Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

On the Massness of Mass Extinction

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The central question in this paper is whether anthropogenic mass extinction is ethically problematic above and beyond the sum of extinctions involved. The point of asking this question is not to determine the ethical status of anthropogenic massive extinction, which is clearly ethical horrendous. It is to see if - as is the case with interrogating the wrongness and badness of extinction - answering it illuminates something about the value of what is being lost and sharpens the considerations that substantiate the view; and, if so, whether that might be useful in the context of evaluating mooted approaches to mitigating or adapting to it. The view defended is that massive extinction driven by undermining the conditions that make life forms possible for diverse and higher taxonomic groups constitutes a planetary shift, a phase change, different in kind from merely accelerated anthropogenic change. Justified partiality to the current assemblages of species and biomes is grounded in human relationships, dependencies, histories, and connections with this particular planetary state. This partiality warrants recognizing the loss of this state of the planet - these biospheric conditions, species assemblages, and biomes - as bad, above and beyond the individual harms and species losses involved. This account explains and substantiates why a mass extinction is worse than an equal number of extinctions spread over multiple systems or planets, all other things being equal. This account also provides reason not to embrace the anthropocene or embark on a synthetic age.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A brief note on methodology and terminology. Thought experiments and common beliefs are not here treated as arguments or justification, though they are in a sense (debunkable) data points. They are used to motivate and sometimes clarify a view or idea. In this case, it is the view that species matter above and beyond the individual organisms that comprise them (which, in this section, is the explanandum). The question then is whether this view can be accommodated (i.e. is consistent with) or explained (i.e. can be accounted for) by theoretical accounts that operate over that space and, in turn, whether those accounts can be substantiated (i.e. arguments and other considerations provided in support of them). If it cannot be accommodated, then either the view or the theoretical account needs revision. So, the question being posed here is whether it is possible to provide an account (in this case, one that encompasses the value of species) that can not only accommodate the view that they matter above and beyond the individuals involved, and explain why that is, but that can also be substantiated. For example, in what follows I argue that the view that species have interests or a welfare above and beyond that of the individuals that comprise them can accommodate and explain the intuition/common belief, but it cannot itself be substantiated. In contrast, the view that species have value in virtue of their being unique forms of life can do all three, so it is a more justified account (all other things being equal). If there was no alternative account, or if there were strong ancillary considerations (e.g. good welfarist arguments) then there would be a choice to make about whether to accept the unsubstantiated theory or give up the common belief, for example. So the criteria for evaluating theoretical accounts that are operating in the background here are accuracy (i.e. does the account improve understanding by mapping well the features in the space over which it is theorizing as evidenced by substantiated explanations) and practical usefulness (i.e. does the theory help enable activities it is meant to support, such as making accurate additional inferences, working through problems of particular kinds, or making reliable predictions). For discussion and defense of this general methodology see Bengson et al. (in press).

References

  • Anthropocene Working Group, International Union of Geological Sciences. (2021). http://quaternary.stratigraphy.org/working-groups/anthropocene/. Accessed 11 Nov 2021

  • Baier, A. (1995). Moral Prejudices. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillie, J. E., Hilton-Taylor, C., & Stuart, S. N. (2004). A global species assessment. International Union for Conservation of nature (IUCN).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Basl, J. (2019). The death of the ethics of life. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Basl, J., & Sandler, R. (2013). The good of non-sentient entities: Organisms, artifacts, and synthetic biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44(4), 697–705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, A., et al. (2021). Anthropocene: Event or epoch? Nature, 597, 332. https://doi.org/10.1038/d41586-021-02448-z

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bendik-Keymer, J. (2017). Anthropogenic mass extinction. In S. Gardiner & A. Thompson (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics (pp. 427–437). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J., Cuneo, T., & Shafer-Landau, R. (in press). Philosophical methodology: From data to theory. Oxford University Press.

  • Bradley, B. (2001). The value of endangered species. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 35, 43–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradshaw, C., et al. (2021). Underestimating the challenges of avoiding a ghastly future. Frontiers in Conservation Science, 13. https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fcosc.2020.615419/full

  • Brondizio, E. S., Settele, J., Díaz, S., & Ngo, H. T. (2019). Global assessment report on biodiversity and ecosystem services of the intergovernmental science-policy platform on biodiversity and ecosystem services. IPBES. https://ipbes.net/global-assessment. Accessed 11 Nov 2021

    Google Scholar 

  • Bull, J. W., & Maron, M. (2016). How humans drive speciation as well as extinction. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 283, 10160600.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cafaro, P. (2015). Three ways to think about the sixth mass extinction. Biological Conservation, 192, 387–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, B. (1984). Non-anthropocentric value theory and environmental ethics. American Philosophical Quarterly, 21(4), 299–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, B. (2001). The land ethic. In D. Jamieson (Ed.), A Companion to Environmental Philosophy (pp. 204–217). Blackwell Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ceballos, G., Ehrlich, P., & Raven, P. (2020). Vertebrates on the bring as indicators of biological annihilation and the sixth mass extinction. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 117(24), 13596–13602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coons, C. (2012). The best expression of Welfarism. Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, 2, 206–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crist, E. (manuscript). “Witnessing Mass Extinction: What’s Invisible, What’s Visible, What’s Possible.”

  • Cuomo, C. (2003). Ethics and the Eco/Feminist Self. In M. Zimmerman & J. B. Callicott (Eds.), Environmental Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology (4th ed., pp. 194–207).

    Google Scholar 

  • de Vos, J. M., Joppa, L. N., Gittleman, J. L., Stephens, P. R., & Pimm, S. L. (2015). Estimating the Normal background rate of species extinction. Conservation Biology, 29(2), 452–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1981). What is equality? Part 1: Equality of welfare. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 10, 185–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • FAO. (2014). State of World Fisheries and Aquaculture. http://www.fao.org/3/i3720e/i3720e.pdf. Accessed 11 Nov 2021 

  • FAOSTAT. (2021). Food and Agricultural Organization of the United Nations Statistics Division. http://www.fao.org/faostat/en/#home. Accessed 11 Nov 2021 

  • Gunn, A. (1980). Should we care about rare species? Environmental Ethics, 2(1), 17–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartley, J. (2012). The virtues of temporal discernment: Rethinking the extent and coherence of the good in a time of mass extinction. Environmental Philosophy, 9(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). (2014). Climate change 2014 synthesis report summary for policymakers. IPCC. https://www.ipcc.ch/pdf/assessment-report/ar5/syr/AR5_SYR_FINAL_SPM.pdf . Accessed 11 Nov 2021 

    Google Scholar 

  • International Union for the Conservation of Nature (IUCN). (2011). IUCN Biodiversity. IUCN. http://www.iucn.org/what/biodiversity/. Accessed 11 Nov 2021

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, K. (1991). A morally deep world. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, S. (2009). Welfarism. Philosophy Compass, 4(1), 82–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krausmann, F., Erb, K.-H., Gingrich, S., Haberl, H., Bondeau, A., Gaube, V., et al. (2013). Global human appropriation of net primary production doubled in the 20th century. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 110(25), 10324–10329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leopold, A. (1949/1968). A Sand County almanac, and sketches here and there. Oxford University Press.

  • Mathews, F. (1994). Relating to nature: Deep ecology or ecofeminism. The Trumpeter, 11(4), 159–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelson, G. (2019). Sentience, life, richness. In C. T. DesRoches, F. Janjunis, & B. Williston (Eds.), Canadian Environmental Philosophy (pp. 883–896). McGill-Queens Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelson, G. (in press). “Abundance and Variety in Nature: Fact and Value.”

  • Odenbaugh, J. (in press). “Owls and Old-Growth: An Examination of the Multi-Layered Moral Conflicts.”

  • Otto, S. (2018). Adaptation, speciation, and extinction in the Anthropocene. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 285, 20182047.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, C. (2010). Animal ethics in context. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, C. (2011). Does Nature Matter? The Place of the Non-human in the Ethics of Climate Change. In D. Arnold (Ed.), The Ethics of Global Climate Change (pp. 272–291). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Preston, C. (2008). Synthetic biology: Drawing a line in Darwin’s sand. Environmental Values, 17, 23–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preston, C. (in press). “Extinct and Alive: Toward a Broader Account of Taxon Loss.”

  • Rockstrom, J., et al. (2009). A safe operating space for humanity. Nature, 461, 472–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolston III, H. (1985). Duties to endangered species. Bioscience, 35(11), 718–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolston III, H. (1986). Philosophy gone wild: Essays in environmental ethics. Prometheus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston III, H. (1995). Duties to endangered species. Encyclopedia of Environmental Biology, 1, 517–528.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston III, H. (2001). Biodiversity. In D. Jamieson (Ed.), A Companion to Environmental Philosophy (pp. 143–153). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, O., et al. (2020). Exploring the Limits of Saving a Subspecies: The ethics and social dynamics of restoring northern white rhinos (ceratotherium simum cottoni). Conservation Science and Practice, 2(8), e241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, R. (2012). The ethics of species. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, R. (2014). The ethics of reviving long extinct species. Conservation Biology, 28(2), 354–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, R. (2018). Is considering the interests of plants absurd? In M. Di Paola & A. Kallhoff (Eds.), Plant ethics (pp. 40–50). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, R., & Basl, J. (2021). Justified species partiality. In B. Bovenkerk & J. Keulartz (Eds.), Animals in Our Midst: The Challenges of Co-existing with Animals in the Anthropocene. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1987). On ethics and economics. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, I. (2016). The intrinsic value of endangered species. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sterba, J. (1995). A Biocentrist Strikes Back. Environmental Ethics, 17(4), 361–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, P. (1986). Respect for nature. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, B., et al. (2020). The need for Ecocentrism in biodiversity conservation. Conservation Biology, 34(5), 1089–1096.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Urban, M. C. (2015). Accelerating extinction risk from climate change. Science, 348(6234), 571–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Dooren, T. (manuscript). “The Unseen Extinction Crisis: Multispecies Storytelling with Hawai’i’s Snails.

  • Vogel, S. (2002). Environmental philosophy after the end of nature. Environmental Ethics, 24(1), 22–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (2010). “Good-for-nothings,” Presidential Address of the 107th Eastern Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association. Proceedings and Addresses of the APA, 85(2), 47–65.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ronald Sandler.

Ethics declarations

None of the declarations are applicable.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sandler, R. On the Massness of Mass Extinction. Philosophia 50, 2205–2220 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00436-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00436-1

Keywords

Navigation