Skip to main content
Log in

The Ontology of Causal Process Theories

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is a widespread belief that the so-called process theories of causation developed by Wesley Salmon and Phil Dowe have given us an original account of what causation really is. In this paper, I show that this is a misconception. The notion of “causal process” does not offer us a new ontological account of causation. I make this argument by explicating the implicit ontological commitments in Salmon and Dowe’s theories. From this, it is clear that Salmon’s Mark Transmission Theory collapses to a counterfactual theory of causation, while the Conserved Quantity Theory collapses to David Fair’s phsyicalist reduction of causation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will use the terms “ontology” and “ontological commitment” in a strict sense, as referring only to those entities that are ontologically basic. So, if an ontological theory for example defines molecules in terms of atoms and not vice versa, I will say that this theory is ontologically committed to atoms, but not to molecules.

  2. One of the important consequences of this is that the criticisms of the Mark Transmission Theory which focus on the concept of “mark” (see Dowe 1992a, pp 200–202) miss the point. By stating that some pseudo-process can allow the transmittance of a mark, they criticize the test but not the theory itself, since its central statement, that only processes which possess permanent structural characteristic features can engage in causal interactions, remains untouched.

  3. Note that Dowe still formulates immanent causation in terms of cause and effect, such as “A is the cause of B”. The idea that the notion of immanent causation implies a switch from thinking in terms of cause and effect to thinking in terms of “causation” as such, without reference to causes and effects, is therefore obviously untrue. (see Dowe 2000, p 52).

  4. More correctly, Dowe rejects David Armstrong’s causal theory of identity, but this automatically entails rejecting Russell’s theory as well.

  5. It should be noted that this does not mean that world lines or Minkowski diagrams are useless in se. It only means that they do not add any information to the CQT.

  6. Of course, it can still be useful to make a distinction between causal objects and pseudo-objects instead, but this does not add any extra information which is not already contained in the definition of causal interactions. The CQ theory is only a theory of causal objects in the same way as the MT theory is a theory about causal processes. Dowe defines causal interactions as exchanges of conserved quantities. Of course, this implies that objects which do not possess such quantities cannot take part in a causal interaction. There is no need to state this explicitly in a different condition or definition. In any case, it is impossible that such a definition could contain extra ontological information.

  7. The main difference is that Dowe has traded in Fair’s notion of a transfer of a conserved quantity fora n exchange of a conserved quantity, which makes his theory symmetrical. As a consequence, Dowe supplements his theory with some conditions which involve statistical correlations in order to distinguish between cause and effect. (see the final chapter of Dowe 2000)

References

  • Chakravartty, A. (2005). Causal Realism: Events and Processes. Erkenntnis, 63, 7–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Vreese, L. (2006). Pluralism in the Philosophy of Causation: Desideratum or not? Philosophica, 5–13.

  • Dowe, P. (1992a). Wesley Salmon’s process theory of causality and the Conserved Quantity Theory. Philosophy of Science, 59(2), 195–216. Referred to as (Dowe 1992aa).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (1992b). An Empiricist Defense of the Causal Account of Explanation. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 6, 123–128. Referred to as (Dowe 1992b).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (1995). Causality and conserved quantities: a reply to Salmon. Philosophy of Science, 62(2), 321–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2000). Physical Causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fair, D. (1979). Causation and the Flow of Energy. Erkenntnis, 14, 219–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Handfield, T., Twardy, C., Korb, K., & Oppy, G. (2008). The Metaphysics of Causal Models. Erkenntnis, 68, 149–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (1995). Salmon on explanatory relevance. Philosophy of Science, 62(2), 304–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific Explanation, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science Volume XIII (pp. 410–506). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1948). Human knowledge. Its scope and limits. London: George Allen and Unwin LTD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1953). On the notion of cause, with applications to the free-will problem. In H. Feigl & M. Brodbeck (Eds.), Readings in the philosophy of science. New York: Appleton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1994). Causality without counterfactuals. Philosophy of Science, 61(2), 297–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1997). A reply to two critiques. Philosophy of Science, 64(3), 461–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anton Froeyman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Froeyman, A. The Ontology of Causal Process Theories. Philosophia 40, 523–538 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-011-9329-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-011-9329-2

Keywords

Navigation