Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Felt Reality and the Opacity of Perception

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We investigate the nature of the sense of presence that usually accompanies perceptual experience. We show that the notion of a sense of presence can be interpreted in two ways, corresponding to the sense that we are acquainted with an object, and the sense that the object is real. In this essay, we focus on the sense of reality. Drawing on several case studies such as derealization disorder, Parkinson’s disease and virtual reality, we argue that the sense of reality is two-way independent from the spatial and sensory contents of experience. We suggest that the sense of reality is an affective experience akin to a metacognitive feeling. Finally, we present a potentially important implication of our account for the current debate between Intentionalism and Naïve Realism. Since perception is “opaque” with respect to the reality of what is perceived, Intentionalism cannot refer to the sense of reality as what differentiates perception from sensory-like experiences such as imaginings. In contrast, Naïve Realism has an independent explanation of the specificity of perception.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Here we shall follow standard terminology and use the phrases “perceptual experience” and “perceptually experiencing” in a non-factive way, as referring to both veridical experiences (i.e. perceptions) and non-veridical (i.e. illusory or hallucinatory) sensory experiences. Moreover, we shall use the phrase “perceptual objects” to refer to what is perceived or at least perceptually experienced.

  2. One might suggest that derealization disorder (see Sect. 3.1) involves the second kind of mediation. Derealized subjects do not perceive any vehicle or representation that stands for the perceived object, but they still lack a sense of acquaintance with respect to the latter.

  3. In previous work (Dokic and Martin 2012, 2015; Martin and Dokic 2013), we argued that the phenomenology of perception is dual: one dimension is constituted by spatio-sensory contents while the other dimension consists in various feelings having to do with familiarity, confidence, but also reality (see Sect. 4).

  4. Note that derealization is most often accompanied by depersonalization in which patients feel an affective detachment from their own body. Some of the quoted literature deals more with depersonalization than with derealization.

  5. A referee suggested that dreams may involve a sense of reality, since dreamers may believe that what they dream about is real. This is debatable. One might claim that dreamers do not have genuine beliefs but only, at best, dreamt beliefs. Independently of this point, though, the dreaming metaphor used by derealized patients could be understood as referring to lucid dreams, which do not involve beliefs that what is dreamt is real.

  6. Could we not say, as a referee suggested, that the subject imagines that someone is around? We are not convinced. First, one might wonder how mere imagination could directly produce the behavioral reaction described by Sacks. Perhaps the suggestion is that the subject mistakes an imagining for a genuine perception. However, parkinsonians are not known to have source monitoring disturbances. Second, if the sense of reality experienced by the subject lacks sensory content, it is not clear what kind of imagination is involved—presumably not sensory (i.e. visual, auditory, tactile, etc.) imagination.

  7. Of course, as an anonymous referee pointed out to us, this kind of behavioral measure should be specific to the sense of reality in contrast to, for example, mere empathetic experiences in which the subject puts herself in the shoes of someone at the edge of a pit without actually having the sense that the pit is real. Empathetic experiences without the sense of reality can also involve physiological responses, but it is an empirical issue whether these responses are the same as the responses that accompany the sense of reality.

  8. The notion of processing fluency refers to the ease with which an operation is processed. It appears that many metacognitive feelings are a (more or less direct) function of processing fluency. See, e.g., Wurtz et al. (2007) and Oppenheimer (2008).

  9. We do not want to say that feelings of reality always depend on the fluency of actual perceptual processes. As we have seen above (Sect. 3.2), the feeling of reality in Parkinson’s syndrome is generated independently of perceptual processes. There is probably more than one kind of cue underlying feelings of reality, and there is also the possibility of monitoring failure (the system over-generates a feeling of reality in the absence of the relevant cue).

  10. This might be seen as an instance of what Travis (2004) calls “the silence of the senses”. Perception does not “tell” us whether the perceptual object is real or not.

  11. Here we discuss only Intentionalist views that allow for singular representations (“This is F”, or “This F”; see Burge 2010), or general representations involving free or bound variables (“x is F”, “There is an F”). All of these representations might be claimed to rest on the possession of suitable criteria of identity. We leave to one side the different view that perceptual experience involves only feature-placing representations in Peter Strawson’s sense (Strawson 1959), namely representations of the form “It’s hot”, “It’s raining”, or “Redness over there”.

  12. For the distinction between sortal concepts and categorial concepts, see Lowe (2012). For a defense of the claim that perception of an object (e.g. a cat) requires the possession and deployment of the relevant categorial concept (e.g. an animal), see McDowell (2008a).

  13. For a defense of the claim that the concept of an object can be a sortal concept, see Xu and Carey (1997). For a dissenting voice, see Wiggins (1997).

References

  • Arango-Muñoz S (2014) The nature of epistemic feelings. Philos Psychol 27(2):193–211

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arango-Muñoz S, Michaelian K (2014) Epistemic feelings, epistemic emotions: review and introduction to the focus section. Philosophical Inq 2(1):97–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayers M (1997) Is physical object a sortal concept? A reply to Xu. Mind Lang 12(3&4):393–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach-y-Rita P (2004) Tactile Sensory Substitution Studies. Ann NY Acad Sci 1013:83–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach-y-Rita P, Collins CC, Saunders FA, White B, Scadden L (1969) Vision substitution by tactile image projection. Nature 221:963–964

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barfield W, Hendrix C (1995) The effect of update rate on the sense of presence within virtual environments. Virtual Real 1:3–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnier AJ, Mitchell CJ (2005) Looking for the fundamental effects of hypnosis. Invited address at the 35th annual congress of the Australian society of hypnosis (scientific program), Sydney, Australia

  • Bayne T, Montague M (2011) Cognitive phenomenology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burge T (2010) Origins of objectivity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne A (2010) Recollection, perception, imagination. Philos Stud 148(1):15–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell J (2002) Reference and consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Casati R, Pasquinelli E (2005) Is the subjective feel of “presence” an uninteresting goal? J Vis Lang Comput 16:428–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997) Being there: putting brain body and world together again. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane T (2006) Is there a perceptual relation? In: Gendler TS, Hawthorne J (eds) Perceptual experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 126–146

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Diederich JN, Fénelon G, Stebbins G, Goetz GC (2009) Hallucinations in Parkinson disease. Nat Rev Neurol 5:331–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dokic J, Martin J-R (2012) ‘Disjunctivism, hallucinations, and metacognition’. WIREs Cognit Sci 3:533–543. doi:10.1002/wcs.1190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dokic J, Martin J-R (2015) ‘Looks the same but feels different’, a metacognitive approach to cognitive penetrability. In: Zeimbekis J, Raftopoulos A (eds) The cognitive penetrability of perception, new philosophical perspectives. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunlosky J, Bjork RA (eds) (2008) Handbook of metamemory and memory. Psychology Press, Hillsdale, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Esquirol E (1838) Des maladies mentales. JB Baillière, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Farkas K (2014) A sense of reality. In: MacPherson F, Platchias D (eds) Hallucinations. MIT Press, Cambridge (Mass.), pp 399–417

    Google Scholar 

  • Fénelon G (2008) Psychosis in Parkinson’s disease: phenomenology, frequency, risk factors, and current understanding of pathophysiologic mechanisms. CNS Spectr 13(3 Suppl 4):18–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fénelon G (2013) Hallucinations associated with neurological disorders and sensory loss. In: Jardri R, Cachia A, Thomas P (eds) The neuroscience of hallucinations. Springer, Berlin, pp 59–83

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fish W (2009) Perception, hallucination, and illusion. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guarniero G (1974) Experience of tactile vision. Perception 3:101–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley S, Noe A (2003) Neural plasticity and consciousness: reply to block. Trends Cogn Sci 7(1):342

  • Husserl E (1907) Ding und Raum (thing and space). In: Claesges U (ed) Husserliana, vol 16. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers K (1963) General psychopathology (7th edn) (trans: Hoenig J, Hamilton MW). University of Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Johnson MK, Raye CL (1981) Reality monitoring. Psychol Rev 88:67–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson MK, Hashtroudi S, Lindsay DS (1993) Source monitoring. Psychol Bull 114(1):3–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat A (2000) The feeling of knowing: some metatheoretical implications for consciousness and control. Conscious Cogn 9:149–171

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat A (2006) Are we frightened because we run away? Some evidence from metacognitive feelings. In: Uttl B, Ohta N, Siegenthaler AL (eds) Memory and emotion: interdisciplinary perspectives. Oxford, Blackwell, pp 83–103

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat A (2007) Metacognition and consciousness. In: Zelazo PD, Moscovitch M, Thompson E (eds) Cambridge handbook of consciousness. CUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe EJ (2012) Individuation, reference, and sortal terms. In: Raftopolous A, Machamer P (eds) Perception, realism, and the problem of reference. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 123–141

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Martin MGF (2002) The transparency of experience. Mind Lang 17:376–425

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin MGF (2006) On being alienated. In: Gendler TS, Hawthorne J (eds) Perceptual experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 354–410

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Martin J-R, Dokic J (2013) seeing absence or absence of seeing? Thought J Philos 2(2):117–125

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin J-R, Le Corre F (2015) Sensory substitution is substitution. Mind Lang 30(2):209–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M (2005) Seeing, doing, and knowing. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen M (2010) Two visual systems and the feeling of presence. In: Gangopadhyay N, Madary M, Spicer F (eds) Perception, action, and consciousness: sensorimotor dynamics and two visual systems. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (1994) Mind and world. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (Mass)

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (2008a) Avoiding the myth of the given. In: Lindgaard J (ed) John McDowell: experience, norm, and nature. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 1–14

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell J (2008b) Responses. In: Lindgaard J (ed) John McDowell: experience, norm, and nature. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 200–268

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Meehan M, Insko B, Whitton M, Brooks FP (2002) Physiological measures of presence in stressful virtual environments. ACM Trans Graph 21:645–652

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melges FT, Tinklenberg JR, Deardorff CM, Davies NH, Anderson RE, Owen CA (1974) Temporal disorganization and delusional-like ideation. Processes induced by hashish and alcohol. Arch Gen Psychiatry 30(6):855–861

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen T (2007) Felt presence: paranoid delusion or hallucinatory social imagery? Conscious Cogn 16:975–983

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nudds M (2009) Recent work in perception: Naïve Realism and its opponents. Anal Rev 69:334–346

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheimer DM (2008) The secret life of fluency. Trends Cognit Sci 12(6):237–241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parnas J, Sass LA (2001) Self, solipsism, and schizophrenic delusions. Philos Psychiatry Psychol 8(2):101–120. doi:10.1353/ppp.2001.0014

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pascual-Leone A, Hamilton R (2001) The metamodal organization of the brain. Prog Brain Res 134:427–445

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pasquinelli E (2012) L’illusion de réalité. Vrin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Peyroux E, Thibaut F, Franck N (2013) Hallucinations. EMC Psychiatr 10(4):1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Prothero J, Parker D, Furness T, Wells M (1995) In proceedings of the conference on experimental analysis and measurement of situational awareness Embry-Riddle Aeronautical Univ., Datona Beach, Florida, USA, pp 359–366

  • Proust J (2013) The philosophy of metacognition. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reber R, Schwartz N, Winkielman P (2004) Processing fluency and aesthetic pleasure: is beauty in the perceiver’s processing experience? Personal Soc Psychol Rev 8(4):364–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed G, Sedman G (1964) Personality and depersonalization under sensory deprivation conditions. Percept Mot Skills 18:659–660

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell MB, Olesen J (1996) A nosographic analysis of the migraine aura in a general population. Brain 9(2):355–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacco RG (2010) The circumplex structure of depersonalization/derealization. Int J Psychol Stud 2:26–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacks O (2012) Hallucinations. Picador, Coydon

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanchez-Vives MV, Slater M (2005) From presence to consciousness through virtual reality. Nat Rev Neurosci 6:332–339

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shanon B (2002) The antipodes of the mind: charting the phenomenology of the ayahuasca experience. Oxford University Press, Oxford and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Shorvon JH, Hill JDN, Burkitt E, Halstead H (1946) The depersonalization syndrome. Proc R Soc Med 39:779–792

    Google Scholar 

  • Slater M (2009) Place illusion and plausibility can lead to realistic behaviour in immersive virtual environments. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 364 1535((Dec)):3549–3557

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slater M, Spanlang B, Corominas D (2010) Simulating virtual environments within virtual environments as the basis for a psychophysics of presence. ACM Trans Graph 29(4):1–9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spelke E (1990) Principles of object perception. Cognition 14:29–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson PF (1959) Individuals: an essay in descriptive metaphysics. Methuen, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Travis C (2004) The silence of the senses. Mind 113:57–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Usoh M, Catena E, Arman S, Slater M (2000) Using presence questionnaires in reality. Presence-Teleoper. Virtual Environ 9:497–503

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins D (1997) Sortal concepts: a reply to Xu. Mind Lang 12(3–4):413–421

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wineburg E, Straker N (1973) An episode of acute, self-limiting depersonalization following a first session of hypnosis. Am J Psychiatry 130:98–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim R (ed) (1980) Seeing-as, seeing-in, and pictorial representation. In: Art and its object, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 205–226

  • Wurtz P, Reber R, Zimmermann TD (2007) The feeling of fluent perception: a single experience from multiple asynchronous sources. Conscious Cogn 17:171–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xu F, Carey S (1997) From lot’s wife to a pillar of salt: evidence that physical object is a sortal concept. Mind Lang 12(3–4):365–392

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmons P, Panter A (2003) The influence of rendering quality on presence and task performance in a virtual environment. In: Proceedings of IEEE virtual reality, 2003. IEEE, pp 293–294

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to three anonymous referees for helpful comments, which we hope have led to clarifying our discussion in this essay. This work has been supported by the following two grants: ANR-10-LABX-0087 IEC and ANR-10-IDEX-0001-02 PSL.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jérôme Dokic.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dokic, J., Martin, JR. Felt Reality and the Opacity of Perception. Topoi 36, 299–309 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9327-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-015-9327-2

Keywords

Navigation