Skip to main content
Log in

The normative and descriptive weaknesses of behavioral economics-informed nudge: depowered paternalism and unjustified libertarianism

  • Published:
Mind & Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The article aims to demonstrate that the nudge theory suffers from three main weaknesses stemming from its theoretical dependence on behavioural economics. The first two weaknesses endanger the paternalistic goal, whereas the third does not justify the libertarian attribute. The first weakness lies in the incomplete realistic characterisation of behavioural economics theory that is the central theoretical pillar of Nudge theory. The second weakness is even more relevant. The normative model of behavioural economics is neoclassical rationality. It can be applied to choices in conditions of risk, when it is possible to forecast the probability of the outcomes of one’s choices. On the contrary the real life problems are inside a complex and uncertain environment. In an uncertain environment the neoclassical algorithms are no longer valid, in that they postulate the knowledge of the probability of the outputs. Thus errors and bias, as observed in behavioural economics, are not such in many instances, but they are instead adaptive and therefore rational responses to the context of decision-making. Therefore nudge theory that pursues the normative paternalistic objective of neutralising the bias and judgement errors discovered by behavioural economics and putting paternalistically the citizen on the right track, is in fact proceeding in the wrong direction. The last weakness concerns an assumption of Nudge theory about the duality of mind. System 1 represents the intuitive mind, while System 2 corresponds to the analytical one. System 1 tends to make decisions quickly and unconsciously, while System 2 follows a slow and conscious process. Biases and judgement errors are mainly generated by System 1. However, System 2 may later intervene to correct them. From this premise, the Nudge theory affirms its libertarian character. In this paper I will argue that the dualism of the mind would not entail the reversibility of some nudges, particularly of default states. In this way the fundamental pillar is weakened to justify the libertarian character of the nudge theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The identification of biases and formal errors of judgement is not a recent phenomenon. Adam Smith (1759) highlighted both the phenomena of “loss aversion” and “hyperbolic discounting” as explanatory factors for human behaviour. Niccolò Macchiavelli also drew attention to the decision-making power of both the “endowment effect” and “loss aversion” (1532; Italian Ed., 1961). Lastly, David Hume (1739) underlined the danger of “present bias” and the myopic nature of human judgement.

  2. For economic rationality I mean the Maximization of Susbjective Expected Utility. This model of rationality is based on canonic deductive logic, probability calculus and utility theory.

  3. According to Simon (1990), rationality is not bounded because of the computational failures of the mind with respect to the canons of economic rationality. Human rationality is bounded by the interactions between the mind and the environment. Mental computations may be considered failures in terms of the normative canons of economic rationality, but they are an adaptive success because they provide a good solution to a given complex task characterized by uncertainty. Therefore bounded rationality is a form of ecological and adaptive rationality (Gigerenzer and Selten 2001).

  4. Large worlds are those characterized by ontic uncertainties. According to Frank Knight (1921), they are situations that do not allow any probabilistic prediction but only estimation. Estimation corresponds to simple and intuitive heuristic decision making. Examples of these worlds are the environment and climate, natural disasters, diseases, financial, political, social and military crises, and so on. In reality most of our everyday life corresponds to large worlds.

  5. Descriptive methodology of economics aims at generating theories that are realistic representation of the cognitive procedures in economic decision making and that are supported by empirical data. Instrumentalist and anti-realist position might be also acceptable, from a pragmatic point of view (which I do not share), provided the theory produces good predictions and successful technological applications and no better theory exists with regard to empirical accuracy and computational simplicity. But, faced with the empirical failures of neoclassical economics, even Friedman’s “as if” fiction no longer works and therefore we must confront the problem of building a different representation of the economic phenomena which we want to explain and predict. In Blaug’s (1980) opinion neoclassical economics does not fit the methodological desiderata of an empirical theory. For example, consumer theory is full of economic laws that are only ad hoc and ex post facto rationalizations of all final demand outcomes. Therefore the only way to increase the empirical adequacy and predictive power of an economic theory is to open the black box of cognitive procedures generating the decision making and action (Viale 2012).

  6. Individuals were presented with 4 cards which were marked with an A, a D, a 2 and a 7 respectively on the visible side. On the hidden side, there might be letters or numbers.

  7. Most subjects almost never chose the card with a 7 on it which, if it had an A on the other side, would have falsified the rule. Many correctly chose the card marked with an A which, if it had a 7 on the other side might have disproved the rule. In general, however, this choice was guided by the expectation that the hidden side would have a 2 on it.

  8. Autonomy is based on conscious deliberation of choices according to personal preferences. The libertarian attribute may be attributed to policy making that empowers autonomy. If an individual is nudged by a policy maker or an architect of choice in a default state that he has not the psychological power to change, the nudge weakens the individual’s autonomy and it may not be considered libertarian.

  9. In Viale (submitted) I argue that the Sistem 1 and 2 model of mind, main pillar of the reversibility tenet of Nudge theory, is undermined by psychological and neural data on incubation and mind wandering.

References

  • Arkes HR, Gigerenzer G, Hertwig R (2016) How bad is incoherence? Decision 3(1):20–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baratgin J, Noveck IA (2000) Not only base rates are neglected in the engineer-lawyer problem: an investigation of reasoners’ underutilization of complementarity. Mem Cogn 28:79–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg N, Gigerenzer G (2010) As-if behavioral economics: neoclassical economics in disguise? Hist Econ Ideas XVIII 1:133–165

    Google Scholar 

  • Blaug M (1980) The methodology of economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chater N, Oaksford M (2008) The probabilistic mind: Prospects for Bayesian cognitive science. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cleermans A, Jimenez L (2002) Implicit learning and consciousness: a graded, dynamic perspective. In: French RM, Cleermans A (eds) Implicit learning and consciousness: an empirical, philosophical and computational consensus in the making. Psychology Press, Hove, pp 1–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen LJ (1981) Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated? Behav Brain Sci 4:317–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel C, Gigerenzer G (2006) Law and Heuristics: An interdisciplinary venture. In: Gigerenzer G, Engel C (eds) Heuristics and the law. The MIT Press, Canbridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans JSBT (2007) Hypotheticaal thinking: dual processes in reasoning and judgement. Psychology Press, Hove

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans JSBT (2008) Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgement and social cognition. Annu Rev Psychol 59:255–278

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans JSBT (2009) How amny dual-processes theories do we need? One, two or many? In: Frankish K, Evans J (eds) In two minds: dual processes and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Evans JSBT, Stanovich KE (2013) Dual-process theories of higher cognition: advancing the debate. Perspect Psychol Sci 8(3):223–241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr E, Schmidt K (1999) A theory of fairness, competition and cooperation. Q J Econ 114:817–868

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1953) Essays in positive economics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G (2015) On the supposed evidence for libertarian paternalism. Rev Philos Psychol. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0248-1

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Hoffrage U (1995) How to improve Bayesian reasoning without instructions: frequency formats. Psychol Rev 102:684–704

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Selten R (eds) (2001) Bounded rationality: the adaptive toolbox. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice P (1989) Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffith T, Kemp C, Tennembaum J (2008) Bayesian models of cognition. In: Sun R (ed) The cambridge handbook on computational psychology. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Griggs RA, Cox JR (1982) The elusive thematic-materials effect in Wason’s selection task. Br J Psychol 73:407–420

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1983) Representing and intervening. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hammond KR (1996) Human judgement and social policy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume D (1739) A treatise of human nature. Penguin Classics, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson Laird P, Legrenzi P, Sonino Legrenzi M (1972) Reasoning and a sense of reality. Br J Psychol 63:395–400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2011) Thinking fast and slow. Allen Lane, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Federick S (2002) Representiveness revisited: attribute subsistution in intuitive judgement. In: Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (eds) Heuristics and Biases: the psychology of intuitive judgment. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 49–81

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Tversky A (1979) Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47(2):263–291

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight FH (1921) Risk, uncertainty and profit. Houghton Mifflin Company, Boston and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger J, Funder DC (2004) Towards a balanced social psychology: causes, consequences and cures for the problem-seeking approach to social cognition and behaviour. Behav Brain Sci 27:313–376

    Google Scholar 

  • Kruglanski AW, Gigerenzer G (2011) Intuitive and deliberative judgements are based on common principles. Psychol Rev 118:97–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laibson D (1997) Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. Q J Econ 112(2):443–477

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macchiavelli N (1532) In: Il Principe (ed. it. 1961). Einaudi, Torino

  • Oliver A (2013) From nudging to budging: using behavioural economics to inform public sector policy, pp 1–16

  • Osman M (2004) An evaluation od dual-process theories of resoning. Pshychonomic Bull Rev 11(6):988–1010

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petty RE, Cacioppo JT (1986) The elaboration likelihood model of persuasion. In: Berkowitz L (ed) Advances in experimental social psychology. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rebonato R (2012) Taking liberties. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sah S, Cain DM, Loewenstein G (2013) Confessing one’s sins but still committing them: transparency and the failure of disclosure. In: Oliver A (ed) Behavioural public policy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage LJ (1954) the foundations of statistics, 2nd edn. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen A (2009) The idea of justice. Allen Lane, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1979) Rational decision making in business organization. Am Econ Rev 69:493–513

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1990) Invariants of human behaviour. Annu Rev Psychol 41:1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (2009) An empirically based microeconomics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA, Egidi M, Viale R, Marris R (1992) Economics bounded rationality and the cognitive revolution. Elgar, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloman SA (1996) The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychol Bull 119:3–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sloman SA (2002) Two systems of reasoning. In: Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (eds) Heuristics and biases: the psychology of intuitive judgement. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 379–398

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith A (1759) The theory of moral sentiments 2010. Penguin Classics, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith ER, Collins EC (2009) “Dual-process theories: A social psychological perspective. In: Evans J, Frankish K (eds) In two minds. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich KE (1999) Who is rational? Studies of individual differences in reasoning. Erlbaum, Mahwah

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich KE (2004) The robot’s rebellion: finding meaning in the age of Darwin. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich KE (2009) Distinguishing the reflective, algorithmic and autonomous minds: Is it time for a tri-process theory? In: Evans J, Frankish K (eds) In two minds. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz G (2010) Freefall: America, free markets, and the sinking of the worls economy. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH (1991) Quasi rational economics. Russell Sage Foundation, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler R, Sunstein CR (2008) Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth, and happiness. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Tversky A, Kahneman D (1986) Rational choice and the framing of decisions. Science 211:453–458

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B (1980) The scientific image. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Viale R (2012) Methodological cognitivism. Vol I, mind rationality and society. Springer, Heidelberg

    Google Scholar 

  • Viale R (2013) Methodological cognitivism. Vol II, cognition, science and innovation. Springer, Heidelberg

    Google Scholar 

  • Viale R (submitted) Architecture of the mind and libertarian paternalism: is the reversibility of Type 1 nudges likely to happen? Thinking & Reasoning

  • Wason PC (1966) Reasoning. In: Foss BM (ed) New horizons in psychology. Penguin, Harmondworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegener PT, Petty RE (1997) The flexible correction model: the role of naïve theories of bias in bias correction. In: Zanna MP (ed) Advances in experimental social psychology. Academic Press, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Riccardo Viale.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Viale, R. The normative and descriptive weaknesses of behavioral economics-informed nudge: depowered paternalism and unjustified libertarianism. Mind Soc 17, 53–69 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-019-00207-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-019-00207-2

Keywords

Navigation