Skip to main content
Log in

Clinical Equipoise and Adaptive Clinical Trials

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Ethically permissible clinical trials must not expose subjects to risks that are unreasonable in relation to anticipated benefits. In the research ethics literature, this moral requirement is typically understood in one of two different ways: (1) as requiring the existence of a state of clinical equipoise, meaning a state of honest, professional disagreement among the community of experts about the preferred treatment; or (2) as requiring an equilibrium between individual and collective ethics. It has been maintained that this second interpretation makes it mandatory to minimize the number of patients receiving the treatment that will eventually be shown to be inferior by the trial. This requirement has led to the development of adaptive trials, i.e., trials in which treatment allocation is determined by data accumulated during interim analysis. Many statisticians argue that in some circumstances—typically with potentially high benefits, as in the much discussed ECMO trial—adaptive design is the only ethically permissible experimental design. Nevertheless, some proponents of clinical equipoise argue that adaptive trials are neither ethically required nor permissible. More specifically, they argue that clinical trials using adaptive designs fail to meet the moral requirement of clinical equipoise, since these trials presuppose an epistemic state that is incompatible with a physician’s duty of care to her subjects. This paper emphasizes that the debate is to a large extent resting on an epistemological confusion. Specifically, I argue that this response conflates two different conceptions of statistical evidence (i.e., frequentist and Bayesian), and that recognizing this distinction elucidates an epistemological framework in which adaptive trials are both consistent with and recommended by the moral requirement of clinical equipoise.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Marquis (1983), Harrington (2000), and Matthews (2006) for similar descriptions of the issue.

  2. There are some exceptions to this principle, e.g., when there is insufficient supply of a treatment.

  3. Similarly, Pullman and Wang (2001) claim that “[m]anaging the tension between these obligations is generally accepted as the fundamental challenge in the ethical design of research giving rise to the dichotomy between ‘collective’ and ‘individual’ ethics.”

  4. There are many non-equivalent definitions of equipoise in the literature. The two conditions I have chosen here seem to be a good basis for the discussion that will follow. See Miller and Weijer (2003) for a more systematic analysis of the various definitions.

  5. Though it is beyond the scope of this paper to go in details (see, e.g. Matthews 2006), there are three broad categories of designs exploiting this strategy: sequential (repeated significance test), Bayesian, and decision-theoretic designs.

References

  • Armitage P (2003) Fisher, Bradford Hill, and randomization. Int J Epidemiol 32(6):925–928

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashby D (2006) Bayesian statistics in medicine: a 25 year review. Stat Med 25:3589–3631

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chard JA, Lilford RJ (1998) The use of equipoise in clinical trials. Soc Sci Med 47(7):891–898

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton DG (1982) Ethically optimised designs. Br J Clin Pharmacol 13(4):469–480

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freedman B (1987) Equipoise and the ethics of clinical research. N Engl J Med 317:141–145

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fried C (1974) Medical experimentation. North Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrington DP (2000) The randomized clinical trial. J Am Stat Assoc 95(449):312–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heilig CM, Weijer C (2005) A critical history of individual and collective ethics in the lineage of Lellouch and Schwartz. Clin Trials 2:244–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill AB (1963) Medical ethics and controlled trials. Br Med J 1(5337):1043–1049

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hogg R V, Tanis E A, Rao J M (2005) Probability and statistical inference, 7th edn. Pearson, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Lellouch J, Schwartz D (1971) L’essai thérapeutique: éthique individuelle ou éthique collective? Rev Inst Int Statist 39:127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marquis D (1983) Leaving therapy to chance. Hastings Cent Rep 13(4):40–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthews JNS (2006) Introduction to randomized controlled clinical trials, 2nd edn. Texts in statistical science. Chapman & Hall, London

  • McNamara P (1996) Must I do what I ought? (or will the least I can do do?). In: Brown MA, Carmo J (eds) Deontic logic, agency and normative systems. Springer, New York, pp 154–173

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Miller PB, Weijer C (2003) Rehabilitating equipoise. Kennedy Inst Ethics J 13(2):93–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer CR (2002) Ethics, data-dependent designs, and the strategy of clinical trials: time to start learning-as-we-go? Stat Methods Med Res 11:381–402

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer CR, Harutyun S (2007) Implementing a decision-theoretic design in clinical trials: why and how? Stat Med 26:4939–4957

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer CR, Rosenberger WF (1999) Ethics and practice: alternative designs for phase iii randomized clinical trials. Control Clin Trials 20:172–186

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piantadosi S (2005) Clinical trials: a methodological perspective, 2nd edn. Wiley, Hoboken

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pullman D, Wang X (2001) Adaptive designs, informed consent, and the ethics of research. Control Clin Trials 22:203–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Royall RM (1991) Ethics and statistics in randomized clinical trials. Stat Sci 6(1):52–62

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vere D (1981) Controlled clinical trials: the current ethical debate. J R Soc Med 74(2):85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walach H, Falkenberg T, Fønnebø V, Lewith G, Jonas WB (2006) Circular instead of hierarchical: methodological principles for the evaluation of complex interventions. BMC Med Res Methodol 6:29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ware JH (1989) Investigating therapies of potentially great benefit: ECMO. Stat Sci 4:298–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weijer C, Shapiro SH, Glass KC, Enkin MW (2000) Clinical equipoise and not the uncertainty principle is the moral underpinning of the randomised controlled trial. Br J Med 321:756–758

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Charles Weijer, Ariella Binik, and two anonymous reviewers for useful and constructive comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicolas Fillion.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fillion, N. Clinical Equipoise and Adaptive Clinical Trials. Topoi 38, 457–467 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9540-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-018-9540-x

Keywords

Navigation