Skip to main content
Log in

Blame and the Humean Theory of Motivation

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A classic, though basically neglected question about motivation arises when we attempt to account for blame’s nature—namely, does the recognition central to blame need help from an independent desire in order to motivate the blame-characteristic dispositions that arise in the blamer? Those who have attended to the question think the answer is yes. Hence, they adopt what I call a Humean Construal of blame on which blame is (a) a judgment that an individual S is blameworthy and (b) an independent desire about S not doing as they did or being as they are. This paper rejects arguments for the Humean Construal, illustrates deep failings of that view, and uses these considerations to support anti-Humean accounts of blame in particular and moral motivation more broadly.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g., Sher (2006, Chpt. 6).

  2. Strawson (1962). There are many versions of this account but this will not effect my arguments here.

  3. Named for Harry Frankfurt (1969). For excellent collections on this debate see, Widerker and McKena (2003) Moya and Cuypers (2009).

  4. Widerker (2003).

  5. Capes (2010, 73). Note that Capes’s argument is limited in scope, since it only appeals to those who reject the W-Defense.

  6. For instance, rejecting (W2) often involves debating the nature of alternative possibilities, since many think that some alternatives are insufficient for action attribution or irrelevant to attributing something to an individual as the basis of moral appraisal. Capes (2010) discusses those sorts of debates at length.

  7. Capes (2010, 13–15).

  8. Cf. Wallace (1994, 21–33) for a now classic statement of this position.

  9. Palmer (2013, 559–560).

  10. Sher (2006, pp. 71–88).

  11. Some deny the phenomenon like Wertheimer (1998). Others like Wallace (1994, 75–78) distinguish between blame and holding responsible. Cf. Wolf (2011, 344) and McKenna (2012, 24–26, 33 & 106).

  12. Cf. Scanlon, (2008, Chpt. 4, esp. 127–138) and Thompson available at https://sites.google.com/a/reasonsresponsive.com/www/research/defending-promiscuous-accounts-of-blame/defending-promiscuous-accounts-of-blame and https://sites.google.com/a/reasonsresponsive.com/www/research/defending-promiscuous-accounts-ofblame/how-anti-humeans-can-keep-the-blame-in-blame-without-emotion-and-why-humeans-cannot.

  13. To be clear, this ‘first’ and ‘second’ is not meant to identify an order in time.

  14. See, e.g., Smith (1987, 1994, 111–119).

  15. See, e.g., Smith (1987, 1994, 119–125).

  16. Shafer-Landau (2003, 173 n. 11).

  17. More on what this independence comes to below.

  18. Smith (1987, 1994, 111–119). Many attribute directions-of-fit talk to Anscombe (1957).

  19. Price also rejects arguments by Lewis (1988) and Collins (1988). Lewis (1996) continues his support for HTM and Hajek & Petit (2004) aSchueler (1991)nd Weintraub (2007) respond. For different sorts of responses to (a)-style objections, see, e.g., , Sobel and Copp (2001), Coleman (2008), and Alverez (2012, 66–71).

  20. Bedke, Matthew (Unpublished ). A Case for Besires. Faculty.arts.ubc.ca/mbedke/Research.html. Accessed 18 Jan 2014. Available at: http://faculty.arts.ubc.ca/mbedke/Research_files/Besires.pdf.

  21. See, e.g., Smith (1994, 123) who cites R. Jay Wallace’s BA thesis as inspiration.

  22. Some of Smith’s targets might actually be committed to the entailment.

  23. See Swartzer (2013) for an alternative response that essentially shows that anti-Humeans can use cases and explanations like those offered by Humeans to make sense of irrational behavior like the one featured in Stocker’s.

  24. Nagel (1970, 27–32) and Dancy (1993, Chpts. 1 & 2; 2000, Chpts. 2 & 3).

  25. Adapted from Dancy (1993), 9, Fig. 1 .1).

  26. See Barry (2005) for a nice summary and critique of Humean commitments.

  27. Following Sher (2006, 112–113) I’m only interested in locating the phenomenon that fulfills the causal and normative roles that moral-responsibility responses like blame do. I am not doing conceptual analysis or attempting to determine what our word ‘blame’ refers to.

  28. Ibid., 102.

  29. Ibid., 99–101.

  30. Sher (2006, 94–95). Sher also notes that self-blame involves the disposition to apologize.

  31. Ibid. 103–111.

  32. Ibid. 104. The bulleted points are directly from Sher. I left out quotation marks to avoid confusion.

  33. Ibid., 105–106. This goes mutatis mutandis for the other blame-constituting desire.

  34. Thus, perhaps he could allow that the dispositions (a) – (c) are partly constitutive of blame. However, if the motivating frustration Sher cites is necessarily affective, it cannot be constitutively tied to blame. And, even so, it seems an individual can blame without being frustrated at all. Suppose that Jaclyn, despite maintaining a good relationship with her brother, wanted to bring some of her concerns about his lifestyle to his attention but could never find the right opportunity. In the face of Hugh’s disrespect, she may see her chance. Thus, rather than being frustrated she is relieved—she finally can say what she thinks needs to be said at a moment when Hugh will likely listen. Thanks to Mark van Roojen for this point.

  35. Sher (2006, 116–133).

  36. To be clear, the worry is simply that both blame-constituting components at least in part originate from the same source—namely, the set of moral principles adopted by the blamer. This would be true even if the blame-constituting belief were about badness and not blameworthiness. I thank an anonymous referee for asking me to clarify this point.

  37. To be clear, we’re not assuming that the blamer is being irrational—she can have an attitude that is non-rationally related to another attitude or set of attitudes and still be rational. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pushing me to clarify this.

  38. Sher (2006, 101–103)

  39. See, e.g. Smith (1987).

  40. See, e.g. Smith (1994, 165).

  41. I am happy to replace wrongdoing and bad character with ill or insufficiently good will and allow for a pluralist view about what an ill will amounts to as Shoemaker (2013, 2015) does.

  42. Sher’s (2006, 94–111) account of how frustration of the blame-constituting desire helps motivate the blame-characteristic disposition strongly suggests that this is how he is thinking of the independence. This argument will go mutatis mutandis for the present-looking desire.

  43. Sher (2006, 126).

  44. Sher (2006, 78–91). For an alternative reason to reject, see, e.g. Oshana (1997).

References

  • Alvarez, M. (2012). Kinds of reasons: an essay in the philosophy of action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, M. (2005). Humean Theories of Motivation. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 5 (pp. 195–224). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capes, J. (2010). The W-Defense. Philosophical Studies, 150(1), 61–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, M. C. (2008). Directions of fit and the Humean theory of motivation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86(1), 127–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, J. (1988). Belief, desire, and revision. Mind, 97(387), 333–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (1993). Moral reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2000). Practical reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1969). Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 66(3), 829–839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A., & Pettit, P. (2004). Desire Beyond Belief. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 82(1), 77–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, E., & Macnamara, C. (2010). Beyond belief: toward a theory of the reactive attitudes. Philosophical Papers, 39(3), 373–399.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1988). Desire as Belief. Mind, 97(387), 323–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Desire as Belief II. Mind, 105(418), 303–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2012). Conversation and responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moya, C., & Cuypers, S. (eds) (2009). Philosophical Explorations, 14(2).

  • Nagel, T. (1970). The possibility of altruism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oshana, M. (1997). Ascriptions of responsibility. American Philosophical Quarterly, 34(1), 71–83.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, D. (2013). Capes on the W-defense. Philosophia, 41(2), 555–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. (2001). A theory of freedom: from the psychology to the politics of agency. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1989). Defending Desire-as-Belief. Mind, 98(389), 119–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schueler, G. F. (1991). Pro-attitudes and directions of fit. Mind, 100(400), 277–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (2003). Moral realism: a defense. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2006). In praise of blame. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D. (2013). Qualities of will. Social Philosophy and Policy, 30(1–2), 95–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D. (2015). Responsibility from the margins. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1987). The Humean theory of motivation. Mind, 96(381), 36–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, D., & Copp, D. (2001). Against direction of fit accounts of belief and desire. Analysis, 61(1), 44–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, M. (1979). Desiring the bad: an essay in moral psychology. Journal of Philosophy, 76(12), 738–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. In G. Watson (Ed.), Free Will, 2nd edition, (2003) (pp. 72–93). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swartzer, S. (2013). Appetitive besires and the fuss about fit. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 975–988.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swartzer, S. (2015). Humean externalism and the argument from depression. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 9(2), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Roojen, M. (1995). Humean motivation and Humean rationality. Philosophical Studies, 79(1), 37–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (1994). Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (2011). Dispassionate Opprobrium: On Blame and the Reactive Sentiments. In R. J. Wallace, R. Kumar, & S. Freeman (Eds.), Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Philosophy of T. M. Scanlon (pp. 348–372). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weintraub, R. (2007). Desire as belief, Lewis notwithstanding. Analysis, 67(2), 116–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, R. (1998). Constraining condemning. Ethics, 108(3), 489–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Widerker, D. (2003). Blameworthiness and Frankfurt’s argument against the principle of alternative possibilities. In D. Widerker & M. McKena (Eds.), Moral responsibility and alternative possibilities: essays on the importance of alternative possibilities (pp. 53–73). Burlington: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Widerker, D., & McKena, M. (2003). Moral responsibility and alternative possibilities: essays on the importance of alternative possibilities. Burlington: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (2011). Blame: Italian Style. In R. J. Wallace, R. Kumar, & S. Freeman (Eds.), Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Philosophy of T. M. Scanlon (pp. 332–347). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I’d like to thank Mark van Roojen and Steve Swartzer for extensive conversation about the topics in this paper. I thank several anonymous referees for comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I thank Franz-Peter Griesmaier, Susanna Goodin, and audience members for helpful discussion at a special colloquium on my work at the University of Wyoming, December 3, 2015. I thank Aaron Elliot, Luke Elwonger, Allison Fritz, Shane George, Christopher Gibilisco, Cliff Hill, Timothy Loughrist, Chris Richards, Chelsea Richardson, Andy Spaid, Mark Selzer, Lauren Sweetland, and others in attendance at the Friday Research Colloquium at the University of Nebraska-Linocln, Fall 2015, for helpful discussion. Finally, I thank Derek Shiller and audience members at the 4th Annual Philosopher’s Cocoon Philosophy Conference, Fall 2016, for helpful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adam R. Thompson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Thompson, A.R. Blame and the Humean Theory of Motivation. Philosophia 45, 1345–1364 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9818-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9818-z

Keywords

Navigation