Skip to main content
Log in

How Am I Supposed to Feel?

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this essay, I raise a puzzle concerning rational emotions. The puzzle arises from the fact that a handful of very plausible claims seem to commit us to the idea that whether a subject ought to have a certain emotion at a given time in part depends on the fittingness of the intensity of the feelings it involves, and the fittingness of these feelings in part depends on the intensity of the feelings the subject has at that time. Yet this idea is incompatible with another plausible claim: namely, that the deontic properties possessed by a subject having an emotion with a certain intensity are not counterfactually dependent on her having that emotion with that intensity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The emotions I have in mind are not importantly different from what Scanlon (1998: §1.2) calls “Judgment-Sensitive Attitudes” or what Portmore (2019: chp. 3) calls “Reasons-Responsive Attitudes”.

  2. I thank an anonymous referee for pressing me to make these clarifications.

  3. I take it that pity need not be an exclusively backward-looking emotional response. For example, you might feel pity for an orphan on account of what has already happened, or you might instead be responding to the known hardships in store, or both. The pity in Horrible Birthday mirrors this last option. You are responding to what has already happened but also what you recognize is to come in the moments leading up to midnight.

  4. To press the point, you are not just wondering about how much pity you should feel regarding a particular misfortune—e.g., just your boss making you work overtime on your birthday—nor are you wondering about how much pity you should feel on your birthday up until the time at which you start to feel pity.

  5. These sorts of intensity adjustments constitute a large part of the regulation of our emotions. An interpersonal example makes this feature of our emotional lives vivid. Often our friends think that we should be feeling a particular emotion, but still wonder whether the intensity with which it is felt is off. Suppose, for example, walking home at night makes you feel fear, but not that much. Your friends worry that you don’t fear intensely enough, and so they raise factors for your consideration. They deliberate with you in an attempt to help get the intensity of your emotion appropriately modulated. The same holds for the intrapersonal case.

  6. This leaves open a couple of options. Perhaps you are trying to sort out the intensity prior to having felt it. Or perhaps you already feel pity but you are wondering whether the intensity with which you feel it is the intensity with which you ought to feel it in the moments to come. This second option has an analogue for doxastic states. You might have settled the question whether to binary believe that p but still wonder about the degree to which you ought to believe that p. Here, as in the case of Horrible Birthday, the focus of your deliberations concerns the strength with which the attitude is held. I owe this analogy to an anonymous referee.

  7. Cases with this structure are not confined to pity. Regret, desire, valuing, fear, and envy can also give rise to such cases. Regret affords an especially clean example. You make a choice that you regret on account of its outcome. Since the outcome will include your regret, the feeling of regret with a certain intensity is part of what the emotion is directed toward.

  8. I should stress that I do not mean to endorse Broad’s account in all its particulars. Rather I find its general outlines plausible. That’s sufficient to motivate the puzzle.

  9. This way of putting it comes from Rosen (2015).

  10. For a powerful defense of this idea, see Thomson (2008: 131) and Smith (2017).

  11. For further defense, see Howard (2018).

  12. For a helpful overview, see d’Arms and Jacobson (2000), Alfano (2016: 86–87), and Scarantino and de Sousa (2018: §5-§7).

  13. For further arguments in favor of this idea, see Smith (2017) and Portmore (2019: 54–61).

  14. For further defense, see Na'aman (2019).

  15. For an overview and defense, see Deonna and Fabrice (2012: 14–16).

  16. I should note that many accounts of welfare assume that a subject’s positive (or negative) feelings are non-instrumentally good-for (or bad-for) her. So another way to arrive at Value Depends on Feelings would be to first claim that the value of the emotion’s object depends on the subject’s welfare level at a time, and then claim that her welfare level that time, in part, depends on whether she feels positively or negatively with a certain intensity at that time. For an account of welfare that would deliver this result, see Heathwood (2019). For more on the connection between emotions and well-being, which also would deliver this result, see Alfano (2016: 86–92). Although I am sympathetic to this line of thought, I hope to avoid these added commitments. I shall thus stick to the wider claim that a subject’s positive or negative feelings can influence the amount of good-simpliciter or bad-simpliciter.

  17. This formulation of the principle is modified from Bykvist (2007: 100).

  18. Vessel (2003), for example, takes this principle to be so obvious that he leverages it against Lewis’s semantics for counterfactuals. For others who endorse this principle, see Carlson (1995), Hare (2011), Timmerman (2016), and Cohen (2020). For criticism, see Bykvist (2007) and Howard-Snyder (2008).

  19. A more compressed version of the sort of argument I’ll offer below can be found in Carlson (1995: §6.3).

  20. Here I am assuming what is arguably the most popular definition of a normative reason: That such reasons are facts that, absent defeat, make it the case that an agent ought to act in some way. To get a feel of the popularity of this definition of reasons, see Alvarez (2017: §2) and Portmore (2021: 18–20). For a very precise formulation of this view, although using different terminology, see Chisholm (1978).

  21. This formulation is modified from Snedegar (2018: 685), who is following Schroeder (2007: 33). For list of the authors who endorse the Deliberative Constraint, see the references in Paakkunainen (2017: 56fn3).

  22. It is not the only one. For another argument, see Paakkunainen (2017).

  23. Some take this connection—between reasons and reasoning—as the place to begin building an account of normative reasons; see, for example, Setiya (2014) and Way (2017).

  24. You may still deliberate concerning the evaluative question: Is feeling a violent wave of pity good? But you cannot deliberate concerning the normative question: Ought I to feel a violent wave of pity? The Deliberative Constraint explains this difference. For more on this point, see Way (2017).

References

  • Alfano, M. (2016). Moral Psychology: An Introduction. Polity Press.

  • Alvarez, M. (2017). Reasons for Action: Justification, Motivation, Explanation. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by Edward N. Zalta.

  • Broad, C. D. (1954). Emotion and Sentiment. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 13(2), 203–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2004). Weighing Lives. Oxford University Press.

  • Bykvist, K. (2007). Violations of Normative Invariance: Some thoughts on Shifty Oughts. Theoria, 73(2), 98–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, E. (1995). Consequentialism Reconsidered. Springer.

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1978). Practical Reason and the Logic of Requirement. In J. Raz (Ed.), Practi­cal Reasoning (pp. 118–127). Oxford University Press.

  • Cohen, D. (2020). An Actualist Explanation of the Procreation Asymmetry. Utilitas, 32(1), 70–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • d’Arms, J., & Jacobson, D. (2000). The Moralistic Fallacy: On the ‘Appropriateness’ of Emotions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61(1), 65–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deonna, J. A., & Fabrice, T. (2012). The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction. Routledge.

  • Hare, C. (2011). Obligation and Regret When There is No Fact of the Matter About What Would Have Happened if You Had not Done What You Did. Noûs, 45(1), 190–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heathwood, C. (2019). Which Desires Are Relevant to Well-Being? Noûs, 53(3), 664–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, C. (2018). Fittingness. Philosophy Compass, 13(11), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard-Snyder, F. (2008). Damned If You Do; Damned If You Don’t! Philosophia, 36(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Na'aman, O. (2019). "The Rationality of Emotional Change: Toward a Process View." Noûs.

  • Paakkunainen, H. (2017). Can There be Government House Reasons for Action. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 12(1), 56–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portmore, D. W. (2021). Morality and Practical Reasons. Cambridge University Press.

  • Portmore, D. W. (2019). Opting for the Best: Oughts and Options. Oxford University Press.

  • Prichard, H. A. (2002). Moral Writings. Oxford University Press.

  • Rosen, G. (2015). The Alethic Conception of Moral Responsibility. In R. Clarke, M. McKenna, & A. M. Smith (Eds.), The Nature of Moral Responsibility: New Essays (pp. 65–87). Oxford University Press.

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What We Owe to Each Other. Harvard University Press.

  • Scarantino, A., & de Sousa R. (2018). Emotion. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, edited by E.N. Zalta.

  • Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the Passions. Oxford University Press.

  • Setiya, K. (2014). What is a Reason to Act? Philosophical Studies, 167(2), 221–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shah, N. (2006). A New Argument for Evidentialism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(225), 481–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2017). Parfit’s Mistaken Meta-Ethics. In P. Singer (Ed.), Does Anything Really Matter: Essays on Parfit on Objectivity (pp. 99–120). Oxford University Press.

  • Snedegar, J. (2018). "Deliberation, Reasons, and Alternatives." Pacific Philosophical Quarterly.

  • Svavarsdóttir, S. (2014). Having Value and Being Worth Valuing. The Journal of Philosophy, 111(2), 84–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (2008). Normativity. Open Court.

  • Timmerman, T. (2016). "Reconsidering Categorical Desire Views." In Immortality and the Philosophy of Death, edited by M. Cholbi. London: Rowman & Littlefield.

  • Vessel, J. P. (2003). Counterfactuals for consequentialists. Philosophical Studies, 112(2), 103–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Way, J. (2017). Reasons as Premises of Good Reasoning. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 98(2), 251–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Winnie Sung, Aldrin Relador, and the reviewers and editors at Philosophia for helpful comments on earlier drafts. This research was supported by the Ministry of Education, Singapore, under its Academic Research Fund Tier 1 (RG62/19 (NS)).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew T. Forcehimes.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Forcehimes, A.T. How Am I Supposed to Feel?. Philosophia 50, 533–542 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00393-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-021-00393-9

Keywords

Navigation