Skip to main content
Log in

Possibilistic beliefs in strategic games

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We introduce possibilistic beliefs into strategic games, describing a player’s belief about his opponents’ strategies as the set of their strategies he regards as possible. We formulate possibilistic strategic games where each player has preferences over his own strategies conditional on his possibilistic belief about his opponents’ strategies. We define several solution concepts for possibilistic strategic games such as (strict) equilibria, rationalizable sets, iterated elimination of never-best responses, and iterated elimination of strictly dominated strategies, and we study their properties and relationships. We develop a class of possibilistic strategic games called possibilistic supermodular games to relate supermodular games to possibilistic strategic games. Lastly, we discuss a direction of extending our possibilistic framework to games with incomplete information.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Luo (2001) adopts Bernheim’s (1984) notion of point rationalizability (in mixed strategies). See also Luo (2016) for a notion of rationalizability called true rationalizability, which is mathematically equivalent to point rationalizability.

  2. The terminologies of L-type, U-type, and LU-type follow from Maeda (2015), who considers similar preferences for games with set-valued payoffs.

  3. For simplicity, we sometimes drop the modifier “possibilistic” or “possibilistically” when we refer to our solution concepts.

  4. A binary relation \(\ge\) on a set X is a partial order if it is reflexive, antisymmetric, and transitive. A partially ordered set \((X, \ge )\) (or a set X with a partial order \(\ge\)) is a complete lattice if for any \(Y \subseteq X\), \(\inf (Y)\) and \(\sup (Y)\) exist as elements of X.

  5. In contrast, the standard SEU preference model corresponds to a model of situation where for every subset \(S' \subseteq S\), each player i’s type space is given by \(\Delta ({\tilde{S}}'_{-i})\), the set of probability distributions over \({\tilde{S}}'_{-i}\), as explained in Example 1 of Chen et al. (2016).

  6. Even if the players have the A-type, L-type, or U-type conditional preference systems, their best-response mappings do not change, and we can draw the same conclusions about equilibria and rationalizable sets. Since \(b_1(\{L\}) = \{U\}\) is not contained in \(b_1(\{L,R\}) = \{D\}\), \(b_1\) is not nondecreasing, and thus this game does not have the \({\mathcal {L}}\)-property.

  7. If the game is not finite and r is continuous, \(R^*\) can be computed as \(r^{\omega }(S):= \cap _{k<\omega } r^k(S)\), where \(\omega\) is the first infinite ordinal. See Olszewski (2021) for the definition of a continuous mapping. In general, we need transfinite induction to obtain the largest fixed point. In Sect. 3.3, we provide a general treatment using transfinite iterations.

  8. A binary relation \(\ge\) on a set X is a strict partial order if it is irreflexive, asymmetric, and transitive. Note that each player’s preference relation conditional on any nonempty belief is a strict partial order for any conditional preference system represented by a payoff function (which includes A-type, L-type, and U-type systems) as well as any LU-type conditional preference system.

  9. Chen et al. (2007) and Chen et al. (2016) denote this definition of IESDS by IESDS* to distinguish it from other forms of IESDS.

  10. For any product belief \(B \in \times _{i \in N} {\mathcal {P}}(S_i)\) and any \(i \in N\), we use \(B_i\) and \(B_{-i}\) instead of \({\tilde{B}}_i\) and \({\tilde{B}}_{-i}\), respectively.

  11. These results also follow from Lemma 1 of Apt (2007).

  12. We use the product order when we compare elements of \(S_{-i}\) or S.

  13. For any set X with a partial order \(\ge\) and any \(y, z \in X\), [yz] denotes the set \(\{ x \in X: z \ge x \ge y \}\) and is called an interval.

  14. See Milgrom and Roberts (1990) for the definition of order continuity.

  15. Alternatively, we can assume that for every \(i \in N\), \(u_i\) is single-plateaued on \(S_i\) so that \(\arg \max _{s_i \in S_i} u_i(s_i, s_{-i}) = [{\underline{\rho }}_i(s_{-i}), {\overline{\rho }}_i(s_{-i})]\) instead of \(\{ \rho _i(s_{-i}) \}\). Then, for every \(i \in N\), we have \({\bar{b}}_i(B_{-i}) = [ {\underline{\rho }}_i({\underline{s}}_{-i}), {\overline{\rho }}_i({\overline{s}}_{-i}) ]\) for all closed \(B_{-i} \in \times _{j \ne i} {\mathcal {P}}_0(S_j)\). To obtain Proposition 5, it suffices to require \({\bar{b}}_i(B_{-i}) = [ {\underline{\rho }}_i({\underline{s}}_{-i}), {\overline{\rho }}_i({\overline{s}}_{-i}) ]\) for \(B_{-i} = S_{-i}\) and all intervals \(B_{-i}\) in \(S_{-i}\) in the definition of a possibilistic supermodular game.

  16. Note that, if \(R^*\) is a singleton, it is a possibilistic equilibrium.

  17. Note that \({\overline{q}}_{-i}\) can be positive infinity, and we set \({\tilde{q}}(+\infty ) = 0\).

  18. In the equilibrium (or rationalizability) condition for type \(t_i\) of player i, he considers the behavior of player \(j \ne i\) whose type \(t_j\) contains a state in \(t_i\). Hence, if there is a self-evident event \(E \subseteq \Omega\) (i.e., if E is a union of elements of \(T_i\) for every \(i \in N\)) (see Sect. 5.2 of Osborne and Rubinstein, 1994), equilibrium conditions are entangled only within E. In other words, if \(\Omega\) can be partitioned into multiple self-evident events, equilibrium beliefs can be obtained separately on each self-evident event.

References

  • Aghassi, M., & Bertsimas, D. (2006). Robust game theory. Mathematical Programming, 107, 231–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Apt, K. R. (2007). The many faces of rationalizability. The B.E. Journal of Theoretical Economics, 7(1), 18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Apt, K. R., & Zvesper, J. A. (2010). The role of monotonicity in the epistemic analysis of strategic games. Games, 1, 381–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergemann, D., & Morris, S. (2017). Belief-free rationalizability and informational robustness. Games and Economic Behavior, 104, 744–759.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B. D. (1984). Rationalizable strategic behavior. Econometrica, 52(4), 1007–1028.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, J., & Micali, S. (2015). Mechanism design with possibilistic beliefs. Journal of Economic Theory, 156, 77–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, J., Micali, S., & Pass, R. (2015a). Tight revenue bounds with possibilistic beliefs and level-\(k\) rationality. Econometrica, 83(4), 1619–1639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, J., Micali, S., & Pass, R. (2015b). Supplement to "Tight revenue bounds with possibilistic beliefs and level-\(k\) rationality". Econometrica Supplemental Material. https://doi.org/10.3982/ECTA12563

  • Chen, Y.-C., Long, N. V., & Luo, X. (2007). Iterated strict dominance in general games. Games and Economic Behavior, 61(2), 299–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Y.-C., Luo, X., & Qu, C. (2016). Rationalizability in general situations. Economic Theory, 61, 147–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dow, J., & Werlang, S. (1994). Nash equilibrium under Knightian uncertainty: Breaking down backward induction. Journal of Economic Theory, 64(2), 305–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Echenique, F. (2005). A short and constructive proof of Tarski’s fixed-point theorem. International Journal of Game Theory, 33, 215–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L. G. (1997). Preference, rationalizability and equilibrium. Journal of Economic Theory, 73(1), 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luo, X. (2001). General systems and \(\varphi\)-stable sets — a formal analysis of socioeconomic environments. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 36(2), 95–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luo, X. (2016). Rational beliefs in rationalizability. Theory and Decision, 81, 189–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maeda, T. (2015). On characterization of Nash equilibrium strategy in bi-matrix games with set payoffs. In A. Hamel, F. Heyde, A. Löhne, B. Rudloff, & C. Schrage (Eds.), Set Optimization and Applications - The State of the Art (pp. 313–331). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Milgrom, P., & Roberts, J. (1990). Rationalizability, learning, and equilibrium in games with strategic complementarities. Econometrica, 58(6), 1255–1277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J. (1950). Equilibrium points in \(n\)-person games. Proceedings of the National academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 36(1), 48–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olszewski, W. (2021). On sequences of iterations of increasing and continuous mappings on complete lattices. Games and Economic Behavior, 126, 453–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne, M. J., & Rubinstein, A. (1994). A Course in Game Theory. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlag, K., & Zapechelnyuk, A. (2020). Compromise, don’t optimize: Generalizing perfect Bayesian equilibrium to games with ambiguity. Working Paper.

  • Sobel, J. (2019). Iterated weak dominance and interval-dominance supermodular games. Theoretical Economics, 14(1), 71–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jaeok Park.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

We benefited from conversations with Nadan Cho. We are grateful to the Coordinating Editor, two anonymous referees, Karl Schlag, and participants at the Econometric Society and Bocconi University World Congress 2020 for helpful comments and suggestions.

Appendix: Proofs

Appendix: Proofs

Proof of Proposition 1

Since \(R^*\) includes any rationalizable set, it suffices to show that \(R^*\) is a rationalizable set to prove that \(R^*\) is the largest rationalizable set. Since the empty set is a rationalizable set, we assume that \(R^*\) is nonempty. Choose any \(s \in R^*\). Since \(R^* = \cup _{R \in {\mathcal {R}}} R\), there exists \(R \in {\mathcal {R}}\) such that \(s \in R\). Then we have \(s_i \in {\bar{b}}_i( {\tilde{R}}_{-i}(s_i) )\) for any \(i \in N\). Since \(R \subseteq R^*\), we have \({\tilde{R}}_{-i}(s_i) \subseteq {\tilde{R}}_{-i}^*(s_i)\). Since \({\bar{b}}_i\) is nondecreasing, we have \(s_i \in {\bar{b}}_i( {\tilde{R}}_{-i}^*(s_i) )\) for any \(i \in N\). Hence, \(R^*\) is a rationalizable set.

Next, we show that \(R^*\) is in product form. Choose any \(s \in \times _{j \in N} {\tilde{R}}_{j}^*\) and any \(i \in N\). Then there exists \(s'_{-i} \in S_{-i}\) such that \((s_i, s'_{-i}) \in R^*\). Since \(R^*\) is a rationalizable set, we have \(s_i \in {\bar{b}}_i( {\tilde{R}}_{-i}^*(s_i) )\). Since \({\tilde{R}}_{-i}^*(s_i) \subseteq \times _{j \ne i} {\tilde{R}}_{j}^*\), we have \(s_i \in {\bar{b}}_i( \times _{j \ne i} {\tilde{R}}_{j}^* )\). Hence, \(\times _{j \in N} {\tilde{R}}_{j}^*\) is also a rationalizable set. Since \(R^* \subseteq \times _{j \in N} {\tilde{R}}_{j}^*\) and \(R^*\) is the largest rationalizable set, it must be that \(R^* = \times _{j \in N} {\tilde{R}}_{j}^*\).\(\square\)

Proof of Proposition 2

Since r is nondecreasing and \({\mathcal {P}}(S)\) is a complete lattice, there exists the largest fixed point of r, which is equal to the largest post fixed point, by Tarski’s fixed point theorem. By Proposition 1, \(R^*\) is the largest post fixed point of r. Since the game is finite, the set \({\mathcal {P}}(S)\) is finite. Note that S is the largest element of \({\mathcal {P}}(S)\). Then the largest fixed point of r can be obtained as \(r^k(S)\) for some finite k (see, for example, Echenique, 2005, Sect. 4). If \(B = \times _{j \in N} B_j\) is a product belief, we have \({\tilde{B}}_{-i}(s_i) = B_{-i}:= \times _{j \ne i} B_j\) for any \(s_i \in B_i\) and \({\tilde{B}}_{-i}(s_i) = \varnothing\) for any \(s_i \notin B_i\), for any \(i \in N\). Hence, we have \(r(B) = \times _{i \in N} {\bar{b}}_i (B_{-i})\) for any product belief \(B \in \times _{i \in N} {\mathcal {P}}(S_i)\). Suppose that \(r(B) \ne \varnothing\) for every \(B \in \times _{i \in N} {\mathcal {P}}_0(S_i)\). Then \(r^k(S)\) is a nonempty product belief for all \(k = 1,2,\ldots\), and thus \(R^*\) is nonempty. Suppose that \(b_i\) is nondecreasing on \(\times _{j \ne i} {\mathcal {P}}(S_j)\) for every \(i \in N\). Then \(r(B) = e(B)\) for all \(B \in \times _{i \in N} {\mathcal {P}}(S_i)\). It follows that \(R^*\) is given by \(e^k(S)\) for some finite k, and it is a (post) fixed point of e. Hence, \(R^*\) is a (strict) equilibrium. Since any equilibrium is contained in \(R^*\), it is the largest (strict) equilibrium. \(\square\)

Proof of Proposition 3

The results that there exists an IENBR procedure and that \(R^{\infty } = R^*\) for any IENBR procedure \(\{ R^{\lambda } \}_{\lambda \in \Lambda }\) can be proven as in the proof of Proposition 2 of Chen et al. (2016). The results that there exists an IESDS procedure and that all IESDS procedures yield the same \(D^{\infty }\) can be proven as in the proof of Theorem 1 of Chen et al. (2007). As shown in Proposition 1, \(R^*\) is a rationalizable set. Choose any \(i \in N\) and any \(s \in R^*\). Then \(s_i\) is not a never-best response given \(R^*\). This implies that \(s_i\) is not strictly dominated given \(R^*\), which in turn implies that \(s_i\) is not strictly dominated given any \(S' \subseteq S\) such that \(R^* \subseteq S'\). Hence, for any IESDS procedure \(\{ D^{\lambda } \}_{\lambda \in \Lambda }\), no \(s \in R^*\) is deleted in any round of the procedure, and thus \(R^* \subseteq D^{\infty }\) holds. \(\square\)

Proof of Proposition 4

Since \(R^{\infty }\) is nonempty and \(R^{\infty } \subseteq D^{\infty }\), \(D^{\infty }\) is nonempty as well. Moreover, both \(R^{\infty }\) and \(D^{\infty }\) are product beliefs.

(i) Let \(B^* \subseteq S\) be an equilibrium of G. Since the empty belief is an equilibrium of \(G |_{R^{\infty }}\), we assume that \(B^*\) is nonempty. Choose any \(s \in B^*\) and any \(i \in N\). Then we have \(s_i \in b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i))\). Since \(B^* \subseteq R^* = R^{\infty }\), we have \(s \in R^{\infty }\) and \({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i) \subseteq R^{\infty }_{-i}\). Since there is no \(s'_i \in S_i\) such that \(s'_i \succ _{i, {\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i)} s_i\), there is no \(s'_i \in R^{\infty }_i\) such that \(s'_i \succ _{i, {\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i)} s_i\). Hence, \(s_i\) is a best response to \({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i)\) in the reduced game \(G |_{R^{\infty }}\). This implies that \(B^*\) be an equilibrium of \(G |_{R^{\infty }}\).

(ii) For any player \(i \in N\), any belief \(B_{-i} \subseteq S_{-i}\) of his, and any nonempty subset \(S'_i \subseteq S_i\), let us define

$$\begin{aligned} b_i(B_{-i}; S'_i) = \{ s_i \in S'_i : \not \exists s'_i \in S'_i \text { s.t. } s'_i \succ _{i, B_{-i}} s_i \}. \end{aligned}$$

That is, \(b_i(B_{-i}; S'_i)\) is the set of best responses to player i’s belief \(B_{-i}\) when his strategy set is restricted to \(S'_i\). Note that \(b_i(B_{-i}) = b_i(B_{-i}; S_i)\) for any \(i \in N\) and any \(B_{-i} \subseteq S_{-i}\).

Let \(B^* \subseteq R^{\infty }\) be a nonempty equilibrium of \(G |_{R^{\infty }}\). Choose any \(s \in B^*\) and any \(i \in N\). Then we have \(s_i \in b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i); R^{\infty }_{i})\). To show that \(s_i \in b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i))\), suppose to the contrary that \(s_i \notin b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i))\). Since the game G has the well-defined best-response property on \(B^*\), there exists \(s'_i \in S_i\) such that \(s'_i \in b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i))\) and \(s'_i \succ _{i, {\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i)} s_i\). Since \({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i) \subseteq R^{\infty }_{-i}\), we have \(s'_i \in R^{\infty }_{i}\). Then it contradicts that \(s_i \in b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i); R^{\infty }_{i})\). Thus, \(B^*\) is an equilibrium of G.

Let \(B^* \subseteq R^{\infty }\) be a nonempty strict equilibrium of \(G |_{R^{\infty }}\). Using the well-defined best-response property of G on \(B^*\), we have already shown that \(B^*\) is an equilibrium of G. To show that \(B^*\) is a strict equilibrium of G, suppose to the contrary that there exists \(s \notin B^*\) such that \(s_i \in b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i))\) for all \(i \in N\). Since \(B^* \subseteq R^{\infty }\), we have \(s \in R^{\infty }\). Since \(B^*\) is a strict equilibrium of \(G |_{R^{\infty }}\) and \(s \in R^{\infty } {\setminus } B^*\), there exists \(i \in N\) such that \(s_i \notin b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i); R^{\infty }_{i})\). This implies that \(s_i \notin b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i))\), which is a contradiction. Hence, \(B^*\) is a strict equilibrium of G.

Let \(B^* \subseteq S\) be a nonempty strict equilibrium of G. We know that \(B^* \subseteq R^{\infty }\) and have already shown in (i) that \(B^*\) is an equilibrium of \(G |_{R^{\infty }}\). To show that \(B^*\) is a strict equilibrium of \(G |_{R^{\infty }}\), suppose to the contrary that there exists \(s \in R^{\infty } \setminus B^*\) such that \(s_i \in b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i); R^{\infty }_{i})\) for all \(i \in N\). Since \(B^*\) is a strict equilibrium of G and \(s \notin B^*\), there exists \(i \in N\) such that \(s_i \notin b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i))\). Using the well-defined best-response property of G on \(B^*\), we can derive a contradiction to \(s_i \in b_i({\tilde{B}}^*_{-i}(s_i); R^{\infty }_{i})\) as in the above argument. Thus, \(B^*\) is a strict equilibrium of \(G |_{R^{\infty }}\).

The results for \(G |_{D^{\infty }}\) can be proven analogously. \(\square\)

Proof of Proposition 5

Let \({\underline{\rho }}(s) = ({\underline{\rho }}_i(s_{-i}))_{i \in N}\) and \({\overline{\rho }}(s) = ({\overline{\rho }}_i(s_{-i}))_{i \in N}\) for all \(s \in S\). Let \({\underline{s}}^0 = \inf (S)\) and \({\overline{s}}^0 = \sup (S)\), and let \({\underline{s}}^k = {\underline{\rho }}({\underline{s}}^{k-1})\) and \({\overline{s}}^k = {\overline{\rho }}({\overline{s}}^{k-1})\) for all \(k = 1,2,\ldots\). Then \(\{ {\underline{s}}^k \}\) is nondecreasing and \(\{ {\overline{s}}^k \}\) is nonincreasing, and the sequences have order limits \({\underline{s}}^* = \inf {\underline{s}}^k\) and \({\overline{s}}^* = \sup {\underline{s}}^k\), which are the smallest and largest pure strategy Nash equilibria, respectively, of the supermodular game \(\langle N, (S_i), (u_i) \rangle\) (see Theorem 5 of Milgrom and Roberts, 1990). Note also that \({\underline{s}}^*\) and \({\overline{s}}^*\) are the unique fixed points of \({\underline{\rho }}\) and \({\overline{\rho }}\), respectively (see Sobel, 2019). We have \(r^k(S) = [{\underline{s}}^k, {\overline{s}}^k]\) for all \(k = 1,2,\ldots\), and thus \(r^{\omega }(S) = [{\underline{s}}^*, {\overline{s}}^*]\). Since \({\underline{s}}^*\) and \({\overline{s}}^*\) are the fixed points of \({\underline{\rho }}\) and \({\overline{\rho }}\), respectively, \(r^{\omega }(S)\) is a fixed point of r. Then by Proposition 3, we have \(R^* = r^{\omega }(S) = [{\underline{s}}^*, {\overline{s}}^*]\). \(\square\)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Park, J., Yun, D.H. Possibilistic beliefs in strategic games. Theory Decis 95, 205–228 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09919-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09919-3

Keywords

Navigation