Skip to main content
Log in

Thoughts matter: a theory of motivated preference

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper develops a model of individual decision-making under bounded rationality in which discretionary cognitive adjustment creates a durable stock that complements choice of action. While it increases utility, adjustment also entails a cost, because focusing attention optimally is effortful and mental resources are scarce. Associated behavioral phenomena are categorized based on whether the operative motivation in adjusting is forward-looking utility maximization or justification of prior action. The theory is in line with prior conceptions of cognitive dissonance, but also offers a more empirically consistent explanation of the endowment effect, persuasive advertising, and sunk-cost effects than existing accounts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The process described here is naturally distinct from consumer search, which has the objective of identifying the individual’s best choice. Adjustment, in contrast, typically involves mental re-positioning with respect to a choice one has already determined—or is, in parallel, determining—to be one’s best.

  2. A recent paper by Bernheim et al. (2021) proposes that individuals choose among “worldviews” that influence their judgments with respect to experiences; in so doing, they exercise direct control over their tastes. The approach envisions selection, in effect, among macro-level reference points rather cognitions with respect to individual objects.

  3. Recent evidence supports the notion that individuals change their attitudes to support their actions through a discretionary or quasi-discretionary process involving classic rationalization (Jarcho et al., 2011) and the expenditure of effort (Kitayama et al., 2013). The notion that the process is essentially a rational one is supported by evidence on the influence of mediating factors that conceivably relate to the costs and benefits of the decision, including the individual’s cultural background (Kitayama et al., 2004; Qin et al., 2011), whether the choice is perceived to be more self-relevant (Jarcho et al., 2011; Kitayama et al., 2013), and whether the matter is construed as relating to high ideals or trivial secondary features (Wakslak, 2012).

  4. Rabin (1994) and Oxoby (2003, 2004) posit agents who engage in dissonance reduction by making costly changes to their beliefs or preferences, hence utility parameters, with respect to the value of moral behavior and status consumption, respectively. Thus their agents trade off cognitive effort, or aversive distaste for holding “dishonest” beliefs, against material benefits accruing to preference change, allowing them to explain characteristic behaviors in these specific areas.

  5. In another “second item” study, Ericson and Fuster (2011) find that manipulated expectations of ownership of an item fail to influence valuation of a second owned item, whereby they conclude that increased valuations associated with increased expectations of ownership are attributable to loss aversion and not “motivated taste change.” But the authors acknowledge that their null result may have accrued to the short duration of ownership in their experiment (a few minutes). For more on the role of duration of ownership in valuation, see Strahilevitz and Loewenstein (1998).

  6. Nelson (1974) argues that costly non-substantive advertising may be interpreted as a signal: the seller demonstrates by advertising that the product is of sufficient quality to warrant a costly expenditure. However, if the purpose is just to show that money is being spent and the ad is not in some measure intended to be persuasive, why should message and image details matter?

  7. Akerlof and Dickens (1982) suggest that advertising may help consumers by furnishing them with an “external justification” for believing that a purchased product meets their needs (p. 317). This idea closely aligns with my notion. For a full analysis of the effects of advertising as self-persuasion in a competitive context, see Nagler (2020).

  8. A recent paper by Eyster et al. (2022) proposes that individuals choose actions and utility functions from a finite set of “rationales” to rationalize past actions. While not explicitly cognitive, their approach can explain the Akerlof and Dickens scenario.

  9. Consistent with this paradigm, Bénabou and Tirole (2004) and Kőszegi (2010) model agents who choose their actions based on their ability to enable instrumental or intrinsically desirable beliefs, whereby actions and beliefs are determined simultaneously in equilibrium. The intersection of desirability and feasibility of beliefs leads naturally to the modeling of cognition manipulation via self-signalling games, as in Bodner and Prelec (2003), Bernheim and Thomadsen (2005), and Dal Bó and Terviö (2013).

  10. For example, Brunnermeier and Parker (2005) posit that agents distort their beliefs about the probabilities of future events subject to feasibility constraints to optimally balance their anticipatory utility against the costs of worse decision making. Mobius et al. (2011) assume an agent who distorts the Bayesian inference process, subject to constraints that govern the reasonable conduct of that process, to optimally maintain desirable positive beliefs.

  11. The reduced-form adjustment cost is analogous to the reduced-form minimum cost function used in classic profit maximization analysis, which subsumes the input combination decisions needed to produce an output at minimum cost. A bounded rationality approach to preference change subsumes decisions over cognitions (and potentially behaviors) needed to produce adjustment at minimum cost. The mechanics of these are not essential to predicting dynamic consumption streams, and so need not be made explicit so long as they are convincingly independent of those streams except through their effect on adjustment.

  12. See, e.g., Yariv (2002).

  13. It could be argued that the habit formation models propose complementarity of current and future actions as a shorthand to represent any underlying cognitive processes that might play a role in such complementarity. But then, the primitives are insufficiently specified, because they fail to distinguish empirically relevant differences. Consider a hypothetical experiment in which two groups of human subjects are forced to take an action that some individuals find repugnant based on cultural factors. One group is selected, because they are influenced by these factors, while the other (control) group is selected based on not being influenced by the factors. Cognitive dissonance theory predicts that the experimental group would rationalize taking the repugnant action and so exhibit an increased propensity to repeat the action subsequently, while the control group would show no significant increased propensity to repeat. Thus the habit formation tendencies of the two groups differ with respect to the same action in a way that the traditional habit formation model cannot explain.

  14. See also the description of these effects by De Clippel and Eliaz (2012).

  15. More broadly, good x might be an activity that could be engaged in at varying levels of intensity.

  16. In the concluding section, I discuss the implications of admitting negative thinking (\(T_{t}<0\)) in the model.

  17. One could conceive of adjustment as depending not only on discretionary thinking—in turn, determined by deterministic factors—but also on stochastic environmental shocks, such as might be caused by unexpected new information about the good. Consistent with the approach in the related literature (e.g., Becker & Murphy, 1988), I abstract from uncertainty to focus on the effects that arise deterministically with respect to my object of study, the complementarity of action and cognition:

  18. Durability is a well-accepted characteristic of attitudes, and the mediators of attitude durability have long been an object of psychological research. See Wu and Shaffer (1987), Haugtvedt and Petty (1992), and Petty et al. (1995).

  19. Analogously, Kőszegi and Rabin (2006) relate the sensation of gain or loss associated with departure from a reference point to the consumption value of the associated good.

  20. The partial equilibrium setup embeds preference manipulation (via adjustment) in a context that trades it off against both consumption of the good in question and consumption utility from other goods, whereby the tradeoff extends only indirectly to adjustment to those other goods. In choosing this approach over general equilibrium, I deliberately abstract from the detailed consideration of tradeoffs across goods in the interest of focusing on applications related to the intertemporal development of the adjustment stock within a single good.

  21. Again to maintain focus on intertemporal development of the adjustment stock and consumption stream, I set aside as essentially orthogonal to these matters of primary interest the question of how a consumer might choose \(x_{0}\) prior to the revelation of \(\mu\) (where that is the process by which \(\bar{x}_{0}\) is determined).

  22. A naïve consumer experiencing any degree of regret over time will perceive her preferences to be dynamically inconsistent as she will believe her future self not to be affected by regret.

  23. This perspective is consistent with the advertising uses and gratifications literature. See O’Donohoe (1994), Ko et al. (2005), Aitken et al. (2008), and Phillips and McQuarrie (2010).

  24. The simple framework presented here abstracts from the competitive effects and price effects of adjustment-facilitating advertising. These are worthy of separate investigation. See the concluding section.

  25. See, for example, the discussion in the introduction of Sun (2011).

  26. The motivated preferences model assumes a consumer who rationally anticipates the effects of her adjustment. On this basis, a consumer accepting a trial membership should anticipate that she will perceive an increased benefit from long-term membership after the trial is done. However, evidence suggests that consumers may not rationally anticipate adjustment due to projection bias (Acland and Levy, 2015). See Sect. 4 for further discussion.

  27. More generally, s could be a vector of individual characteristics.

  28. Note that the variables used to measure \(y_{0}\) are distinguished from the characteristic s in that they are endogenous, while s must be convincingly exogenous.

  29. Consider that even a consumer who does no thinking at all about food still gets sustenance from it.

References

  • Acland, D., & Levy, M. R. (2015). Naiveté, projection bias, and habit formation in gym attendance. Management Science, 61(1), 146–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aitken, R., Gray, B., & Lawson, R. (2008). Advertising effectiveness from a consumer perspective. International Journal of Advertising, 27(2), 279–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Akerlof, G. A., & Dickens, W. T. (1982). The economic consequences of cognitive dissonance. American Economic Review, 72(3), 307–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ambuehl, S. (2017). An offer you can’t refuse? Incentives change how we inform ourselves and what we believe. CESifo Working Papers (6296).

  • Ariely, D., Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (2003). “Coherent arbitrariness’’: Stable demand curves without stable preferences. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 118, 73–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aronson, E. (2004). The social animal (9th ed.). Worth Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aylesworth, A. B., & MacKenzie, S. B. (1998). Context is key: The effect of program-induced mood on thoughts about the ad. Journal of Advertising, 27(2), 17–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baliga, S., & Ely, J. C. (2011). Mnemonomics: the sunk cost fallacy as a memory kludge. American Economic Journal: Microeconomics, 3(4), 35–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. S., & Murphy, K. M. (1988). A theory of rational addiction. Journal of Political Economy, 96(4), 675–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bénabou, R., & Tirole, J. (2004). Willpower and personal rules. Journal of Political Economy, 112(4), 848–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bénabou, R., & Tirole, J. (2011). Identity, morals, and taboos: Beliefs as assets. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 126(2), 805–855.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B. D., Braghieri, L., Martínez-Marquina, A., & Zuckerman, D. (2021). A theory of chosen preferences. American Economic Review, 111(2), 720–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim, B. D., & Thomadsen, R. (2005). Memory and anticipation. Economic Journal, 115(503), 271–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bodner, R., & Prelec, D. (2003). Self-signaling and diagnostic utility in everyday decision making. In I. Brocas & J. D. Carrillo (Eds.), The psychology of economic decisions (Vol. 1, pp. 105–26). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunnermeier, M. K., & Parker, J. A. (2005). Optimal expectations. American Economic Review, 95(4), 1092–1118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chatterjee, P., Irmak, C., & Rose, R. L. (2013). The endowment effect as self-enhancement in response to threat. Journal of Consumer Research, 40(3), 460–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cherepanov, V., Feddersen, T., & Sandroni, A. (2013). Rationalization. Theoretical Economics, 8(3), 775–800.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chih, W.-H., Liou, D.-K., & Hsu, L.-C. (2015). From positive and negative cognition perspectives to explore e-shoppers’ real purchase behavior: An application of tricomponent attitude model. Information Systems and e-Business Management, 13(3), 495–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dal Bó, E., & Terviö, M. (2013). Self-esteem, moral capital, and wrongdoing. Journal of the European Economic Association, 11(3), 599–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R., & Carlisle, T. R. (1976). Parental investment, mate desertion and a fallacy. Nature, 262, 131–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Clippel, G., & Eliaz, K. (2012). Reason-based choice: A bargaining rationale for the attraction and compromise effects. Theoretical Economics, 7(1), 125–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickens, W. T. (1986). Crime and punishment again: The economic approach with a psychological twist. Journal of Public Economics, 30(1), 97–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dolan, P., & Kahneman, D. (2008). Interpretations of utility and their implications for the valuation of health. Economic Journal, 118(525), 215–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dommer, S. L., & Swaminathan, V. (2013). Explaining the endowment effect through ownership: The role of identity, gender, and self-threat. Journal of Consumer Research, 39(5), 1034–1050.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epley, N., & Gilovich, T. (2016). The mechanics of motivated reasoning. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 30(3), 133–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ericson, K. M. M., & Fuster, A. (2011). Expectations as endowments: Evidence on reference-dependent preferences from exchange and valuation experiments. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 126(4), 1879–1907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eyster, E. (2002). Rationalizing the past: A taste for consistency. Nuffield College Mimeograph.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eyster, E., Li, S., & Ridout, S. (2022). A theory of ex post rationalization. arXiv preprint. arXiv:2107.07491.

  • Festinger, L. (1962). A theory of cognitive dissonance (Vol. 2). Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Festinger, L., & Carlsmith, J. M. (1959). Cognitive consequences of forced compliance. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 58(2), 203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, S. M. (1980). Consistent plans. Review of Economic Studies, 47(3), 533–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, P. E. (2005). Ab components impact on brand preference. Journal of Business Research, 58(4), 508–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugtvedt, C. P., & Petty, R. E. (1992). Personality and persuasion: Need for cognition moderates the persistence and resistance of attitude changes. Journal of Personality and Social psychology, 63(2), 308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hotelling, H. (1929). Stability in competition. Economic Journal, 39(153), 41–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, J., Payne, J. W., & Puto, C. (1982). Adding asymmetrically dominated alternatives: Violations of regularity and the similarity hypothesis. Journal of Consumer Research, 9(1), 90–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Izuma, K., Matsumoto, M., Murayama, K., Samejima, K., Sadato, N., & Matsumoto, K. (2010). Neural correlates of cognitive dissonance and choice-induced preference change. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107(51), 22014–22019.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jarcho, J. M., Berkman, E. T., & Lieberman, M. D. (2011). The neural basis of rationalization: Cognitive dissonance reduction during decision-making. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience, 6(4), 460–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., & Thaler, R. H. (1990). Experimental tests of the endowment effect and the Coase theorem. Journal of Political Economy, 98(6), 1325–1348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J. L., & Thaler, R. H. (1991). Anomalies: The endowment effect, loss aversion, and status quo bias. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 5(1), 193–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Sugden, R. (2005). Experienced utility as a standard of policy evaluation. Environmental and Resource Economics, 32(1), 161–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitayama, S., Chua, H. F., Tompson, S., & Han, S. (2013). Neural mechanisms of dissonance: An fMRI investigation of choice justification. NeuroImage, 69, 206–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitayama, S., Snibbe, A. C., Markus, H. R., & Suzuki, T. (2004). Is there any ‘free’ choice? Self and dissonance in two cultures. Psychological Science, 15(8), 527–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ko, H., Cho, C.-H., & Roberts, M. S. (2005). Internet uses and gratifications: A structural equation model of interactive advertising. Journal of Advertising, 34(2), 57–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kőszegi, B. (2010). Utility from anticipation and personal equilibrium. Economic Theory, 44(3), 415–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kőszegi, B., & Rabin, M. (2006). A model of reference-dependent preferences. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 121(4), 1133–1165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laibson, D. (1997). Golden eggs and hyperbolic discounting. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 112(2), 443–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, M. D., Ochsner, K. N., Gilbert, D. T., & Schacter, D. L. (2001). Do amnesics exhibit cognitive dissonance reduction? The role of explicit memory and attention in attitude change. Psychological Science, 12(2), 135–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, J. A. (2003). Does market experience eliminate market anomalies? Quarterly Journal of Economics, 118(1), 41–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, J. A. (2004). Neoclassical theory versus prospect theory: Evidence from the marketplace. Econometrica, 72(2), 615–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lleras, J. S., Masatlioglu, Y., Nakajima, D., & Ozbay, E. Y. (2017). When more is less: Limited consideration. Journal of Economic Theory, 170, 70–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., & Mariotti, M. (2007). Sequentially rationalizable choice. American Economic Review, 97(5), 1824–1839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manzini, P., & Mariotti, M. (2012). Categorize then choose: Boundedly rational choice and welfare. Journal of the European Economic Association, 10(5), 1141–1165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenzie, C. R., Liersch, M. J., & Finkelstein, S. R. (2006). Recommendations implicit in policy defaults. Psychological Science, 17(5), 414–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meloy, M. G. (2000). Mood-driven distortion of product information. Journal of Consumer Research, 27(3), 345–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mittelstaedt, R. (1969). A dissonance approach to repeat purchasing behavior. Journal of Marketing Research, 6(4), 444–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mobius, M. M., Niederle, M., Niehaus, P., & Rosenblat, T. S. (2011). Managing self-confidence: Theory and experimental evidence. Working Paper 17014, National Bureau of Economic Research.

  • Morewedge, C. K., Shu, L. L., Gilbert, D. T., & Wilson, T. D. (2009). Bad riddance or good rubbish? Ownership and not loss aversion causes the endowment effect. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 45(4), 947–951.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagler, M. G. (2020). Assisted self-persuasion: A motivated preference theory of advertising. City College of New York working paper.

  • Nagler, M. G. (2021). Loving what you get: The price effects of consumer self-persuasion. Review of Industrial Organization, 59(3), 529–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, P. (1974). Advertising as information. Journal of Political Economy, 82(4), 729–754.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donohoe, S. (1994). Advertising uses and gratifications. European Journal of Marketing, 28(8/9), 52–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oxoby, R. J. (2003). Attitudes and allocations: Status, cognitive dissonance, and the manipulation of attitudes. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 52(3), 365–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oxoby, R. J. (2004). Cognitive dissonance, status and growth of the underclass. Economic Journal, 114(498), 727–749.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg, B., & Yaari, M. E. (1973). On the existence of a consistent course of action when tastes are changing. Review of Economic Studies, 40(3), 391–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petty, R. E., Haugtvedt, C. P., & Smith, S. M. (1995). Elaboration as a determinant of attitude strength: Creating attitudes that are persistent, resistant, and predictive of behavior. In R. E. Petty & J. A. Krosnick (Eds.), Attitude strength: Antecedents and consequences (pp. 93–130). Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, B. J., & McQuarrie, E. F. (2010). Narrative and persuasion in fashion advertising. Journal of Consumer Research, 37(3), 368–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollak, R. A. (1968). Consistent planning. Review of Economic Studies, 35(2), 201–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Qin, J., Kimel, S., Kitayama, S., Wang, X., Yang, X., & Han, S. (2011). How choice modifies preference: Neural correlates of choice justification. NeuroImage, 55(1), 240–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (1994). Cognitive dissonance and social change. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 23, 177–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rabin, M. (1998). Psychology and economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 36(1), 11–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rozen, K. (2010). Foundations of intrinsic habit formation. Econometrica, 78(4), 1341–1373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharot, T., De Martino, B., & Dolan, R. J. (2009). How choice reveals and shapes expected hedonic outcome. Journal of Neuroscience, 29(12), 3760–3765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharot, T., Velasquez, C. M., & Dolan, R. J. (2010). Do decisions shape preference? Evidence from blind choice. Psychological Science, 21(9), 1231–1235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simonson, I. (1989). Choice based on reasons: The case of attraction and compromise effects. Journal of Consumer Research, 16(2), 158–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spiegler, R. (2002). Equilibrium in justifiable strategies: A model of reason-based choice in extensive-form games. Review of Economic Studies, 69(3), 691–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staw, B. M. (1976). Knee-deep in the big muddy: A study of escalating commitment to a chosen course of action. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 16(1), 27–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strahilevitz, M. A., & Loewenstein, G. (1998). The effect of ownership history on the valuation of objects. Journal of Consumer Research, 25(3), 276–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strotz, R. H. (1955). Myopia and inconsistency in dynamic utility maximization. Review of Economic Studies, 23(3), 165–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sun, M. (2011). Disclosing multiple product attributes. Journal of Economics and Management Strategy, 20(1), 195–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Svirsky, D. (2014). Money is no object: Testing the endowment effect in exchange goods. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 106, 227–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thaler, R. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1(1), 39–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tompson, S., Chua, H. F., & Kitayama, S. (2016). Connectivity between mPFC and PCC predicts post-choice attitude change: The self-referential processing hypothesis of choice justification. Human Brain Mapping, 37(11), 3810–3820.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Veen, V., Krug, M. K., Schooler, J. W., & Carter, C. S. (2009). Neural activity predicts attitude change in cognitive dissonance. Nature Neuroscience, 12(11), 1469–1474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakslak, C. J. (2012). The experience of cognitive dissonance in important and trivial domains: A construal-level theory approach. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 48(6), 1361–1364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wathieu, L. (2004). Consumer habituation. Management Science, 50(5), 587–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, C., & Shaffer, D. R. (1987). Susceptibility to persuasive appeals as a function of source credibility and prior experience with the attitude object. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52(4), 677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yariv, L. (2002). I’ll see it when i believe it? A simple model of cognitive consistency. Discussion Paper No. 1352, Cowles Foundation, Yale University.

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author is grateful to Heski Bar-Isaac, Roland Bénabou, Uwe Dulleck, Simon Grant, Hanna Halaburda, Sander Heinsalu, Jin Hyuk-Kim, Botond Kőszegi, Shengwu Li, Michael I. Norton, Ariel Rubinstein, Daniel Stone, Adam Szeidl, and seminar participants at the Australian National University, Hunter College, the Melbourne Institute, Monash University, QUT Business School, and the University of New South Wales for helpful comments. Kelly Page Nelson provided excellent research assistance.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew G. Nagler.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Theorem 1

The optimization problem is the same every period, so fix \(t=\tau\) and consider the problem for self \(\tau\) of solving (3). This player recognizes that his move \(\left( x_{\tau },T_{\tau }\right)\) will influence the subsequent moves of future selves. Specifically, his choice of \(T_{\tau }\) will influence future decisions, because it affects the future stock of adjustment which in turn influences the preferences of future selves; his choice of \(x_{\tau }\) has no bearing on future selves’ preferences or decisions. A subgame perfect strategy takes account of how the choice of \(T_{\tau }\) affects responses in all \(t>\tau\) by treating \(T_{t}\) as a function \(T_{t}\left( T_{\tau }\right)\) for all \(t>\tau\) when choosing the optimal \(T_{\tau }\).

Observe from (2) that self \(\tau\)’s objective function nests the objective function of each \(t>\tau\). One may rewrite (2) accordingly as

$$\begin{aligned} U_{\tau }\equiv \mu u\left( x_{\tau },T_{\tau }\right) +K-x_{\tau }-T_{\tau }+\delta U_{\tau +1} \end{aligned}$$
(6)

whence the nesting of future selves’ objectives for \(t>\tau +1\) follows by induction. Observe also that \(T_{t}\) for \(t>\tau\) appears in self \(\tau\)’s objective function only within \(U_{t}\). It follows that one may write

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial U_{\tau }}{\partial T_{\tau }}=\left. \frac{\partial U_{\tau }}{\partial T_{\tau }}\right| _{D}+\sum _{t=1}^{\infty }\frac{\partial U_{\tau }}{\partial U_{\tau +t}}\frac{\partial U_{\tau +t}}{\partial T_{\tau +t}}\frac{\partial T_{\tau +t}}{\partial T_{\tau }} \end{aligned}$$
(7)

where the “D” indicates the direct effect, not through the choice of T by another self.

For an interior solution \(\frac{\partial U_{\tau +t}}{\partial T_{\tau +t}}=0\) for all \(t\ge 1\) in (7). Thus by the envelope theorem \(\frac{\partial U_{\tau }}{\partial T_{\tau }}=\left. \frac{\partial U_{\tau }}{\partial T_{\tau }}\right| _{D}\), that is, the overall effect of \(T_{\tau }\) on utility is equal to the direct effect, ignoring effects of \(T_{\tau }\) through the \(T_{\tau +t}\) that are already being optimized by future selves.

With this in mind, the first-order conditions of (3) may be written

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{x}=1; \mu u_{y}=1. \end{aligned}$$
(8)

As the problem is the same in every period, the first-order conditions yield the same \(\left( x^{*}\left( \mu \right),y^{*}\left( \mu \right) \right)\) interior solution in all periods \(t\ge 0\). (An interior solution is assured by the assumption of \(\mu\) large enough that \(\mu u_{x}\left( 0,0\right) >1\) and \(\mu u_{y}\left( 0,0\right) >1\).) It follows that \(T_{0}=y^{*}\left( \mu \right)\) and \(T_{t}=\sigma y^{*}\left( \mu \right)\) for all \(t>0\). Note that the constant marginal cost of adjustment implies the consumer engages in adjustment in each period t until the level \(y^{*}\left( \mu \right)\) is reached, regardless of \(y_{t-1}\). It is, moreover, easy to see from the first-order conditions that \(x_{\mu }^{*},y_{\mu }^{*}>0\).

One now must show that this interior solution is the unique maximum. The derivatives of (6) needed to evaluate the Hessian with respect to this objective, reflecting the relevant values of \(\left( x,y\right)\) at which they are evaluated, are

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{\partial U_{\tau }}{\partial x_{\tau }}=\mu u_{x}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) -1 ;\quad \frac{\partial ^{2}U_{\tau }}{\partial x_{\tau }^{2}}=\mu u_{xx}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) \\ &\frac{\partial ^{2}U_{\tau }}{\partial x_{\tau }\partial T_{\tau }}=\mu u_{xy}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) ;\quad \frac{\partial U_{\tau }}{\partial T_{\tau }}=\mu u_{y}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) +\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) \mu u_{y}\left( x_{\tau +1},y_{\tau +1}\right) +\cdots -1 \\ &\frac{\partial ^{2}U_{\tau }}{\partial T_{\tau }^{2}} = \mu u_{yy}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) +\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{\tau +1},y_{\tau +1}\right) +\cdots \end{aligned}$$
(9)

To simplify notation, I drop the arguments for \(t=\tau\) and show only arguments for \(t>\tau\). The Hessian is

$$\begin{aligned} \left| H\right|= & {} \mu ^{2}\left| \begin{array}{cc} u_{xx} &{} u_{xy}\\ u_{xy} &{} u_{yy}+\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}u_{yy}\left( x_{\tau +1},y_{\tau +1}\right) +\cdots \end{array}\right| \\= & {} u_{xx}u_{yy}-u_{xy}^{2}+u_{xx}\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}u_{yy}\left( x_{\tau +1},y_{\tau +1}\right) +\cdots>u_{xx}u_{yy}-u_{xy}^{2}>0 \end{aligned}$$
(10)

which follows from the strict concavity of \(u\left( .\right)\). Since \(\frac{\partial ^{2}U}{\partial x_{\tau }^{2}}<0\) and \(\frac{\partial ^{2}U}{\partial T_{\tau }^{2}}<0\), \(U_{\tau }\left( x_{\tau },T_{\tau }\right)\) is strictly concave. This establishes the solution \(\left( x_{\tau }^{*},y_{\tau }^{*}\right)\) to the first-order conditions as the unique interior absolute maximum for \(\tau\). By induction, this is true for all \(\tau \ge 0\).

To dispense with the possibility of a corner solution: it was noted previously that the unique interior solution is \(\left( x_{t}^{*},y_{t}^{*}\right) =\left( x^{*}\left( \mu \right),y^{*}\left( \mu \right) \right)\) for all \(t\ge 0\), thus \(T_{t}^{*}=\sigma y^{*}\left( \mu \right)\) for all \(t>0\). A corner solution of \(T_{1}=0\) could result if and only if \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) y_{0}^{*}\left( \mu \right) >y^{*}\left( \mu \right)\). But this would imply \(y_{0}^{*}\left( \mu \right) >y^{*}\left( \mu \right)\), which is a contradiction of the unique interior solution for \(t=0\). Thus no corner solution will result in \(t=1\). By similar argument, a corner solution in any \(t=\tau\) requires \(y_{\tau -1}^{*}\left( \mu \right) >y^{*}\left( \mu \right)\), a contradiction of the interior solution for the prior period. By induction, the interior solution is the only solution for all periods.

This confirms \(\left( x_{0},T_{0}\right) =\left( x^{*}\left( \mu \right),y^{*}\left( \mu \right) \right)\) and \(\left( x_{t},T_{t}\right) =\left( x^{*}\left( \mu \right),\sigma y^{*}\left( \mu \right) \right)\) for all \(t>0\) constitutes the unique subgame perfect equilibrium strategy for the infinite game.

Proof of Corollary 1

Without varying the setup for Theorem 1 substantively, one may treat self 0 as two selves, one (\(0_{x}\)) who sets \(x_{0}\) and another (\(0_{T}\)) who subsequently sets \(T_{0}\), both with \(\mu\) known. Both receive the same payoff, given by (2) for \(\tau =0\), subsequent to \(0_{T}\)’s move. It is obvious that the theorem holds for this trivial variation. Relative to this, an endowment constitutes an out-of-equilibrium deviation for self \(0_{x}\). The subgame that follows this deviation has a unique subgame perfect equilibrium strategy, per Theorem 1, by definition of a subgame perfect equilibrium.

Proof of Lemma 1

The derivatives of (4) needed to evaluate the Hessian with respect to this objective are

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{\partial U^{R}}{\partial x_{\tau }}=\left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) \left( \mu u_{x}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) -1\right) ;\quad \frac{\partial ^{2}U^{R}}{\partial x_{\tau }^{2}}=\left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) \mu u_{xx}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) \\ &\frac{\partial ^{2}U^{R}}{\partial x_{\tau }\partial T_{\tau }}=\left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) \mu u_{xy}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) \\ &\frac{\partial U^{R}}{\partial T_{\tau }}=\left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) \left( \mu u_{y}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) -1+\delta \left\{ \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{\tau +1}^{\prime }\left( T_{\tau }\right) \right] \mu u_{y}\left( x_{\tau +1},y_{\tau +1}\right) -T_{\tau +1}^{\prime }\left( T_{\tau }\right) \right\} \right. \\ &\quad \left. +\delta ^{2}\left\{ \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}+\left( 1-\sigma \right) T_{\tau +1}^{\prime }\left( T_{\tau }\right) +T_{\tau +2}^{\prime }\left( T_{\tau }\right) \right] \mu u_{y}\left( x_{\tau +2},y_{\tau +2}\right) -T_{\tau +2}^{\prime }\left( T_{\tau }\right) \right\} +\cdots \right) \\ &\quad +\beta _{\tau }\left( \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{\tau }\right) -\mu u_{y}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{\tau }\right),y_{\tau }\right) \right) \\ &\frac{\partial ^{2}U^{R}}{\partial T_{\tau }^{2}}=\left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) \left( \mu u_{yy}\left( x_{\tau },y_{\tau }\right) +\delta \left\{ \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{\tau +1}^{\prime }\right] ^{2}\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{\tau +1},y_{\tau +1}\right) \right\} \right. \\ &\quad \left. +\delta ^{2}\left\{ \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}+\left( 1-\sigma \right) T_{\tau +1}^{\prime }+T_{\tau +2}^{\prime }\right] ^{2}\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{\tau +2},y_{\tau +2}\right) \right\} +\cdots \right) \\ &\quad +\beta _{\tau }\left[ \mu u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{\tau }\right) -\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{\tau }\right),y_{\tau }\right) -\mu u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{\tau }\right),y_{\tau }\right) x_{T}^{*}\right] \end{aligned}$$
(11)

where \(x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right)\) arises implicitly as the solution to \(\mu u_{x}\left( x_{0}^{*},y_{0}\right) =1\). (Thus terms \(\mu u_{x}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) x_{T}^{*}-x_{T}^{*}\) drop out of the parentheses on the bottom line of \(\frac{\partial U^{R}}{\partial T_{\tau }}\).)

Suppose first that \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) y_{\tau -1}<y_{\tau }^{*}\), such that the solution arising from the first-order condition is an interior solution and candidate unique solution. Note, in this case, that all the \(T_{t}^{\prime }\) terms in (11) are constants that either take a value of zero or \(-\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{t-\tau }\). The value taken by each of these terms follows from the form of the state equation (1) and depends specifically on the size of the base value of \(T_{\tau }\), which determines in turn whether each \(T_{t}\) is a corner or interior solution. Suppose first that \(T_{\tau }\) is relatively small; then the depreciated value of adjustment \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) y_{\tau }\) will be less than the optimizing value of \(y_{\tau +1}\), whereby there will be an interior solution for \(T_{\tau +1}\) such that \(T_{\tau +1}^{\prime }\left( T_{\tau }\right) =-\left( 1-\sigma \right)\). It follows that \(T_{\tau +t}^{\prime }\left( T_{\tau }\right) =0\) for all \(t>1\). If, however, \(T_{\tau }\) is a bit larger but not too large, \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) y_{\tau }\) will be large enough to push \(T_{\tau +1}\) to a corner solution at zero; \(T_{\tau }\) would then be large enough that changes in its value would influence the choice of T in the following period, \(\tau +2\), whence \(T_{\tau +2}^{\prime }\left( T_{\tau }\right) =-\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}\) and \(T_{\tau +t}^{\prime }\left( T_{\tau }\right) =0\) for all \(t>2\) . And so on. It can be shown, therefore, that each squared expression in square brackets in \(\frac{\partial ^{2}U^{R}}{\partial T_{\tau }^{2}}\) is non-negative; more precisely, they take the value \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2t}\) up to a threshold t and zero thereafter. Overall, the sum of the curly bracketed terms within the non-regret component of \(\frac{\partial ^{2}U^{R}}{\partial T_{\tau }^{2}}\) (i.e., the portion that is weighted by \(1-\beta _{\tau }\)), which I shall refer to as “NR” for convenience, is unambiguously negative. The regret component (weighted by \(\beta _{\tau }\)), which I shall refer to as “R”, is ambiguously signed.

Dropping the arguments for \(t=\tau\) to simplify notation, the Hessian may be written

$$\begin{aligned} \left| H\right|&=\mu ^{2}\left| \begin{array}{cc} \left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) u_{xx} &{} \left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) u_{xy}\\ \left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) u_{xy} &{} \left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) \left( u_{yy}+NR\right) +\beta _{\tau }R \end{array}\right| \\&= \mu ^{2}\left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) ^{2}\left[ u_{xx}u_{yy}-u_{xy}^{2}+u_{xx}NR\right] +\mu ^{2}\left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) \beta _{\tau }u_{xx}R. \end{aligned}$$

This takes the sign of

$$\begin{aligned}&\left( 1-\beta _{\tau }\right) \left( u_{xx}u_{yy}-u_{xy}^{2}+u_{xx}NR\right) +\beta _{\tau }u_{xx}R. \end{aligned}$$
(12)

Given the strict concavity of \(u\left( .\right)\), \(u_{xx}u_{yy}-u_{xy}^{2}>0\), whereby it follows that the first term in (12) is positive. It is, therefore, sufficient for signing the entire expression positive, given \(\beta _{\tau }\) sufficiently small, that R be bounded above.

Proof of Proposition 1

Begin by writing the version of (4) for \(\tau =0\):

$$\begin{aligned}&\max _{T_{0}\left| \bar{x}_{0}\right. }U^{R}\left( \bar{x}_{0},T_{0}\right) =\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) \left\{ \mu u\left( \bar{x}_{0},T_{0}\right) +K-\bar{x}_{0}-T_{0}+\sum _{t=1}^{\infty }\delta ^{t}\left[ \mu u\left( x_{t},T_{t}\right) +K-x_{t}-T_{t}\right] \right\} \\ &\quad +\beta _{0}\left\{ \left[ \mu u\left( \bar{x}_{0},T_{0}\right) +K-\bar{x}_{0}-T_{0}\right] -\left[ \mu u\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),T_{0}\right) +K-x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right) -T_{0}\right] \right\} . \end{aligned}$$
(13)

Take the first-order condition with respect to \(T_{0}\), using (9):

$$\begin{aligned}&\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) \left( \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) -1+\delta \left\{ \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] \mu u_{y}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) -T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right\} \right. \\ &\quad \left. +\delta ^{2}\left\{ \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}+\left( 1-\sigma \right) T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) +T_{2}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] \mu u_{y}\left( x_{2},y_{2}\right) -T_{2}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right\} +\cdots \right) \\ &\quad +\beta _{0}\left\{ \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) -\mu u_{y}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) \right\} =0 \end{aligned}$$
(14)

where as mentioned in the proof of Lemma 1, \(x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right)\) arises implicitly as the solution to \(\mu u_{x}\left( x_{0}^{*},y_{0}\right) =1\). (Thus terms \(\mu u_{x}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) x_{T}^{*}-x_{T}^{*}\) drop out of the last line.) Recall also from the proof of the lemma that all terms \(T_{\tau }^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right)\) are constants. Totally differentiating (14) and using \(D_{1}\), \(D_{2}\), \(N_{11}\), \(N_{12}\), and \(N_{2}\) to represent respective curly bracketed terms yields

$$\begin{aligned}&\left[ \left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) \left\{ \mu u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) +\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] ^{2}\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) +\cdots \right\} \right. \\ &\qquad \left. \left. +\beta _{0}\left\{ \mu u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) \right. -\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) -\mu u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) x_{T}^{*}\right\} \right] dT_{0} \\ &\quad =-\left[ \left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) \left\{ u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) +\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] u_{y}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) +\cdots \right\} \right. \\ &\qquad \left. +\beta _{0}\left\{ u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) -u_{y}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) \right\} \right] d\mu -\left[ \left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) \left\{ \mu u_{xy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) \right\} +\beta _{0}\left\{ \mu u_{xy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) \right\} \right] dx_{0} \\ &\quad \Longleftrightarrow \left[ \left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}+\beta _{0}D_{2}\right] dT_{0}=\left[ -\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) N_{11}-\beta _{0}N_{12}\right] d\mu -N_{2}dx_{0}. \end{aligned}$$
(15)

This yields, using Cramer’s rule, for \(\beta _{0}=0\):

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial T_{0}}{\partial \mu }= & {} -\frac{N_{11}}{D_{1}}=-\frac{u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) +\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] u_{y}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) +\cdots }{\mu u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) +\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] ^{2}\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) +\cdots }>0. \end{aligned}$$
(16)

For \(\beta _{0}\approx 1\)—the case of extreme regret in the initial period—\(y_{0}^{*}\) is set for given \(\bar{x}_{0}\) by implicit solution to \(\mu u_{x}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}^{*}\right) =1\) as the “justifying” value of \(y_{0}\). One performs comparative static analysis for this case by totally differentiating \(\mu u_{x}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}^{*}\right) =1\):

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{xy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}^{*}\right) dT_{0}=-u_{x}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}^{*}\right) d\mu -u_{xx}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}^{*}\right) d\bar{x}_{0}. \end{aligned}$$
(17)

This yields

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial T_{0}}{\partial \mu }=-\frac{u_{x}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}^{*}\right) }{\mu u_{xy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}^{*}\right) }<0. \end{aligned}$$

To understand what happens as \(\beta _{0}\) varies between 0 and 1, one applies Cramer’s rule to (15) for general \(\beta _{0}\) and then differentiates with respect to \(\beta _{0}\):

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial T_{0}}{\partial \mu }= & {} -\frac{\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) N_{11}+\beta _{0}N_{12}}{\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}+\beta _{0}D_{2}} \\ \rightarrow \frac{\partial ^{2}T_{0}}{\partial \mu \partial \beta _{0}}= & {} -\tfrac{\left[ \left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}+\beta _{0}D_{2}\right] \left( N_{12}-N_{11}\right) -\left[ \left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) N_{11}+ \beta _{0}N_{12}\right] \left( D_{2}-D_{1}\right) }{\left[ \left( 1- \beta _{0}\right) D_{1}+\beta _{0}D_{2}\right] ^{2}}. \end{aligned}$$
(18)

Recognizing that (18) takes the sign of the numerator, let us evaluate the numerator. This can be simplified as follows, prior to substitutions:

$$\begin{aligned}&-\left[ \left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}+\beta _{0}D_{2}\right] \left( N_{12}-N_{11}\right) +\left[ \left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) N_{11}+\beta _{0}N_{12}\right] \left( D_{2}-D_{1}\right) \\ &\quad =-\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}N_{12}+\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}N_{11}-\beta _{0}D_{2}N_{12}+\beta _{0}D_{2}N_{11}\\ &\qquad -\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}N_{11}+\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{2}N_{11}-\beta _{0}D_{1}N_{12}+\beta _{0}D_{2}N_{12}\\ &\quad =-\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}N_{12}+\beta _{0}D_{2}N_{11}+\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{2}N_{11}-\beta _{0}D_{1}N_{12}\\ &\quad =-D_{1}N_{12}+D_{2}N_{11}. \end{aligned}$$

Substitution back yields

$$\begin{aligned}&-\left\{ \mu u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) +\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] ^{2}\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) +\cdots \right\} \left\{ u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) -u_{y}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) \right\} \\ &\quad +\left\{ \mu u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) -\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) -\mu u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) x_{T}^{*}\right\} \\ &\quad \times \left\{ u_{z}z_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) +\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] u_{z}z_{y}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) +\cdots \right\} . \end{aligned}$$

Now evaluate this expression at \(\mu =\bar{\mu }\), the value of \(\mu\) at which the endowment \(\bar{x}_{0}\) would have resulted if \(\left( \bar{x}_{0},T_{0}\right)\) were chosen simultaneously with \(\mu\) known, that is, the value of \(\mu\) for which \(x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right) =\bar{x}_{0}\). This is the appropriate value at which to evaluate \(\nicefrac {\partial ^{2}T_{0}}{\partial \mu \partial \beta _{0}}\), as the expression is then interpreted as showing how regret influences the individual’s response to a quality surprise relative to endowment-based expectations. At this value, the second term in curly brackets is zero. This leaves

$$\begin{aligned} \mu \left\{ u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) -u_{yy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) -u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) x_{T}^{*}\right\} \left\{ u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) +\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] u_{y}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) +\cdots \right\} \end{aligned}$$

The first and second terms cancel at \(x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right) =\bar{x}_{0}\), leaving

$$\begin{aligned} -\mu u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) x_{T}^{*}\cdot \left\{ u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) +\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] u_{y}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) +\cdots \right\} \end{aligned}$$
(19)

An expression for \(x_{T}^{*}\) comes from totally differentiating \(\mu u_{x}\left( x_{0}^{*},y_{0}\right) =1\):

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{xx}\left( x_{0}^{*},y_{0}\right) dx_{0}= & {} -\mu u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*},y_{0}\right) dT_{0} \\ \rightarrow x_{T}^{*}= & {} -\frac{u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*},y_{0}\right) }{u_{xx}\left( x_{0}^{*},y_{0}\right) }>0. \end{aligned}$$
(20)

Thus, one can sign (19) as negative. It follows that \(\nicefrac {\partial ^{2}T_{0}}{\partial \mu \partial \beta _{0}}<0\).

Proof of Proposition 2

Applying Cramer’s rule to (15) yields, for \(\beta _{0}=0\):

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial T_{0}}{\partial \bar{x}_{0}}= & {} -\frac{N_{2}}{D_{1}}=-\frac{\mu u_{xy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) }{\mu u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) +\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] ^{2}\cdot \mu u_{yy}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) +\cdots }>0. \end{aligned}$$

For \(\beta _{0}\approx 1\), one may apply Cramer’s rule to (17), yielding

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial T_{0}}{\partial \bar{x}_{0}}= & {} -\frac{u_{xx}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}^{*}\right) }{\mu u_{xy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}^{*}\right) }>0. \end{aligned}$$

To understand what happens as \(\beta _{0}\) varies between 0 and 1, apply Cramer’s rule to (15) for general \(\beta _{0}\) and then differentiate with respect to \(\beta _{0}\):

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial T_{0}}{\partial x_{0}}=-\frac{N_{2}}{\left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}+\beta _{0}D_{2}}\rightarrow \frac{\partial ^{2}T_{0}}{\partial x_{0}\partial \beta _{0}}=\tfrac{N_{2}\left( D_{2}-D_{1}\right) }{\left[ \left( 1-\beta _{0}\right) D_{1}+\beta _{0}D_{2}\right] ^{2}}. \end{aligned}$$
(21)

The sign of (21) takes on the sign of the numerator. Substitution back yields

$$\begin{aligned}&\left\{ \mu u_{xy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) \right\} \cdot \left\{ \mu u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) -\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) -\mu u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) x_{T}^{*}\right. \\ &\quad \left. -\mu u_{yy}\left( \bar{x}_{0},y_{0}\right) -\delta \left[ \left( 1-\sigma \right) +T_{1}^{\prime }\left( T_{0}\right) \right] ^{2}\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right) -\cdots \right\} . \end{aligned}$$

The first bracketed term is clearly positive. The first and fourth terms in the second bracketed expression cancel. Evaluate the second and third, substituting (20):

$$\begin{aligned}&-\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) - \mu u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) \left[ -\frac{u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) }{u_{xx}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) }\right] \\ &\quad =-\mu u_{yy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) + \mu \frac{\left[ u_{xy}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) \right] ^{2}}{u_{xx}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right) }. \end{aligned}$$

Multiply through by \(-u_{xx}\left( x_{0}^{*}\left( T_{0}\right),y_{0}\right)\) and the sign is the same. Removing the arguments to save space:

$$\begin{aligned} -\mu u_{xy}^{2}+\mu u_{xx}u_{yy}=\mu \left( u_{xx}u_{yy}-u_{xy}^{2}\right) >0. \end{aligned}$$

Thus \(\nicefrac {\partial ^{2}T_{0}}{\partial \bar{x}_{0}\partial \beta _{0}}>0\).

Proof of Proposition 3

Let \(\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right)\) represent the steady-state optimum under the unique subgame perfect equilibrium with no endowment, and let \(y_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0}\right) =T_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0}\right)\) represent the level of \(y_{0}\) arising from the no-regret first-order condition for T based on \(\bar{x}_{0}\). Observe that \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) y_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{01}\right) =y^{*}\) defines implicitly the threshold level \(\bar{x}_{01}\) of the endowment that leads to a corner solution for adjustive thinking in \(t=1\). That is, it is the minimum level that induces the consumer to set \(T_{1}=0\): for lower levels of \(x_{0}\), \(y_{1}<y^{*}\) unless \(T_{1}>0\). At the threshold itself, the unique interior solution that obtains for \(t>0\) remains unaffected, thus \(\left( x_{t},y_{t}\right) =\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right)\) for \(t\ge 1\) even when \(\left( x_{0},y_{0}\right) =\left( \bar{x}_{01},\frac{y^{*}}{1-\sigma }\right)\). Because \(y_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{01}\right)\) itself is defined based on the first-order condition for T, use that condition to write

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{01},\frac{y^{*}}{1-\sigma }\right) +\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) \mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) +\cdots= & {} 1 \end{aligned}$$
(22)

(Note that here, because endowments may create corner solutions in the optimization problem of future selves, the full first-order condition for T must be used, rather than the simplified version used in the proof of Theorem 1 based on application of the envelope theorem.) Using the fact that the optimum still obtains at the threshold, one may write

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{01},\frac{y^{*}}{1-\sigma }\right)= & {} \mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(23)

Now consider that \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}y_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{02}\right) =y^{*}\) defines implicitly the threshold level \(\bar{x}_{02}\) of the endowment that leads to a corner solution for adjustive thinking in \(t=2\). Analogous to the above, one needs the first-order condition for T to obtain a precise expression for \(\bar{x}_{02}\); however, in that expression it will be necessary to replace \(\left( x_{1},y_{1}\right)\) with threshold values in place of the optimal values appearing in (23). Given the depreciation rate of adjustment, \(y_{1}=\frac{y^{*}}{1-\sigma }\). Therefore, because the process is the same every period, there is an expression identical to (23) that defines a hypothetical \(t=1\) threshold level of consumption \(\bar{x}_{12}\) for adjusting thinking in \(t=2\), whereby \(\bar{x}_{12}=\bar{x}_{01}\). Using the first-order condition with respect to T then

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{02},\frac{y^{*}}{\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}}\right) +\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{01},\frac{y^{*}}{1-\sigma }\right) +\cdots= & {} 1 \end{aligned}$$

whereby substituting (23) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{02},\frac{y^{*}}{\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}}\right) +\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) \mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) +\cdots= & {} 1 \end{aligned}$$

whence, again using the fact that the optimum still obtains at the threshold, one may write

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{02},\frac{y^{*}}{\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}}\right)= & {} \mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

By induction, the level of the endowment that corresponds to the threshold of a corner solution for adjustive thinking in \(t=\bar{t}\) is defined implicitly by

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0\bar{t}},\frac{y^{*}}{\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\bar{t}}}\right)= & {} \mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

For any \(\bar{x}_{0}>\bar{x}_{0\bar{t}}\), \(u_{xy}>0\) implies

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{y}\left( \bar{x}_{0},\frac{y^{*}}{\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\bar{t}}} \right)> & {} \mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) \end{aligned}$$

and, moreover, \(y_{t}>y^{*}\) for all \(t\le \bar{t}\); which in turn implies \(x_{t}>x^{*}\), as well as an increased marginal valuation for \(x_{t}\) at all values of \(x_{t}\), which is what we sought to show.

Proof of Proposition 4

Let \(\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right)\) represent the steady-state optimum under the unique subgame perfect equilibrium with no advertising, and let \(\left( x\left( \tilde{y}_{01}\right),\tilde{y}_{01}\right)\) represent the consumption-adjustment pair corresponding to a level of advertising (write as \(A_{01}\)) in \(t=0\) just sufficient to induce a corner solution for adjustive thinking in \(t=1\). Using the full first-order condition for T as in the proof of Proposition 3, it follows that

$$\begin{aligned}&\mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) +\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) \mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) +\cdots = 1\\ &\mu u_{y}\left( x\left( \tilde{y}_{01}\right),\tilde{y}_{01}\right) +\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) \mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) +\cdots = 1-\phi \left( A_{01}\right) \end{aligned}$$

where the second condition follows, because one is dealing with the threshold value of the corner solution. Using the fact that all the terms on the left-hand side in these expressions are equal beyond the first, one may write

$$\begin{aligned} 1-\mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) &= {} 1-\phi \left( A_{01}\right) -\mu u_{y}\left( x\left( \tilde{y}_{01}\right),\tilde{y}_{01}\right) \\ \rightarrow \frac{\phi \left( A_{01}\right) }{\mu }&= u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) -u_{y}\left( x\left( \tilde{y}_{01}\right),\tilde{y}_{01}\right) \\&=u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) -u_{y}\left( x\left( \frac{y^{*}}{1-\sigma }\right),\frac{y^{*}}{1-\sigma }\right) \end{aligned}$$

where, for the last line, I again use the fact that \(\tilde{y}_{01}\) just induces a corner solution in \(t=1\).

Now consider the level of advertising in \(t=0\), \(A_{02}\), just sufficient to induce a corner solution for adjustive thinking in \(t=2\), and consider the corresponding \(\tilde{y}_{02}\). Using the first-order condition for T:

$$\begin{aligned} \mu u_{y}\left( x\left( \tilde{y}_{02}\right),\tilde{y}_{02}\right) +\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) \mu u_{y}\left( x\left( \left( 1-\sigma \right) \tilde{y}_{02}\right),\left( 1-\sigma \right) \tilde{y}_{02}\right) +\cdots= & {} 1-\phi \left( A_{02}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Here, because it reflects the threshold value of the corner solution at \(t=2\), all terms on the left-hand side are equal to those in the steady-state first-order condition beyond the second; this means one can write

$$\begin{aligned}&1-\mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) -\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) \mu u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) = 1-\phi \left( A_{02}\right) -\mu u_{y}\left( x\left( \tilde{y}_{02}\right),\tilde{y}_{02}\right) \\ &\qquad - \delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) \mu u_{y}\left( x\left( \left( 1-\sigma \right) \tilde{y}_{02}\right),\left( 1-\sigma \right) \tilde{y}_{02}\right) \\ &\quad \rightarrow \frac{\phi \left( A_{02}\right) }{\mu } = u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) -u_{y}\left( x\left( \frac{y^{*}}{\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}}\right),\frac{y^{*}}{\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{2}}\right) \\ &\qquad + \delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) -\delta \left( 1-\sigma \right) u_{y}\left( x\left( \frac{y^{*}}{1-\sigma }\right),\frac{y^{*}}{1-\sigma }\right) . \end{aligned}$$

By induction

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\phi \left( A_{0\bar{t}}\right) }{\mu }> & {} \sum _{i=0}^{\bar{t}-1}\delta ^{i}\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{i}\left[ u_{y}\left( x^{*},y^{*}\right) -u_{y}\left( x\left( \frac{y^{*}}{\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\bar{t}-i}}\right),\frac{y^{*}}{\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\bar{t}-i}}\right) \right] \end{aligned}$$
(24)

defines the level of advertising \(A_{0\bar{t}}\) in \(t=0\) sufficiently large to induce \(y_{t}>y^{*}\) and \(x_{t}>x^{*}\) for all \(t\le \bar{t}\). Note that existence of such a level of advertising depends on \(\frac{\alpha }{\mu }\) being larger than the right-hand side of (24); specifically, this is a necessary condition for \(\phi \left( A\right)\) being able to get large enough, given its limit, for (24) to hold.

The welfare results follow trivially: because the consumer adjusts in equilibrium, and advertising reduces the cost of adjustment, it relaxes the consumer’s constraint and so increases utility. The only additional requirement for the welfare effect of advertising to be unambiguously positive overall is that advertising be profitable for firms.

Proof of Proposition 5

The proof of Proposition 3 establishes that for the no-regret case there exists a threshold endowment level for every \(\tau\) that is defined implicitly by \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\tau }y_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0\tau }\right) =y^{*}\), where \(y_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0\tau }\right) =T_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0\tau }\right)\) is in turn defined by the first-order condition with respect to T, evaluated at \(\bar{x}_{0\tau }\). Totally differentiating \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\tau }T_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0\tau }\right) =y^{*}\) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\tau }\frac{\partial T_{0}}{\partial \bar{x}_{0\tau }}d\bar{x}_{0\tau }= & {} -\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\tau }\frac{\partial T_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0\tau }\right) }{\partial \beta _{0}}d\beta _{0} \end{aligned}$$

and, by Cramer’s rule,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \bar{x}_{0\tau }\left( \beta _{0}\right) }{\partial \beta _{0}}= & {} -\frac{\nicefrac {\partial T_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0\tau }\right) }{\partial \beta _{0}}}{\nicefrac {\partial T_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0\tau }\right) }{\partial \bar{x}_{0\tau }}}. \end{aligned}$$

The denominator can be signed positive based on Proposition 2. Given \(\nicefrac {\partial ^{2}T_{0}}{\partial \bar{x}_{0}\partial \beta _{0}}>0\)—also from Proposition 2—the numerator is also positive for \(\bar{x}_{0\tau }>x^{*}\). It follows that \(\frac{\partial \bar{x}_{0\tau }\left( \beta _{0}\right) }{\partial \beta _{0}}<0\).

Proof of Proposition 6

Consider first the extreme regret case \(\beta _{\tau }=1\) for some \(\tau >0\). It is clear from analysis of (4) that \(\bar{x}_{0}>x^{*}\) implies \(y_{\tau }>y^{*}\). Now instead suppose \(\beta _{\tau }\in \left( 0,1\right)\). We consider two cases. Suppose first that \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\tau }y_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0}\right) >y^{*}\). Then \(y_{\tau }>y^{*}\) for \(\beta _{\tau }=0\), whence by complementarity of x and y, it follows that \(x_{\tau }>x^{*}\) for \(\beta _{\tau }=0\). As it has already been established that \(y_{\tau }>y^{*}\) in the extreme regret case, then \(y_{\tau }>y^{*}\) also when \(\beta _{\tau }\in \left( 0,1\right)\), and we are done. Suppose instead that \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\tau }y_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0}\right) \le y^{*}\). Then \(y_{\tau }=y^{*}\) for \(\beta _{\tau }=0\). However, since \(y_{\tau }>y^{*}\) in the extreme regret case, it follows also that \(y_{\tau }>y^{*}\) for any \(\beta _{\tau }\in \left( 0,1\right)\), and so \(x_{\tau }>x^{*}\) follows by complementarity of x and y.

Proof of Proposition 7

Consider first the extreme regret case \(\beta _{\tau }=1\). It is clear from analysis of (4) that \(\bar{x}_{0}<x^{*}\) implies \(y_{\tau }<y^{*}\). Now instead suppose \(\beta _{\tau }\in \left( 0,1\right)\). It is obvious that \(\left( 1-\sigma \right) ^{\tau }y_{0}\left( \bar{x}_{0}\right) <y^{*}\). This means \(y_{\tau }=y^{*}\) for \(\beta _{\tau }=0\). However, since \(y_{\tau }<y^{*}\) in the extreme regret case, it follows also that \(y_{\tau }<y^{*}\) for any \(\beta _{\tau }\in \left( 0,1\right)\), and so \(x_{\tau }<x^{*}\) follows by complementarity of x and y.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nagler, M.G. Thoughts matter: a theory of motivated preference. Theory Decis 94, 211–247 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09891-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09891-y

Keywords

Navigation