In talking about olfaction, I assume a regular representationalist position according to which olfactory states represent odors, which are usually understood as chemical mixtures or structures (e.g., Batty 2009, 2010a; Cavedon-Taylor 2018; Young 2016). From this perspective, odors are different from odor-sources, which are understood as entities from which odors emanate (e.g., a cigarette may be considered the source of a cigarette odor). The considerations in the previous section have demonstrated that visual objects satisfy a notion of primary subject due to the fact that they unify visual features into perceptual units but themselves do not need to be constituted by complex entities unified by something else. The question is whether the same notion of primary subject is also satisfied in the case of odors.
This is not obvious for three reasons. First, while authors who postulate that odors are experienced as objects usually treat them as subjects (e.g., Carvalho 2014; Millar 2019; Young 2016), the particular notion of ‘subject’ that is used has not been established, so it is unclear whether odors are subjects in the same way that visual objects are. Second, one of the main reasons why visual objects are primary subjects is that they play a crucial role in solving the Many Properties Problem. However, serious arguments have been proposed in order to demonstrate that human olfaction, in opposition to vision, does not have abilities to solve this problem (Batty 2010a, 2014; Keller 2016). Third, some authors believe that odors are experienced as instantiated by some other type of entities, like locations (Batty 2010b) or odor sources (Mole 2010). This is inconsistent with characterizing odors as primary subjects, so some arguments are required to refute these views.
The further argumentation is specifically shaped to address the above concerns. I argue that odors are primary subjects in the same sense as visual objects, i.e., they unify properties into perceptual units but themselves do not need to be constituted by complex entities unified by something else. This is done by (a) showing that there are similar intuitions concerning subject-statues of odors and visual objects (Section 3.1), (b) demonstrating the presence of psychological results suggesting the subject status of odors (Section 3.2), (c) arguing that odors play a major role in solving the olfactory version of the Many Properties Problem (Section 3.3), and (d) showing that odors are not experienced as subjects of some other entities (Section 3.4). The point (c) is directly related to the second concern as I address the arguments by Batty and Keller aimed to show that olfaction cannot solve the Many Properties Problem. Similarly, point (d) corresponds to the third concern as I argue why odor sources and places are not good candidates for subjects of odors. Finally, in Section 3.5, I additionally demonstrate that the arguments provided against the idea of olfactory object perception do not threaten my thesis concerning odors as primary subjects.
Intuitions Concerning Odors
I believe that there are analogous intuitive reasons to treat perceptually experienced odors as subjects of features, just as in the case of visually experienced objects. First, it seems that a single odor is presented as combined with many olfactory features, for instance a certain intensity, a certain pleasantness, and various qualities such as fruitiness or woodiness. In addition, odors are usually presented as having a feature determining the odor-type to which they belong. For instance, odors are experienced as being onion-odors or strawberry-odors. Furthermore, a relation between an experienced odor and its features can be plausibly characterized as an asymmetric unification. For instance, in the case of a complex perceptually presented odor, like a perfume, the odor may be experienced as possessing a woody node, but it would be implausible to state that a woody note possesses the whole perfume. In addition, a perceptually experienced odor together with all its features constitutes a perceptual unit that can be attended, analyzed, and evaluated. Such a level of unity does not seem to be present in the case of experiencing two odors as sharing a feature, like in a case of a cigarette odor partially masked by an onion odor, which may both possess the feature of being unpleasant. Finally, the relation between odors presented in olfactory experiences and their features does not seem to be contingent. In particular, there are no experiences as of free-floating olfactory features, such as a fruitiness that is not presented as a fruitiness of any odor; rather they are always experienced as related to some odors.Footnote 5
All the above intuitive observations suggest that perceptually experienced odors satisfy the crucial characteristics of subjects in their relation to features. They are presented as combined with many such features and as asymmetrically unifying them into perceptual units. It should be noted that, as mentioned in section one, despite what the examples may suggest, I do not assume that being experienced as a subject necessarily requires being categorized as a member of some category of odors (e.g., as a cherry odor or a cigarette odor).
Psychological Data
While the empirical results concerning olfactory perceptual units are not so abundant as in the case of vision, in this context too one can find data showing the asymmetry between the unificatory role of odors and features. First, the ability of human olfaction to represent multiple odors at the same time seems to be limited (see Stevenson and Mahmut 2013). In particular, simultaneously presented odors are usually experienced in such a way that one odor is distinguished from an olfactory ground constituted by the other odors, which are represented in a more rudimentary fashion (Batty 2010a; Gottfried 2010; Millar 2019; Stevenson and Wilson 2007; Young 2016). Such a figure/ground character of olfaction suggests that an odor together with its features is presented as constituting a perceptual unit, differentiated from the other olfactory stimuli forming ‘ground’. On the other hand, two perceptually presented odors “unified” through their sharing a feature, like a cigarette odor and an onion odor united by unpleasantness, do not achieve such a level of unity. It is so because one of them would be experienced as a figure while the second will be experienced as a ground that obtains only a sketchy representation.
Some authors claim that the relation between simultaneously experienced odors should not be characterized as a distinction between a figure and a ground because, in contrast to the case of vision, such odors do not stand in appropriate spatial relations (Keller 2016, pp. 72–75). However, this does not change the presented argument, as it requires only that odors in some way compete for resources no matter whether this competition is characterized as a spatial figure/ground discrimination or otherwise.
Another possible counter-argument is to postulate that if two odors sharing a feature, like an onion and a cigarette odor, are simultaneously experienced, then they are also experienced as components of a third, complex onion-cigarette odor. In this case, even if they compete for resources, they are still experienced as belonging to a higher-level perceptual unit. Nevertheless, while the individuation criteria of perceptually experienced odors are not completely clear, the literature strongly suggest that sharing a single feature, like “being irritating”, is not sufficient to experience odors as components of a complex whole. Because of this, not all cases of experiencing odors sharing a feature will be also experiences presenting a unit composed of these odors. To experience such a higher-order unit some additional conditions have to be satisfied, for instance, it is more likely that odors will be experienced as unified within a higher-level whole if they are connected by complex relations of congruency; they have previously been frequently experienced together; and a person possesses a concept that allows her to recognize that the odors are likely to come from a single source (see Batty 2014; Stevenson and Wilson 2007).
Furthermore, the unificatory asymmetry between odors and features presented in olfactory experiences is revealed in the case of olfactory tracking. People are able to find the location of an odor-source by following an odor (Porter et al. 2007). Such an ability involves recognizing that an odor is the same despite the fact that during tracking its intensity or some qualitative properties may undergo modifications (Richardson 2013). Hence, it seems that a perceptually presented odor, together with its features, defines a perceptual unit that can be followed through time and change. On the other hand, such a unit is not created when an odor at an earlier moment and an odor at a later moment are presented as having the same feature. Having a common feature does not guarantee that odors are experienced as being the same. It is so because there are many odors that people recognize as being clearly distinct despite the fact that they share some features (Zarzo and Stanton 2009). As a result, perceptual “units” – created by several subsequent perceptually presented odors sharing a feature – are not useful in tracking odor-sources, because having a common feature does not provide a strong justification that the same thing is being tracked. Such observations suggest that the perceptual units used in olfactory tracking are odors with features and not several odors that share an olfactory feature.
The Many Properties Problem
Furthermore, I believe that odors in the context of olfactory experiences serve an analogous role in solving the Many Properties Problem as visual objects do in the case of visual experiences. Nevertheless, there are authors who doubt whether olfaction has the ability to solve the Many Properties Problem because of severe limitations concerning the olfactory ability to represent space. For instance, it may happen that one attempts to mask a cigarette odor with an air freshener odor and in consequence has an experience presenting both these odors (an example proposed by Batty 2010a). In the visual domain, two objects can be presented in many ways by virtue of the richness of visual spatial representation. For instance, one object may be presented on the right of another or objects may partially overlap. On the other hand, such variety does not seem to be present in the case of olfactory experiences. For example, it is unlikely that one can have two distinct experiences such that in one the air freshener odor is presented as being on the left of the cigarette odor and in the second the air freshener odor is on the right of the cigarette odor.
One way to refute the above argument is to claim that it neglects the actual olfactory abilities for spatial representation. In particular, it is proposed that to properly asses the way in which olfaction represents space, olfactory experiences should be considered as temporally extended in order to accommodate the time needed for various exploratory activities such as sniffing while moving around. According to this perspective, olfactory experiences may represent ‘smellscapes’ i.e., arrays of spatially positioned odors, which are useful in olfactory navigation and tracking (see Young 2020; Young et al. 2020). If olfaction represents smellscapes, then it can solve the Many Properties Problem in a manner that is analogous to the visual solution, since distinct combinations of the same properties may be distinguished by the way in which properties are distributed among spatially positioned odors.
Nevertheless, even if olfactory abilities to represent spatial properties are severely restricted, the argument against olfactory resolution of the Many Properties Problem relies on a controversial assumption that all solutions to the Many Properties Problem must involve spatial discriminations. Indeed, it may be the case that vision has the ability to create spatial representations that allow us to distinguish between situations where the same elements are present but differ only in terms of their occurring spatial relations, while olfaction is unable to make analogous discriminations in the case of presented odors. However, such a result is not sufficient to claim that there are no alternative ways for olfaction to resolve some cases of the Many Properties Problem (see Carvalho 2014 for a similar observation). This is because the ability to solve the problem lies in distinguishing varying arrangements of the same elements, and making spatial discriminations is only one possible way to achieve this goal.
In particular, olfaction, apart from presenting odors, also presents their various qualities. For instance, odors are experienced as having some intensity (Morton 2000), trigeminal featuresFootnote 6 such as irritating or cooling (Laska et al. 1997), and hedonic features (Castro and Seeley 2014). Relying on this observation, let’s again analyze a situation in which one is presented with a cigarette odor and an onion odor. It may be the case that both these odors are experienced as unpleasant and irritating, but the cigarette odor is experienced as having a high intensity while onion odor is presented as being less intense. But it seems that olfaction is also able to present a different situation composed of the same elements with reversed intensities, such that the cigarette odor has a lower intensity but the onion odor has high intensity. If olfaction presents such situations differently, then it is able to resolve some cases of the Many Properties Problem. In consequence, it is not adequate to characterize olfactory content in terms of a list of elements, like odor categorized as an exemplar of the onion-category, odor categorized as an exemplar of the cigarette-category, low intensity, high intensity, and unpleasantness, because in both considered situations the list would be the same.
Instead, in order to solve the olfactory Many Properties Problem, the experiential content should be characterized in terms of perceptual units constituted by odors and their features. Such a characterization allows us to distinguish the olfactory experiences described above. In the first, there is (1) a cigarette odor with a high intensity that is also unpleasant, as well as (2) an onion odor with low intensity that is also unpleasant. In the second case, the perceptual units are different because a cigarette odor is experienced as having low intensity and an onion odor as having a high intensity.
In contrast, it has been argued by Keller (2016, pp. 75-55) that even if human olfaction has some non-spatial ways of solving the Many Properties Problem, this occurs not due to rules of perceptual organization, but as a result of higher-level expectations. For instance, we may perceive a pizza-odor and an anchovies-odor as composing a perceptual unit because we ordered a pizza with that topping and so expect these odors to emanate from a single source. However, it is not obvious why some of the rules governing odor-binding cannot be perceptual. For instance, they may be acquired by perceptual mechanisms by detecting statistical regularities in combinations of perceived odors without the necessity for involvement of high-level concepts (see Young 2019b for a similar point). In fact, human olfaction offers significant abilities for perceptual pattern-learning, which allows for successful odor recognition despite changes in the composition of chemical stimuli (see Stevenson and Wilson 2007).
Another way of arguing against the idea of non-spatial means of solving the olfactory Many Properties Problem is to claim that in fact Many Properties Problem does not arise in case of olfaction (Batty 2010a, 2014). In particular, one of the major functions of olfactory mechanisms is to classify odors as exemplars of odor types (Stevenson and Wilson 2007). The classification of odors may determine which properties are attributed to them and in consequence the Many Properties Problem does not arise. For example, recognizing an odor as a cigarette odor entails that it is irritating and recognizing that it is a rose odor entails that it is flowery. In consequence, there are no cases in which the olfactory system has to choose between alternative combinations of the same properties, since the unique pattern is determined by odor classification.
However, the cases considered above show that this is not universally true. In particular, intensity-features are suitable for constructing olfactory versions of the Many Properties Problem. It is not the case that mere odor categorization is sufficient to determine the intensity of an experienced odor and it is likely that information about the recognized intensity and the qualitative aspects of an odor have to be additionally combined by the olfactory system. This is suggested by cases of anosmia, in which one can detect intensity-related features without being able to classify an odor and recognize its qualities (Morton 2000). Other versions of the olfactory Many Properties Problem may be constructed by referring to hedonic features, which are likely to change independently from other qualitative features due to acquired positive and negative experiences, and trigeminal features, which are detected by physiological mechanisms distinct from those that process typical olfactory features.
Primary Subjects
The above considerations show that there are reasons to treat perceptually experienced odors as subjects of features, analogously to visually experienced objects. The subject-status of odors presented in olfactory experiences is suggested by our intuitions concerning olfactory phenomenology, and is supported by results in olfactory science, as well as by the role of odors in resolving the olfactory version of the Many Properties Problem. However, a further question is whether we experience odors as primary subjects. In the philosophical literature, we find two positions according to which odors are themselves experienced as properties of some other elements. First, they are considered as properties of places (Batty 2010c). Second, they are interpreted as properties of odor-sources (see Mole 2010; Todd 2018 for discussion of this point). If either of these options is correct, then olfactorily odors are not perceptually presented as primary subjects, even if they are presented as subjects of features.
Within the philosophy of perception, there is no agreement on how exactly olfaction represents space. In particular, some authors believe that olfaction represents odors as being merely external or positioned in a vague, “somewhere around” region (e.g., Batty 2010b; Richardson 2013), while others ascribe to it additional spatial abilities related to representing spatial extension and the direction of odors (e.g., Aasen 2019; O’Callaghan 2016; Young 2020).Footnote 7 To be subjects of perceptually experienced odors, olfactory places should be presented as simultaneously related to many odors and should unify those odors into a perceptual unit. Despite differences in the characterization of olfactory space, it seems likely that the first of these conditions can be satisfied. In particular, if only one “somewhere around” place is olfactorily presented, then all simultaneously experienced odors are presented as related to this place.
However, it is not plausible that a common place unifies several odors into a perceptual unit. As stated earlier, human olfaction presents odors simultaneously in such a way that one is an olfactory “figure” distinguished from a ground constituted by other odors (Batty 2010a; Gottfried 2010; Young 2016). In consequence, even if two such odors are experienced as related to the same olfactory place, they do not constitute a single perceptual unit.
According to the second option, odors are not experienced as primary subjects because they are experienced as properties of odor-sources. If this is the case, then olfactory experiences present not only odors, features, and places, but also entities from which odors emanate. For instance, an experience representing an onion odor also represents its source: an onion or some onions. It should be noted that there is no consensus that olfaction presents sources, and philosophers have offered several arguments against this idea (e.g., Batty 2010a, however see Todd 2018 for arguments in favor of a thesis that sources are olfactorily represented). First, the phenomenal character of olfactory experiences does not suggest that anything beyond odors and their features is presented. Second, it is often the case that an odor is experienced long after its source is gone. Because perceptual content is commonly understood as determining the accuracy conditions of experiences (e.g., Siegel 2010), a perceptual experience representing the source of an odor would be inaccurate if the source were no longer present. However, it is implausible to claim that such cases are olfactory illusions (see Batty 2010a).
Nevertheless, I believe that even if olfactory experiences present odor-sources in addition to odors, it is not the case that such odor-sources are presented as subjects of odors. Analogously to case of olfactory places, if odor-sources are experienced as subjects of odors, then they can be presented as simultaneously related to more than one odor and should be experienced as unifying these odors into a perceptual unit. However, in case of odor-sources, even the first condition is hardly satisfied. To fulfill this condition, and thus present at least two odors as simultaneously having the same source, human olfaction has to be able to (a) recognize the presence of two odors, (b) establish their sources, and (c) identify the source of the first odor with the source of the second.
However, it is implausible that the olfactory mechanism can succeed in achieving (c). This is because information about sources that can be inferred from detected odors is quite limited. For instance, it does not allow one to establish how many items constitute a source (e.g., whether an onion odor is emanating from a single onion or from several onions). In addition, as our olfactory abilities to represent space are limited, at most allowing us to represent an approximate spatial extension of an odor, it is also difficult to determine the exact location of a source from the spatial characteristics of an experienced odor. While some data show that source of an odor can tracked by detecting the changes intensities in response to one’s movements (Porter et al. 2007), it is not clear if, as a result of such tracking process, two odors can be localized and attributed to the same source. Finally, it is often difficult to recognize what type of object is the source of an odor. For instance, an onion odor may be caused either by an onion or by a packet of onion-flavored crisps. In consequence, when two odors are simultaneously presented in an olfactory experience, there is not enough available data to allow us to determine whether their sources are identical.
Neither olfactory places nor odor-sources are plausible candidates for being subjects of perceptually presented odors. Because there are no other serious candidates for this kind of subject, it should be accepted that odors are not only perceptually presented as subjects of features but are also presented as primary subjects. As a result, they play a role in olfactory experiences analogous to that of objects in visual experiences: they unify other presented elements without the need to constitute perceptual units unified by something else.
Olfactory Subjects and Objects
In the introductory section, I have observed that it is debated whether human olfaction presents odors as objects and that being a subject is a necessary characteristic of being an object. Hence, we may ask what the connections are between the debate regarding olfactory objecthood and my thesis that odors are presented as primary subjects. In particular, it is important to consider whether arguments against treating odors as olfactorily presented objects may also undermine the subject-status of odors. It should be noted that even if odors are not experienced as objects they may still be experienced as primary subjects: Being a subject is only a necessary and not a sufficient condition for being an object, and there are entities such as events or processes which are commonly considered as subjects but not as objects. Nevertheless, it is still possible that arguments against olfactory objecthood of odors may undermine their status as perceptual primary subjects.
The thesis that olfaction presents odors as objects has been challenged by Barwich (2019), who proposes three arguments against olfactory objecthood: (a) olfaction does not provide stable representations of the physical stimuli, (b) perceptual constancy is absent in human olfaction, and (c) figure/ground discrimination differs significantly in olfaction compared to vision. This critique is particularly interesting as it relies on the current empirical knowledge concerning functioning of olfactory mechanisms. Below, I argue that Barwich’s arguments do not threaten the thesis that odors are experienced as subjects. In fact, the positive account of olfactory experiences proposed by Barwich is not plausible without ascribing the subject-status to odors.
According to the first argument, olfaction does not present the environment in terms of objects due to the fact that there is no stable relationship between qualitative elements of olfactory experiences and external chemical properties. In particular, there is no one-to-one correspondence between the olfactory phenomenal character and the chemical characteristics of stimuli since, depending on concentration and presence of other substances, the same substances may smell differently, or significantly distinct substances may evoke similar qualities. Furthermore, there are considerable individual differences concerning the way in which people experience chemical stimuli, and experiences of a single individual may change due to gained memories and formed expectations.
There are two ways in which such lack of stability may undermine the thesis that odors are experienced as subjects. First, due to the way in which chemical stimuli are processed, the olfactory phenomenology may be so variable and unstable that it does not make sense to postulate that in olfactory experiences some properties are attributed to odors. Nevertheless, it does not seem to be the case, since phenomena such as olfactory tracking show that one can perceive an odor as having the same features despite changes in intensity and spatial position. Second, the lack of stable correspondence between olfactory qualities and chemical properties may suggest that olfactory experiences should not be treated as representations, rather they should be conceptualized in processual terms (see Barwich 2018). Such a conclusion would be problematic for the thesis concerning the subject-status of odors as this thesis has been proposed in representational terms. While I believe that phenomena discussed by Barwich should be taken into account by proponents of representational approaches to olfaction, their presence is not enough to refute the core representational thesis that experiences have accuracy conditions. In particular, a proponent of representational account does not have to assume one-to-one correspondence, unaffected by changes in context and presence of top-down influence, between phenomenology and stimuli properties. Furthermore, a representationalist may even postulate that properties ascribed to odors in olfactory experience do not really exist (see Mendolovici 2018 for such ‘error-theory’ of olfaction). In fact, even if one agrees that the role of olfaction is not to represent chemical properties but to evaluate stimulus—for instance as unpleasant or harmful—there are also representational theories of evaluative aspects of experiences (mainly developed in the context of pain perception, see Bain 2012 for a review). In consequence, because the thesis that odors are presented as subjects does not assume any particular representational theory, but only a general representationalist framework, it is not undermined by phenomena described by Barwich.
To establish her second point concerning the lack of olfactory constancy perception, Barwich provides several examples of cases in which an odor is experienced as being qualitatively distinct due to external, contextual changes without modifying the actual chemical composition of a stimulus. For instance, a chemical mixture may be experienced differently depending on preceding stimulation, expectations evoked by verbal labels, or mere time of stimulation due to adaptation effects. I believe that such way of arguing is problematic; since olfaction does not achieve constancy in some circumstances, it does not follow that olfactory constancy perception is completely absent. For example, it seems plausible that olfaction is able to present sameness of odors and their properties despite intensity changes. Nevertheless, even if lack of olfactory constancy were successfully demonstrated, such a result poses no significant threat for the subject-status of odors, because the thesis that odors are experiences as subjects concerns the experiential relation between odors and properties and is neutral regarding the way that the diachronic sameness of odors and olfactory properties is perceived. In other words, odors may be experienced as subjects even if contextual changes are always connected with perception of property change and not perception of property constancy.
Finally, in consideration regarding distinguishing figure from ground, Barwich agrees with Keller (2016) in postulating that there is no olfactory phenomenon analogous to visual figure/ground discrimination. Instead, she proposes that the olfactory experiences should be described in terms of perceptual grouping of properties, which serves as a basis for odor recognition, evaluation, and conducting actions. I believe that the idea of olfactory grouping not only does not undermine the subject-status of odors, but in fact is likely to require the odors-subjects in order to be plausible. To convincingly argue in favor of olfactory grouping one has to explain what it means for olfactory properties to be experienced as grouped. In this context, it is not enough to postulate that olfactory properties are grouped simply in virtue of spatiotemporal co-occurrence. In this case, one would not be able to distinguish that there are two odors in the environment, differing in their qualitative character and intensity, as all co-occurring properties would be grouped with each other. Similarly, mere spatiotemporal grouping does not allow to successfully evaluate and act upon olfactory stimuli as proper evaluation and action require recognizing which of the detected properties are co-instantiated and not only that they jointly occur at a given moment. Treating odors as subjects allows omitting these problems, because then olfactory grouping can be understood in terms of creating perceptual units composed of odors and properties ascribed to them.