Responsibility and Manipulation,” Journal of Ethics 8: 145–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J.M. 1999. “Recent Work on Moral Responsibility,” Ethics 110: 93–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J.M. 1982. “Responsibility and Control,” Journal of Philosophy 79: 24–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. 1969. “Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility,” Journal of Philosophy 66: 829–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. 1996. “In Defense of the Principle of Alternative Possibilities: Why I Don’t Find Frankfurt’s Argument Convincing,” Philosophical Perspectives 10: 403–417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobart, R.E. 1934. “Free Will as Involving Determinism and Inconceivable Without It,” Mind 43: 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. 1979. “‘Could,’ Possible Worlds, and Moral Responsibility,” Southern Journal of Philosophy 17: 345–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hunt, D. 2000. “Moral Responsibility and Unavoidable Action,” Philosophical Studies 97: 195–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kane, R. 1996. The Significance of Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. 1976. “‘Can’ in Theory and Practice: A Possible Worlds Analysis,” M. Brand and D. Walton (eds.) Action Theory, Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Co.: 241–70.

  • Lewis, D. 1981. “Are We Free to Break the Laws?” Theoria 47: 113–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Long, T. 2004. “Moderate Reasons-Responsiveness, Moral Responsibility, and Manipulation,” in Joseph Campbell, Michael O’Rourke, and David Shier (eds.) Freedom and Determinism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press: 151–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. 2008. “A Hard-Line Reply to Pereboom’s Four-Case Manipulation Argument,” Phenomenological Research 77: 142–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. 2003. “Robustness, Control, and the Demand for Morally Significant Alternatives,” in David Widerker and Michael McKenna (eds.) Moral Responsibility and Alternative Possibilities. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate Press: 201–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. 2000. “Reactive Attitudes, Reactivity, and Omissions,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61: 447–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. and Robb, B. 1998. Rescuing Frankfurt-Style Cases,” Philosophical Review 107: 97–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowell-Smith, P.H. 1948. “Free Will and Moral Responsibility,” Mind 57: 45–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Otsuka, M. 1998. “Incompatibilism and the Avoidability of Blame,” Ethics 108: 685–701.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. 2001. Living without Free Will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Smart, J.J.C. 1961. “Free-Will, Praise, and Blame,” Mind 70: 291–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Speak. D. 2007. “The Impertinence of Frankfurt-style Argument,” The Philosophical Quarterly 57: 76–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vihvelin, K. 2000. “Freedom, Foreknowledge, and the Principle of Alternate Possibilities,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30: 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Widerker, D. 1995. “Libertarianism and Frankfurt’s Attack on the Principle of Alternative Possibilities,” Philosophical Review 104: 247–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I’d like to thank Michael McKenna for his guidance and his valuable remarks on earlier drafts of this essay. I am also grateful to John Martin Fischer, whose work on free will and moral responsibility has been hugely influential in my thinking on these matters.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hannah Tierney.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Tierney, H. A Pilgrimage Through John Martin Fischer’s Deep Control: Essays on Free Will and Value . Criminal Law, Philosophy 10, 179–196 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9301-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9301-x

Keywords

Navigation