Skip to main content
Log in

Uncertainty in Hiring Does Not Justify Affirmative Action

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Luc Bovens has recently advanced a novel argument for affirmative action, grounded in the plausible idea that it is hard for an employer to evaluate the qualifications of candidates from underrepresented groups. Bovens claims that this provides a profit-maximizing employer with reason to shortlist prima facie less-qualified candidates from underrepresented groups. In this paper, I illuminate three flaws in Bovens’s argument. First, it suffers from model error: A rational employer does not incur costs to scrutinize candidates when it knows their qualifications with perfect certainty, nor does it refuse to hire better-qualified candidates just because they did not require extra scrutiny. Second, Bovens’s core premise--that there is greater variance in the evaluation of underrepresented candidates than there is the evaluation of other candidates--hurts underrepresented candidates rather than helps them. Third, candidates who are not shortlisted for the reasons Bovens gives have a plausible complaint about unfairness in the hiring process.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Whether this is in fact a libertarian ideal is debatable, as many libertarians will be loath to put any restrictions on owners’ liberty to manage their businesses however they desire (see, e.g., Narveson 1993).

  2. At least as far as mathematical ability is concerned, Summers presented the empirical evidence fairly: There is no mean difference in ability between men and women, but men do display greater variance than women (see, e.g., Hedges and Nowell 1995 and Hyde et al. 2008). Whether this explains, even in part, the underrepresentation of women is unclear.

  3. An optimal shortlist size will in fact be a function of both the costs involved in shortlisting and the uncertainty over the qualifications of the candidates who are being considered for inclusion on the shortlist.

  4. The probability that the selector gets a score 7 candidate is the probability that D, E, and F are all 7 s. This is 0.203 = 0.008. The probability that the selector gets a score 9 candidate is the probability that at least one of D, E, and F is a 9. This is 1–0.93 = 0.271. Therefore, the probability that the selector gets a score 8 candidate is 1–0.008 – 0.271 = 0.721. The expected qualification is thus (7 × 0.008) + (8 × 0.721) + (9 × 0.271) = 8.263.

  5. “This is precisely why we are shortlisting: We need to get a better view of the candidates in order to reduce the variance in our assessment.” (Bovens 2016: 424).

  6. I set aside the possibility of having to enter into battle with Human Resources, which might object—as is its wont—to the selection of a candidate not on the shortlist.

  7. Recall from n. 4 that the probability that the selector gets a score 9 candidate is 0.271. This time, if the selector doesn’t get a score 9 candidate, it is guaranteed to get a score 8 candidate. So the expectation is (8 × 0.729) + (9 × 0.271) = 8.271.

  8. See also Finnigan and Corker 2016 and Ganley et al. 2013.

  9. See, e.g., Arkes and Tetlock 2004, Blanton et al. 2009, Forscher et al. 2017, Manuscript, and Oswald et al. 2013.

  10. Here I shall follow the models of Phelps and Aigner and Cain (1977).

  11. Although this is a weak assumption, obviously satisfied in the real world, it is an important one, since everything gets reversed for candidates below the mean: Var(ε B) > Var(ε W) helps rather than hurts blacks, and Var(q B) > Var(q W) hurts rather than helps them. With equation (2) in mind, think of it this way: If you’re above the mean, you want the signal to be as accurate as possible. If you’re below the mean, you’re aided by noise in the signal, since selectors will place greater weight on the mean, which exceeds your actual qualifications.

  12. Cf. Aigner and Cain: “Blacks confront environmental restrictions on fulfilling their capacities, and this may lead to a smaller variance of [q B].” (1977: 180 n. 13).

  13. I thank an anonymous referee for the evocative example.

  14. I thank an anonymous referee for suggesting this interpretation of promise to me.

  15. See, e.g., Ewens, Tomlin, and Choon Wang 2014 and List 2004.

  16. See, e.g., Baldi 1995, Burris 2004, Clauset, Arbesman, and Larremore 2015, Jacobs 1999 and 2004, Keith and Babchuk 1998, McGinnis and Long 1997, and Oprisko, Dobbs, and DiGrazia 2013.

  17. These are cases of taste discrimination (Becker 1957).

  18. I discuss these issues of justice in hiring in detail in my Mulligan 2017.

References

  • Aigner, D. J., & Cain, G. C. (1977). Statistical theories of discrimination in labor markets. Industrial and Labor Relations Review, 30, 175–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen-Hermanson, S. (2017). Leaky pipeline myths: in search of gender effects on the job market and early career publishing in philosophy. Frontiers in Psychology, 8, 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arkes, H., & Tetlock, P. E. (2004). Attributions of implicit prejudice, or “Would Jesse Jackson ‘fail’ the Implicit Association Test?”. Psychological Inquiry, 15, 257–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow, K. J. (1973). The theory of discrimination. In O. Ashenfelter & A. Rees (Eds.), Discrimination in Labor Markets (pp. 3–33). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldi, S. (1995). Prestige determinants of first academic job for new sociology Ph.D.s 1985–1992. Sociological Quarterly, 36, 777–789.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. (1957). The Economics of Discrimination. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanton, H., Jaccard, J., Klick, J., Mellers, B., Mitchell, G., & Tetlock, P. E. (2009). Strong claims and weak evidence: reassessing the predictive validity of the IAT. Journal of Applied Psychology, 94, 567–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L. (2016). Selection under uncertainty: affirmative action at shortlisting stage. Mind, 125, 421–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burris, V. (2004). The academic caste system: prestige hierarchies in PhD exchange networks. American Sociological Review, 69, 239–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ceci, S. J., & Williams, W. M. (2015). Women have substantial advantage in STEM faculty hiring, except when competing against more-accomplished men. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clauset, A., Arbesman, S., & Larremore, D. B. (2015). Systematic inequality and hierarchy in faculty hiring networks. Science Advances, 1.

  • Connolly, M. R., Lee, Y.-G., and Savoy, J. N. 2015. Faculty hiring and tenure by sex and race: new evidence from a national survey. Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the American Educational Research Association, 16-20 April 2015.

  • Dicey Jennings, C., Kyrilov, A., Cobb, P., Vlasits, J., Vinson, D. W., Montes, E., & Franco, C. (2015). Academic placement data and analysis: 2015 final report. At https://www.dropbox.com/s/b9p0dx817qkcb3e/APDAFinalReport2015.pdf?dl=0.

  • Ewens, M., Tomlin, B., & Choon Wang, L. (2014). Statistical discrimination or prejudice? A large sample field experiment. Review of Economics and Statistics, 96, 119–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finnigan, K. M., & Corker, K. S. (2016). Do performance avoidance goals moderate the effect of different types of stereotype threat on women’s math performance? Journal of Research in Personality, 63, 36–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flore, P. C., & Wicherts, J. M. (2015). Does stereotype threat influence performance of girls in stereotyped domain? A meta-analysis. Journal of School Psychology, 53, 25–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forscher, P. S., Lai, C. K., Axt, J. R., Ebersole, C. R., Herman, M., Devine, P. G., Nosek, B. A. (2017). A meta-analysis of change in implicit bias. https://osf.io/preprints/psyarxiv/dv8tu/. Accessed 22 July 2017.

  • Ganley, C. M., Mingle, L. A., Ryan, A. M., Ryan, K., Vasilyeva, M., & Perry, M. (2013). An examination of stereotype effects on girls’ mathematics performance. Developmental Psychology, 49, 1886–1897.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedges, L. V., & Nowell, A. (1995). Sex differences in mental test scores, variability, and numbers of high-scoring individuals. Science, 269, 41–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyde, J. S., Lindberg, S. M., Linn, M. C., Ellis, A. B., & Williams, C. C. (2008). Gender similarities characterize math performance. Science, 321, 494–495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, D. (1999). Ascription or productivity? The determinants of departmental success in the NRC quality rankings. Social Science Research, 28, 228–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, D. (2004). Ascription and departmental rankings revisited: A correction and a reanalysis. Social Science Research, 33, 183–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keith, B., & Babchuk, N. (1998). The quest for institutional recognition: A longitudinal analysis of scholarly productivity and academic prestige among sociology departments. Social Forces, 76, 1495–1533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, J. A. (2004). The nature and extent of discrimination in the marketplace: evidence from the field. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 119, 49–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marinoff, L. 2009. Inside a search. Inside Higher Ed, <https://www.insidehighered.com/advice/2009/08/31/marinoff>, retrieved 3 July 2017.

  • McGinnis, R., & Long, J. S. (1997). Entry into academia: Effects of stratification, geography and ecology. In M. J. Finkelstein & P. G. Altbach (Eds.), The Academic Profession: The Professorate in Crisis (pp. 342–366). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, T. (2017). Justice and the Meritocratic State. New York: Routledge.

  • Narveson, J. (1993). Moral Matters. Peterborough, Canada: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oswald, F. L., Mitchell, G., Blanton, H., Jaccard, J., & Tetlock, P. E. (2013). Predicting ethnic and racial discrimination: a meta-analysis of IAT criterion studies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 105, 171–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oprisko, R. L., Dobbs, K. L., and DiGrazia, J. 2013. Honor, prestige, and the academy: A portrait of political science tenured and tenure-track faculty in Ph.D.-granting institutions (2012-2013). Paper presented at the 2013 annual meeting of the American Political Science Association.

  • Phelps, E. S. (1972). The statistical theory of racism and sexism. American Economic Review, 62, 659–661.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sackett, P. R., Hardison, C. M., & Cullen, M. J. (2004). On interpreting stereotype threat as accounting for African American-White differences on cognitive tests. American Psychologist, 59, 7–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steele, C. M., & Aronson, J. (1995). Stereotype threat and the intellectual test performance of African Americans. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 797–811.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinpreis, R. E., Anders, K. A., & Ritzke, D. (1999). The impact of gender on the review of the curricula vitae of job applicants and tenure candidates: a national empirical study. Sex Roles, 41, 509–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, W. M., & Ceci, S. J. (2015). National hiring experiments reveal 2:1 faculty preference for women on STEM tenure track. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112, 5360–5365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank two anonymous referees for their many helpful suggestions on this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Mulligan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mulligan, T. Uncertainty in Hiring Does Not Justify Affirmative Action. Philosophia 45, 1299–1311 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9877-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9877-1

Keywords

Navigation