Skip to main content
Log in

The Consequence Argument and the Possibility of the Laws of Nature Being Violated

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a recent paper, Brian Cutter objected to the consequence argument due to its dependence on the principle that miracle workers are metaphysically impossible. A miracle worker is someone who has the ability to act in a way such that the laws of nature would be violated. While there is something to the thought that agents like us do not have this ability, Cutter claims that there is no compelling reason to regard miracle workers as metaphysically impossible. However, the paper contends that miracle workers are indeed impossible according to well-known theories concerning the laws of nature. This result highlights the reliance of the consequence argument on a plausible premise, which is widely accepted by proponents of non-Humean views of laws. The paper also provides a way to explain away the intuition that miracle workers are possible, but this has the upshot that a recent, two-dimensional formulation of the consequence argument is unsound.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As noted by an anonymous reviewer, Cutter’s assertion that NL is “clearly” contingent may be deemed overly assertive: the way that NL is “clearly” contingent seems to depend on NFL being clearly false; but it isn’t clearly false. Now, I think the reason why NL seems clearly contingent is that most philosophers think that L is contingent, and since N is a factive operator, if L is contingent, NL will be contingent as well.

  2. For replies to Campbell along these lines, see Bailey (2012), Loss (2009, 2010), Brueckner (2008). See also Campbell (2008, 2009).

  3. By Lewis’s response I literally mean Lewis’s own reply to the consequence argument that presupposes his theory of counterfactuals. Some philosophers, such as Kadri Vivhvelin (2013), argue that the Lewisian response does not depend on Lewis’s theory of counterfactuals, since it only relies on a distinction between weak and strong abilities that may be accepted by a form of compatibilism that permits laws to be fixed. If this is correct, then the miracle workers problem might well turn out to be a problem similar to the Necessary Fixity of the Past. But because this view is far from being popular, my focus here will be on the Necessary Fixity of the Laws.

  4. It is interesting to see though that NL follows from \(\Box L\) without assuming (\(\alpha \)), but only the Lewisian duality, where \(\Diamond {\hspace{-4pt}}\rightarrow \) stands for the might-counterfactual:

    (L):

    \(\phi \Diamond {\hspace{-4pt}}\rightarrow \psi \dashv \vdash \mathord {\sim }(\phi \Box {\hspace{-4.1pt}}\rightarrow \mathord {\sim }\psi )\)

    The following proof becomes available:

  5. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.

  6. Here is a more detailed formulation of the argument:

    1. 1.

      \( Can(s,a) \& (Does(s,a) \Diamond {\hspace{-4pt}}\rightarrow \mathord {\sim }L)\), assumption.

    2. 2.

      \( Can(s,a) \supset \Diamond (Does(s,a) \& L)\), from (Background Assumption).

    3. 3.

      Can(sa), from 1.

    4. 4.

      \( \Diamond (Does(s,a) \& L)\), from 2 and 3.

    5. 5.

      \( \Diamond (Does(s,a) \& L) \rightarrow (Does(s,a) \Box {\hspace{-4.1pt}}\rightarrow L)\), from (NP).

    6. 6.

      \(Does(s,a) \Box {\hspace{-4.1pt}}\rightarrow L\), from 5 and 6.

    7. 7.

      \(Does(s,a) \Diamond {\hspace{-4pt}}\rightarrow \mathord {\sim }L\), from 1.

  7. I’m grateful to an anonymous reviewer for bringing this to my attention.

References

  • Bailey, A. M. (2012). Incompatibilism and the past. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85, 351–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. (2000). The nongoverning conception of laws of nature. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61, 571–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. (2003). Local miracle compatibilism. Noûs, 37(2), 258–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2005). The dispositionalist conception of laws. Foundations of Science, 10, 353–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brueckner, A. (2008). Retooling the consequence argument. Analysis, 68(1), 10–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. K. (2007). Free will and the necessity of the past. Analysis, 67(2), 105–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. K. (2008). Reply to Brueckner. Analysis, 68, 264–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. K. (2010). Incompatibilism and fatalism: Reply to loss. Analysis, 70, 71–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, J. W. (1994). Laws of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cutter, B. (2017). What is the consequence argument an argument for? Analysis, 77(2), 278–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demarest, H. (2015). Fundamental properties and the laws of nature. Philosophical Compass, 10(5), 334–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demarest, H. (2017). Powerful properties, powerless laws. In J. Jacobs (Ed.), Putting Powers to Work: Causal Powers in Contemporary Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, P. A. (2008). A defense of local miracle compatibilism. Philosophical Studies, 140, 65–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gustafsson, J. (2017). A strengthening of the consequence argument for incompatibilism. Analysis, 77, 705–715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2000). Van Inwagen’s consequence argument. The Philosophical Review, 109(4), 525–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kimpton-Nye, S. (2017). Humean laws in an unhumean world. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 3(2), 129–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lampert, F., & Merlussi, P. (2021). Counterfactuals, counteractuals, and free choice. Philosophical Studies, 178, 445–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lampert, F., & Merlussi, P. (2021). How(not) to construct worlds with responsibility. Synthese, 199(3–4), 10389–10413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2009). Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, N., & McKenna, M. (2009). Recent work on free will and moral responsibility. Philosophy Compass, 4(1), 96–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13, 455–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1981). Are we free to break the laws? Theoria, 47, 113–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loew, C., & Jaag, S. (2020). Humean laws and (nested) counterfactuals. Philosophical Quarterly, 70(278), 93–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oakley, S. (2006). Defending Lewis’s local miracle compatibilism. Philosophical Studies, 130(2), 337–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pendergraft, G. (2010). The explanatory power of local miracle compatibilism. Philosophical Studies, 156, 249–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pruss, A. R. (2013). Incompatibilism proved. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 43, 430–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1962). Paradox. Scientific American (April), 84–96.

  • Tooley, M. (1987). Causation: A Realist Approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1983). An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warfield, T. (2000). Causal determinism and human freedom are incompatible: a new argument for incompatibilism. Philosophical Perspectives, 14, 167–80.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I extend my gratitude to the two anonymous reviewers of Philosophia for providing invaluable feedback that significantly enhanced thequality of this paper. Huge thanks also go to Célia Teixeira and Marcos Klemz for their insightful comments on an early draft presentedat the LEME seminar in Rio. And of course, special thanks to Sergio Miranda, Fabio Lampert, Sagid Salles, and Iago Bozza for theirawesome discussions that really enriched the topics covered here.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pedro Merlussi.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Merlussi, P. The Consequence Argument and the Possibility of the Laws of Nature Being Violated. Philosophia (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00726-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-024-00726-4

Keywords

Navigation