Skip to main content
Log in

Michelangelo’s Puzzle

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Michelangelo thought that stone statues pre-exist their sculptors’ performance. Michelangelo’s view gives rise to a puzzle, which we call Michelangelo’s puzzle. Michelangelo’s puzzle looks structurally similar to so-called problems of material constitution (e.g., the puzzle of the statue and the clay, or the puzzle of Tibbles the cat); so it is tempting to suppose that it can be similarly accounted for. This paper argues that the supposition is misguided. Michelangelo’s puzzle raises specific problems, which cannot be adequately dealt with unless one is prepared to give up either the natural view that stone sculptures are human creations, or a very plausible principle concerning the persistence of middle-sized material objects. A tentative solution to the puzzle is provided, in which borders can play an ontological role in the making of material objects. This solution is intuitively more palatable than Michelangelo’s view, but is nonetheless at odds with a commonsensical, realist attitude towards material objects. Thus, Michelangelo’s puzzle poses a serious challenge to common sense, which is unparalleled by other problems of material constitution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The case of Michelangelo’s David and its counterpart(s) within the marble block is mentioned in Van Inwagen 1981.

  2. Sometimes further requirements are put on coincidence, i.e., that coincident objects have the same proper parts, or that they share the same underlying matter (see, e.g., Wasserman 2017). We stick with the simple characterisation of coincidence given in the text, for these additional requirements have no bearings on the derivation of the puzzle and its analysis.

  3. We are making no special assumption on the notion of an intrinsic property; any account in the literature will do (see Weatherson and Marshall 2014 for an overview). The notion of a component can be identified with the mereological notion of a proper part or, in a more cautious way, with a suitable contextual restriction of that notion. The main reasons to be cautious in identifying components and mereological proper parts have to do with vagueness, and with some intuitive requirements that are ordinarily put on the former (e.g., disjointness) but not on the latter.

  4. We ignore complications that may emerge if the possibility of time travels is taken into the account.

  5. Below, we briefly discuss the option of rejecting (4). If premise (1) is taken to entail that Ur-David is a material object at t, then some philosophers would reject it for conceptual or metaphysical reasons, most notably van Inwagen (1981). We ignore this (unusual) attitude due to space limitations. However, we shall consider the hypothesis that Ur-David is not an ordinary material object.

  6. When we speak of the ‘emergence’ of boundaries, we intend to remain neutral as to whether boundaries are literally created through the sculpting process or they pre-exist the process and only come to light at the end of it. When framed in accordance with the former understanding of emergence, the view that David’s creation requires the emergence of certain boundaries is consistent with Varzi’s (2016: 50) insistence that “the possession of a boundary is a sign of objecthood”. See also Smith and Varzi 2000.

  7. We assume that the notion of internal change, or some suitable refinement of it, can be applied also to objects like A, even if we have no intuitive o pre-theoretical idea of what the components of a white triangle are.

References

  • Burke, M. (1992). Copper statues and pieces of copper: A challenge to the standard account. Analysis, 52(1), 12–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1976). Person and object. Open Court, La Salle: A Metaphysical Study.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickie, G. (1983). The new institutional theory of art. Proceedings of the 8th International Wittgenstein Symposium, Vol. 10, pp. 57–64.

  • Fine, K. (2003). The non-identity of a material thing and its matter. Mind, 112(446), 195–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanizsa, G. (1955). Margini quasi-percettivi in campi con stimolazione omogenea. Rivista di Psicologia, 49, 7–30. Trans. As quasi-perceptual margins in homogeneously stimulated fields, in S. Petry and G. E. Mayer (1987) (Eds.), The Perception of Illusory Contours (pp. 40–49). New York: Praeger.

  • Smith, B. (2001). Fiat objects. Topoi, 20(2), 131–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B., & Varzi, A. (2000). Fiat and bona fide boundaries. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60(2), 401–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1981). The doctrine of arbitrary undetached parts. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62(2), 123–137. Reprinted in his (2000) Ontology, Identity, and Modality (pp. 75–94). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Varzi, A. (2008). The extensionality of parthood and composition. The Philosophical Quarterly, 58(230), 108–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varzi, A. (2016). On drawing lines across the board. In L. Zaibert (Ed.), The theory and practice of ontology (pp. 45–78). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wasserman, R. (2017). Material constitution. In Zalta, E. N. (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (fall 2017 Ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/material-constitution.

  • Weatherson, B., & Marshall, D. (2014). Intrinsic vs. extrinsic properties. In Zalta, E. N., ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (fall 2014 Ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/intrinsic-extrinsic.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Francesco Orilia and an anonymous reviewer of Philosophia for their useful remarks on previous versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giuseppe Spolaore.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Spolaore, G., Giaretta, P. Michelangelo’s Puzzle. Philosophia 46, 453–464 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9940-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9940-y

Keywords

Navigation