Skip to main content
Log in

Conservation of behavioral diversity: on nudging, paternalism-induced monoculture, and the social value of heterogeneous beliefs and behavior

  • Published:
Mind & Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Aims of life vary with each and every individual; and the more society is civilized, the more will individuality be developed, and the more will desires be varied.

—Kropotkin (1892, Chapter IX paragraph 1).

Abstract

Heterogeneous beliefs and decision processes generate positive externalities for social and economic systems, analogous to biodiversity in biological systems. Although some aspects of biodiversity (e.g., pests, parasites and bacteria) can lead to ecological and economic problems, biodiversity provides flows of beneficial ecological services and is widely regarded as a valuable natural resource and informational asset, whose value increases as we learn more and science progresses (Wilson in Bioscience 35(11):700–706, 1985). Heterogeneous beliefs and decision processes (and heterogeneous behaviors they generate) similarly provide flows of beneficial economic services. Behavioral diversity should therefore be seen as a natural resource and informational asset likely to improve human wellbeing in surprising ways in the future. Paternalistic policies motivated by the goal of “correcting” allegedly suboptimal beliefs and behavior that diverge from expert recommendations jeopardize behavioral diversity at a substantial cost to social welfare. The risk of encroaching on this beneficial behavioral heterogeneity with policies that aim to induce behavioral and belief monocultures should be included explicitly as costs when evaluating nudges and other paternalistic policies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Gigerenzer and Selten (2001), Smith (2003), Berg and Gigerenzer (2010), Berg (2014a) and Mousavi and Kheirandish (2014) for definitions of ecological rationality and the research program based on Herbert Simon's seminal work on bounded rationality. Ecological rationality measures "success" of procedures for making inferences or decisions, and the social institutions that influence those decisions and inferences, by domain-specific performance metrics (e.g., wealth in financial decision making tasks, clinical outcomes in health decision making tasks, objective accuracy in prediction tasks, happiness in mate choice, etc.).

  2. Simon (1957, p. 198): "The first consequence of the principle of bounded rationality is that the intended rationality of an actor requires him to construct a simplified model of the real situation in order to deal with it. He behaves rationally with respect to this model, and such behavior is not even approximately optimal with respect to the real world."

    Simon (1979, p. 498): "The first is to retain optimization, but to simplify sufficiently so that the optimum (in the simplified world!) is computable. The second is to construct satisficing models that provide good enough decisions with reasonable costs of computation. By giving up optimization, a richer set of properties of the real world can be retained in the models…"

  3. Shafer (1986): "The idea that subjective expected utility is uniquely normative plays only a regressive role; it obstructs the development and understanding of alternative tools for subjective judgment of probability and value. Thus, subjective expected utility is just one of several possible tools for constructing a decision."

  4. For example, we can expect some proportion of the population to formulate different beliefs and take different actions depending on whether expert advice is disseminated as "Consider this information and then you can decide what is best for you" as opposed to "This decision has been structured to influence you to choose what experts believe is best for you."

  5. In Law, Legislation and Liberty (1973, p. 35), Hayek wrote: "Order is an indispensable concept for the discussion of all complex phenomena, in which it must largely play the role the concept of law plays…".

  6. Zywicki (2018) reports that participants in the private nudging program, Save More Tomorrow, contributed significantly more to tax-advantaged 401 k retirement accounts. Those participants who were successfully nudged to save more also wound up with problems, such as signficantly higher revolving balances on credit cards and other high-interest-rate credit products like payday lending. In Zywicki's evaluation, although the nudge worked as designed, the evidence suggested its effects on participants' financial and psychological wellbeing were net negative.

  7. (Simon1969, p. 53): "Human beings, viewed as behaving systems, are quite simple. The apparent complexity of our behavior over time is largely a reflection of the complexity of the environment in which we find ourselves."

  8. A similar tension can be seen in the sociology literature concerning ethnic and cultural diversity. Collins and Bilge (2016) advocate intersectional praxis acknowledging the autonomy and heterogeneity of individuals sharing a common minority group status. They argue for a pluralistic and context-specific approach rather than one-size-fits-all prescriptions for addressing social inequality based on single-identity factors (e.g., race, gender, social class). It is noteworthy that Collins and Bilge's arguments also apply to minority groups (defined by their anomalous dietary, health, and financial behaviors) targeted by nudge policies.

  9. Identification of rationality with internal logical consistency underpins the biases and heuristics research program inspired largely by Kahneman, which focuses on deviations from neoclassical rationality axioms and its prescriptive program of inducing greater behavioral conformity with those consistency requirements (de-biasing as in Jolls et al. 1998 or Thaler and Sunstein 2008; cf. Sheffrin 2017).

  10. In contrast, nudges designed to cue "System 2" such as cooling-off periods (i.e., more deliberation and analytic reflection of benefits and costs) are not vulnerable to this criticism.

  11. Hawkes (2018) reports allegations of influence from lobbyists representing pharmaceutical firms and complaints about removal of board members from Cochrane (a widely respected UK charity and Limited Liability Company). Many observers regard Cochrane as the most trusted and well-executed institutions committed to evidence-based evaluation of drugs and medical procedures using sophisticated meta-analyses of medical research studies. These allegations and controversy among former Cochrane Board members illustrate how fragile perceptions of experts' objectivity are and their vulnerability to (perceived) un-transparent influence.

References

  • Arthur BW (1994) Inductive reasoning and bounded rationality. Am Econ Rev Pap Proc 84:406–411

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennis W, Katsikopolous K, Goldstein D, Dieckmann A, Berg N (2012) Designed to fit minds: institutions and ecological rationality. In: Todd PM, Gigerenzer G, ABC Research Group (eds) Ecological rationality: intelligence in the world. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 409–427

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg N (2003) Normative behavioral economics. J Socio-Econ 32:411–427

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N (2006) A simple Bayesian procedure for sample size selection in an audit of property value appraisals. Real Estate Econom 34(1):133–155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N (2010) Behavioral economics. In: Free RC (ed) 21st century economics: a reference handbook, vol 2. Sage, Los Angeles, pp 861–872

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N (2014a) The consistency and ecological rationality schools of normative economics: singular versus plural metrics for assessing bounded rationality. J Econ Methodol 21(4):375–395

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N (2014b) Success from satisficing and imitation: entrepreneurs’ location choice and implications of heuristics for local economic development. J Bus Res 67(8):1700–1709

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N (2015) Gerd Gigerenzer. In: Altman M (ed) Real world decision making: an encyclopedia of behavioral economics. Praeger, Santa Barbara

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg N (2017) Smart people’s rational mistakes. In: Altman M (ed) Handbook of behavioral economics and smart decision-making: rational decision-making within the bounds of reason. Edward Elgar Publishing, Cheltenham, pp 43–67

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N (2018) Decentralization mislaid: on new paternalism and skepticism toward experts. Rev Behav Econ 5(3–4):361–387

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Gabel T (2015) Did Canadian welfare reform work? The effects of new reform strategies on Social Assistance participation. Can J Econ 48(2):494–528

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Gabel T (2017) Did tax cuts on earned income reduce Social Assistance participation in Canada? Aust Tax Forum 32(1):175

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Gigerenzer G (2007) Psychology implies paternalism? Bounded rationality may reduce the rationale to regulate risk-taking. Soc Choice Welf 28(2):337–359

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Gigerenzer G (2010) As-if behavioral economics: neoclassical economics in disguise? Hist Econ Ideas 18(1):133–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Hoffrage U (2008) Rational ignoring with unbounded cognitive capacity. J Econ Psychol 29:792–809

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Kim JY (2014) Prohibition of Riba and Gharar: a signaling and screening explanation? J Econ Behav Organ 103:146–159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Kim JY (2015) Quantity restrictions with imperfect enforcement in an over-used commons: permissive regulation to reduce over-use? J Inst Theor Econ 171(2):308–329

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Kim JY (2016) Equilibrium national border and its stability. Prague Econ Pap 25(6):637–654

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Kim JY (2018a) Plea Bargaining with multiple defendants and its deterrence effect. Int Rev Law Econ 55:58–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Kim JY (2018b) Free expression and defamation. Law Probab Risk 17(3):201–223

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Kim JY (2019) A good advisor. Bull Econ Res 71(3):558–572

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Maital S (2007) Tailoring globalization to national needs and wellbeing: one size never fits all. Glob Bus Econ Rev 9(2/3):319–334

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Murdoch J (2008) Access to grocery stores in Dallas. Int J Behav Healthc Res 1(1):22–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Hoffrage U, Abramczuk K (2010) Fast acceptance by common experience: FACE-recognition in Schelling’s model of neighborhood segregation. Judgm Decis Mak 5(5):391–410

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Abramczuk K, Hoffrage U (2013) Schelling’s neighborhood segregation model with FACE-recognition. In: Hertwig R, Hoffrage U, The ABC Research Group (eds) Simple heuristics in a social world. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 225–257

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, El-Komi M, Kim JY (2016a) The puzzle of uniform standards and market segmentation among Islamic banks. J Econ Behav Organ 132:39–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Biele G, Gigerenzer G (2016b) Consistent Bayesians are no more accurate than non-Bayesians: economists surveyed about PSA. Rev Behav Econ (ROBE) 3(2):189–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bookstaber R, Langsam J (1985) On the optimality of coarse behaviour rules. J Theor Biol 116(2):161–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins PH, Bilge S (2016) Intersectionality. Policy Press, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Conly S (2014) Against autonomy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cyert R, March JG (1992 [1963]) A behavioral theory of the firm, 2 ed. Wiley-Blackwell, Hoboken. ISBN: 0-631-17451-6

  • Dold MF, Schubert C (2018) Toward a behavioral foundation of normative economics. Rev Behav Econ 5(3–4):221–241. https://doi.org/10.1561/105.00000097

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eckel C, Grossman PJ, Johnston RM (2005) An experimental test of the crowding out hypothesis. J Public Econ 89(8):1543–1560

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein RA (1995) Simple rules for a complex world. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein RA (2003) Skepticism and freedom: a modern case for classical liberalism. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Gage D (2012) The venture capital secret: 3 out of 4 start-ups fail. Wall Street J. https://www.wsj.com/articles/SB10000872396390443720204578004980476429190. Accessed 9 Oct 2019

  • Gigerenzer G (2016) On the supposed evidence for libertarian paternalism. Rev Philos Psychol 6:361–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Selten R (2001) Rethinking rationality. In: Gigerenzer G, Selten R (eds) Bounded rationality: the adaptive toolbox. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 1–12

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Todd PM, The ABC Research Group (1999) Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gintis H (2007) The dynamics of general equilibrium. Econ J 117(523):1280–1309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison GW, Ross D (2018) Varieties of paternalism and the heterogeneity of utility structures. J Econ Methodol 25(1):42–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawkes N (2018) Cochrane director’s expulsion results in four board members resigning. BMJ. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.k3945

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1973) Law, legislation and liberty. Routledge, Abingdon

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig R, Hoffrage U, The ABC Research Group (2013) Simple heuristics in a social world. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Infante G, Lecouteux G, Sugden R (2016) Preference purification and the inner rational agent: a critique of the conventional wisdom of behavioural welfare economics. J Econ Methodol 23(1):1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jolls C, Sunstein CR, Thaler R (1998) A behavioral approach to law and economics. Stanf Law Rev 50:1471–1480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kameda T, Tsukasaki T, Hastie R, Berg N (2011) Democracy under uncertainty: the wisdom of crowds and the free-rider problem in group decision making. Psychol Rev 118:76–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knowles S, Stahlmann-Brown P (2020) Cash is not king in incentivising online surveys. Appl Econ Lett. https://doi.org/10.1080/13504851.2020.1734524

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kropotkin P (1892) The conquest of bread: chapter IV. http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/anarchist_archives/kropotkin/conquest/ch9.html. Accessed 12 Jan 2019

  • Mellström C, Johannesson M (2008) Crowding out in blood donation: was titmuss right? J Eur Econ Assoc 6(4):845–863

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom P, Stokey N (1982) Information, trade and common knowledge. J Econ Theory 26(1):17–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mousavi S, Kheirandish R (2014) Behind and beyond a shared definition of ecological rationality: a functional view of heuristics. J Bus Res 67:1780–1785

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rebonato R (2012) Taking liberties. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid R (2019) It’s forestry that must change—not farmers. For J. http://www.forestryjournal.co.uk/features/18001019.forestry-must-change–not-farmers/. Accessed 24 Nov 2019

  • Rizzo MJ, Whitman G (2018) Rationality as a process. Rev Behav Econ 5(3–4):201–219. https://doi.org/10.1561/105.00000098

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowland MP (2016) The food pyramid of the future. Forbes. https://www.forbes.com/sites/michaelpellmanrowland/2016/11/02/the-food-pyramid-of-the-future/#50d3d2324da3. Accessed 18 Jan 2019

  • Shafer G (1986) Savage revisited. Stat Sci 1(4):463–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sheffrin SM (2017) Behavioral law and economics is not just a refinement of law and economics. Oeconomia 7(3):331–352

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1957) Models of man. Wiley, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1969) The sciences of the artificial. MIT University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1979) Rational decision making in business organizations, Nobel Memorial Lecture 1978. Am Econ Rev 69(4):493–513

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1985) Human nature in politics: the dialogue of psychology with political science. Am Polit Sci Rev 79:293–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1990) Invariants of human behavior. Annu Rev Psychol 41:1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith VL (2003) Constructivist and ecological rationality in economics. Am Econ Rev 93(3):465–508

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2017) Do people really want to be nudged towards healthy lifestyles? Int Rev Econ 64:113–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2018) Paternalism and entrepreneurship. Rev Behav Econ 5(3–4):243–259. https://doi.org/10.1561/105.00000089

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein C, Vermeule A (2008) Conspiracy theories. Harvard public law working paper 08-03

  • Thaler RH, Benartzi S (2004) Save more tomorrow™: using behavioral economics to increase employee saving. J Polit Econ 112:S164–S187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2008) Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Todd PM, Gigerenzer G, ABC Research Group (2012) Ecological rationality: intelligence in the world. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 409–427

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Viale R (ed) (2001) Knowledge and politics. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Viale R (ed) (2012) Methodological cognitivism, vol 1. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Viale R (2018) The normative and descriptive weaknesses of behavioral economics-informed nudge: depowered paternalism and unjustified libertarianism. Mind Soc 17:53–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viale R (2019) Architecture of the mind and libertarian paternalism: is the reversibility of System 1 nudges likely to happen? Mind Soc 18:143–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viale R, Pozzali A (2010) Complex adaptive systems and the evolutionary triple helix. Crit Sociol 36(4):575–594. https://doi.org/10.1177/0896920510365923

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson EO (1985) The biological diversity crisis. Bioscience 35(11):700–706

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zywicki TJ (2018) The behavioral economics of behavioral law and economics. Rev Behav Econ 5(3–4):439–471. https://doi.org/10.1561/105.00000094

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nathan Berg.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Berg, N., Watanabe, Y. Conservation of behavioral diversity: on nudging, paternalism-induced monoculture, and the social value of heterogeneous beliefs and behavior. Mind Soc 19, 103–120 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-020-00228-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-020-00228-2

Keywords

Navigation