Skip to main content
Log in

Pacifism and Punishment

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article seeks to expose some of the implications of certain versions of pacifism for matters of criminal punishment, arguing that the plausibility of these versions of pacifism depend on the extent to which their implicit denials of certain central punishment-related concepts are themselves reasonable.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Narveson (1984). Emphasis added.

  2. While the focus of this paper is on the particular conceptions of the nature of pacifism found in Narveson and May, respectively, a comprehensive account of pacifism and punishment would require a treatment of a variety of other conceptions of pacifism and their implications for the punishment-related concepts in question. There are a host of conceptions of pacifism in the philosophical literature. More recent accounts include those found in Holmes (1999; 1989); Regan (1972); and Ryan (1983, 2009).

  3. Feinberg (1970). Feinberg believes that the hard treatment and reprobatory aspects of criminal punishment must be part of the definition of “punishment.”

  4. Narveson, “Pacifism: A Philosophical Analysis,” p. 87.

  5. Rawls (1999, Chapter 2).

  6. A view such as this is also found in Reiman (1998).

  7. May (2008, p. 34).

  8. May (2008, pp. 39-40).

  9. For an argument for this position, see Corlett (2010).

  10. Rawls (1999, Chapter 2).

  11. Reiman (1998, p. 67).

  12. Reiman (1998, p. 68).

  13. Reiman (1998, p. 68).

  14. Corlett (2013, Chapter 8).

  15. Reiman’s does not because it makes deterrence a central justificatory component of capital punishment. While most retributivists follow Immanuel Kant in holding that desert is always the primary justification of punishment, they can and often do admit that social utility considerations such as deterrence can be justified only in a secondary sense (See Corlett 2013, Chapter 4).

  16. This notion of retributivism is articulated and defended in Corlett (2013, Chapter 5); Corlett (2001, 2003).

  17. Alarcón and Mitchell (2011, 2012).

  18. Many thanks to the referees of Philosophia and to Asa Kasher for their excellent comments on an earlier draft of this paper which was presented at the conference on pacifism at Belgrade University, Belgrade, Serbia, June 2012.

References

  • Alarcón, A., & Mitchell, P. (2011). Executing the will of the voters? A roadmap to mend or end the California legislature’s multi-billion-dollar death penalty debacle. Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, 45, S41–S224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alarcón, A., & Mitchell, P. (2012). Costs of capital punishment in California: Will voters choose reform this November? Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review, 46, S1–S34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boxer, K. E. (2013). Rethinking responsibility. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

  • Cooper, J., & Hutchinson, D. S. (Eds.). (1997). Plato: Complete works. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corlett, J. A. (2001). Making sense of retributivism. Philosophy, 76, 76–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corlett, J. A. (2003). Making more sense of retributivism. Philosophy, 78, 277–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corlett, J. A. (2010). U.S. responsibility for war crimes in Iraq. Res Publica, 16, 227–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corlett, J. A. (2013). Responsibility and punishment (4th ed.). Dordrecht: Springer. Chapter 8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1970). Doing and deserving. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Holmes, R. (1989). On war and morality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes, R. (1999). Pacifism for non-pacifists. Journal of Social Philosophy, 30, 387–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, L. (2008). Aggression and crimes against peace. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 39–40.

  • Narveson, J. (1984). Pacifism: A philosophical analysis. In J. White (Ed.), Assent/dissent. Dubuque: Kendall/Hunt.

  • Rawls, J. (1999). In S. Freeman (Ed.), Collected papers. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Regan, T. (1972). A defense of pacifism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 2, 73–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiman, J. (1998). Why the death penalty should be abolished in America. In L. Pojman & J. Reiman (Eds.), The death penalty: For and against. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.

  • Ryan, C. C. (1983). Self-defense, pacifism, and the possibility of killing. Ethics, 93, 508–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, C. C. (2009). War, sacrifice, and personal responsibility. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Washington, J. M. (Ed.). (1986). A testament of hope: The essential writings of Martin Luther King, Jr. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. Angelo Corlett.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Corlett, J.A. Pacifism and Punishment. Philosophia 41, 945–958 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-013-9468-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-013-9468-8

Keywords

Navigation