Skip to main content
Log in

In Nietzsche’s Shadow: Unenlightened Politics

The Seduction of Unreason: The Intellectual Romance with Fascism from Nietzsche to Postmodernism by Richard Wolin. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2004, 400pp.

  • Critical Study
  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. See Rorty (1988, 1990, 2004).

  2. An early indictment comes from one of Heidegger’s most famous students, Herbert Marcuse, who wrote to his former teacher in 1948 seeking some acknowledgment from Heidegger of what he had endorsed; none was received. Marcuse had admonished: “...we cannot make the distinction between the philosopher and the human being Martin Heidegger – It contradicts your own philosophy. A philosopher can be mistaken about politics – Then he will openly admit his error. But he cannot be mistaken about a regime that murdered millions of Jews merely because they were Jews, that made terror part of everyday life and turned everything that ever was really tied to the concept of spirit and freedom and truth into its bloody opposite.” Quoted in Schalow (1989), p. 124. See also Rockmore (1992). Rather than disassociating Nazism from the substance of his philosophy, Heidegger himself proudly asserted an essential connection, as Mark Lilla reports: “In 1936...Karl Löwith saw him in Rome, where he wore a Nazi lapel pin and explained to his former student how concepts in Being and Time had inspired his political engagement.” See Lilla (2001), pp. 22–23 and similarly Wolin (1991), p. 10.

  3. See Sternhell (1986); Sternhell, Mario Sznajder and Maia Asheri (1994).

  4. See Yovel (1998), and Wolin (1991), pp. 31–2 and 58.

  5. See for example, Aschheim (1992); Schrift (1995).

  6. Aschheim (1992), p. 258. (As is well-known, Heidegger devoted his lectures in 1936–1940 to Nietzsche.)

  7. Aschheim (1992), p. 259.

  8. Aschheim (1992), p. 261.

  9. Aschheim (1992), p. 55.

  10. See further, Noll (1994), on which Wolin draws.

  11. Odanjyk (1976), pp. 107–108. Consideration of these matters will in future have to include Bair’s (2003) massive Jung: A Biography, which cannot be addressed here.

  12. Gadamer (1997a), p.7.

  13. See Detmer (1997) and Gadamer (1997b).

  14. On these matters, appreciations and defences of Gadamer include McDowell (2002) and Taylor (2002). Gadamer aside, I myself have written favourably about the role of tradition in morals and politics, in Aronovitch (1996).

  15. See Gadamer (1997a), p. 13.

  16. See also Grondin (2003), pp. 181–183.

  17. Wolin has reviewed Grondin’s biography in Wolin (2003).

  18. See Eribon (1991), Chapter 19.

  19. By way of background, there is the interesting (but wearying) “L’affaire Derrida” which played out over many weeks in The New York Review of Books (1993). Derrida, Wolin, and others engaged in an exchange over Wolin’s (1991) publication in The Heidegger Controversy of a version of an interview Derrida had earlier given in France.

  20. See Bennington (2001) and Simon Critchley (1992) pp. XII, 236.

  21. See Dworkin (1986).

References

  • Appiah, K. A. (2005). The ethics of identity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aronovitch, H. (1996). Reflective equilibrium or evolving tradition? Inquiry, 39(3–4), 399–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aschheim, S. E. (1992). The Nietzsche legacy in Germany, 1890–1990. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bair, D. (2003). Jung: A biography. Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barry, B. (2001). Culture and equality. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennington, G. (2001). Derrida and politics. In T. Cohen (Ed.), Jacques Derrida and the humanities: A critical reader (pp. 193–212). Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, W. (1991). Identity/difference: Democratic negotiations of political paradox. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Critchley, S. (1992). The ethics of deconstruction. Oxford, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Blackwell.

  • Derrida, J. (1992). Forces: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority’. In D. Cornell, M. Rosenfeld, & D. G. Carlson (Eds.), Deconstruction and the possibility of justice. London: Routledge (Trans. Mary Quaintance).

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1994). Specters of Marx. New York: Routledge (Trans. Peggy Kamuf).

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (1997). Politics of friendship. London; New York: Verso (Trans. George Collins).

  • Derrida, J., Wolin, R., et al. (1993). L’affaire Derrida. New York Review of Books, 40 (4), 44–45, February 11; 40 (5), 57, March 4; 40 (6), 65–66, March 25; 40 (8), 68–69, April 22.

  • Detmer, D. (1997). Gadamer’s critique of the enlightenment. In L.E. Hahn (Ed.), The philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer (pp. 275–286). Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

  • Dworkin, R. (1986). Law’s empire. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eribon, D. (1991). Michel Foucault. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press (Trans. Betsy Wing).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferry, L., & Renaut, A. (1990). French philosophy of the sixties. Amherst: The University of Massachusetts (Trans. Mary Cattani).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferry, L., & Renaut, A. (Eds.) (1997). Why we are not Nietzscheans. Chicago: University of Chicago (Trans. Robert de Loaiza).

  • Gadamer, H-G. (1997a). Reflections on my philosophical journey. In L. E. Hahn (Ed.), The philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer (pp. 3–63). Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H-G. (1997b). Reply to David Detmer. In L. E. Hahn (Ed.), The philosophy of Hans-Georg Gadamer (pp. 287–288). Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grondin, J. (2003). Hans-Georg Gadamer: A biography. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, pp. 157ff. (Trans. Joel Weinsheimer).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaufmann, W. [1950]1974. Nietzsche: Philosopher, psychologist, antichrist, 4th ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Kymlicka, W. (1995). Multicultural citizenship. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lilla, M. (2001). The reckless mind: Intellectuals in politics. New York: New York Review Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2002). Gadamer and Davidson on understanding and relativism. In J. Malpas, U. Answald, & J. Kertscher (Eds.), Gadamer’s Century: Essays in Honor of Hans-Georg Gadamer (pp. 173–93). Cambridge, Massachusetts, London: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nehamas, A. (1985). Nietzsche: Life as literature. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noll, R. (1994). The Jungian cult: Origins of a charismatic movement. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odanjyk, W. (1976). Jung and politics: The political and social ideas of C.G. Jung. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rockmore, T. (1992). Heidegger’s philosophy and Nazism. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1988). Taking philosophy seriously. The New Republic, 198 (15), 31–34, April 11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1990). Another possible world. London Review of Books. p. 21. February 8.

  • Rorty, R. (2004). Philosophical convictions. The Nation, pp. 53–54. June 14.

  • Ryan, A. (1993). Foucault’s life and hard times. New York Review of Books, 40 (7), 12–17. April 8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schalow, F. (1989). Heidegger, the polity and national socialism. Interpretation, 26 (1), 121–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrift, A. D. (1995). Nietzsche’s French legacy: A genealogy of poststructuralism. New York; London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sternhell, Z. (1986). Neither right nor left: Fascist ideology in France. Princeton: Princeton University Press (Trans. David Maisell).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sternhell, Z., Sznajder, M., & Asheri, M. (1994). The birth of fascist ideology: From cultural rebellion to political revolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press (Trans. David Maisel).

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmon, J. L. (1970). The origins of totalitarian democracy. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (2002). Understanding the other: A Gadamerian view on conceptual schemes. In J. Malpas, U. von Arnswald, & J. Kertscher (Eds.), Gadamer’s century: Essays in honor of Hans-Georg Gadamer (pp. 279–297). Boston: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C, et al. (1992). Multiculturalism and the politics of recognition. In A. Gutmann (Ed.), Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Walzer, M. (1986). The politics of Michel Foucault. In D. C. Hoy (Ed.), Foucault: A critical reader (p. 51–68). Oxford; New York: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolin, R (Ed.) (1991). The Heidegger controversy: A critical reader. New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Wolin, R. (2003). Socratic Apology: A Wonderful, Horrible Life of Hans-Georg Gadamer. Book Forum. http://www.bookforum.com/wolin.html. (Summer).

  • Yovel, Y. (1998). Dark riddle: Hegel, Nietzsche and the Jews. University Park, Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hilliard Aronovitch.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Aronovitch, H. In Nietzsche’s Shadow: Unenlightened Politics. Philosophia 34, 209–221 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-006-9016-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-006-9016-x

Keywords

Navigation