Skip to main content
Log in

The Burdens of Life

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I make the case for risks and burdens of morality and meaning. Recognizing such risks and burdens would require many of us to expand how we think about the imposition of risks and burdens. As I take it, if such an expansion helps us make more sense of relevant cases and helps us clarify or resolve debates for which risks and burdens are relevant, then it is well-motivated. Accordingly, I will demonstrate the relevance of my proposed expansion to recent philosophical discussion on the ethics of procreation and provide a series of cases which my proposed expansion makes more sense of than an unexpanded account of risks and burdens and. Moreover, if adopted, I expect an expanded notion of risks and burdens will have implications far beyond procreative ethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To give credit where due, these arguments are inspired by remarks made by Seana Shiffrin and Rivka Weinberg. But these arguments are merely inspired by such remarks and do not reflect the dialectical contexts in which these remarks were made nor the concerns which motivated them. My thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pushing me to be clearer on this point.

  2. Shiffrin (1999), p. 124.

  3. Shiffrin (1999), p. 127.

  4. Ibid. p. 137. Here, and throughout the rest of the paper, I understand the kind of significance referred to in this principle as normative significance.

  5. Weinberg (2015), p. 127. I read Weinberg as making a claim about the evidentiary relevance of a person’s evaluations. But we could read Weinberg as making a claim about a kind of a personal authority over what the value of an experience consists in. My arguments and conclusion are, mutatis mutandis, compatible with this second reading as well.

  6. See Weinberg (2015), p. 129.

  7. I set aside one complication for Personal Significance as an objection. Some people will find the risks and burdens imposed by their procreation significant. So, every procreator risks the imposition of significant risks and burdens. This strikes me as a morally important but orthogonal to my purposes here.

  8. Of course, anti-natalists like Benatar (2006, pp. 60-92), and philosophers outside of the debate, like Haybron (2008), have challenged this assumption. Nonetheless, the truth of this assumption has no bearing on the soundness of my argument here. As such, I will not consider these challenges.

  9. While I do not have an account of recognition to offer here, the truth of my claim can stand without any such account.

  10. See Young (2001). This example is meant to illustrate how a child might be complicit in injustice. But my argument does not rely on Young’s as a premise.

  11. Berners-Lee (2011), p. 149.

  12. Wolf (2012), p. 1–6.

  13. As such, this sense of ‘meaning’ is not what everyone has in mind when talking about meaning. For example, Camus takes a certain kind of meaningless life, a life spent in revolt against the absurd, to be choice-worthy. See Camus (1955).

  14. Rosenthal (1975), p. 119.

  15. See Davies, Klaassen, & Längle (2014).

  16. This is not an uncontroversial claim. But it is an antecedent commitment of all those engaged in the anti-natalism debate. If the normative significance of morality was simply up to the discretion of the individual, then there’d be little point in debating the morality of procreation.

  17. I thank an anonymous reviewer for drawing my attention to this kind of case and urging me to respond to it.

  18. Benatar attempts to debunk optimism about how well off we are in (2006), Haybron argues that many of us unwittingly pursue unhappiness in (2008), and Himma takes seriously the risk of Hell in (2010) and (2016). Academic philosophers who lack of religiosity, which is most of them, ought to be especially guarded about discounting the magnitude of the threat of eternal suffering. We are prone to discount the magnitude of harms when we think they are unlikely (c.f. deniers’ attitudes towards climate change).

References

  • Benatar, D. (2006). Better never to have been: The harm of coming into existence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berners-Lee, M. (2011). How bad are bananas?: The carbon footprint of everything. Vancouver: Greystone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camus, A. (1955). The myth of sisyphus and other essays. Translated by Justin O'Brien. New York: Vintage Books.

  • Davies, G., Klaassen, D., Längle, A. (2014). Purpose in life test. In A. C. Michalos (Ed.), Encyclopedia of quality of life and well-being research. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0753-5_2336.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Haybron, D. M. (2008). The pursuit of unhappiness: the elusive psychology of well-being. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Himma, K. E. (2010). Birth as a grave misfortune: the traditional doctrine of hell and christian salvific exclusivism. In J. Buenting (Ed.), The problem of hell. Burlington: Ashgate Publishing.

  • Himma, K. E. (2016). The ethics of subjecting a child to the risk of eternal torment. Faith and Philosophy, 33(1), 94–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, B. G. (1975). Dmitri Sergeevich Merezhkovsky and the silver age: The development of a revolutionary mentality. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shiffrin, S. V. (1999). Wrongful life, procreative responsibility, and the significance of harm. Legal Theory, 5(2), 117–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, R. (2015). The risk of a lifetime: how, when, and why procreation may be permissible. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190243708.001.0001.

  • Wolf, S. (2012). Meaning in life and why it matters. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, T. (2001). Overconsumption and procreation: Are they morally equivalent? Journal of Applied Philosophy, 18(2), 183–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank David Faraci, Katia Vavova, James Harold, Nina Emery, Samuel Mitchell, Laura Sizer, and an anonymous reviewer for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Wells.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wells, M. The Burdens of Life. Philosophia 47, 1613–1620 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-019-00061-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-019-00061-z

Keywords

Navigation