Skip to main content
Log in

Stronger utility

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Empirical research often requires a method how to convert a deterministic economic theory into an econometric model. A popular method is to add a random error term on the utility scale. This method, however, ignores stochastic dominance. A modification of this method is proposed to account for stochastic dominance. The modified model compares favorably to other existing models in terms of goodness of fit to experimental data. The modified model can rationalize the preference reversal phenomenon. An intuitive axiomatic characterization of the modified model is provided. Important microeconomic concept of risk aversion is well defined in the modified model.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Camerer (1989), Starmer and Sugden (1989), Hey and Orme (1994), Wu (1994), Ballinger and Wilcox (1997), Loomes and Sugden (1998), Hey (2001), Schmidt and Hey (2004), Schmidt and Neugebauer (2007).

  2. If a decision maker has a strict preference over all outcomes (for any \(x, y \in X\) either \(x\succ y\) or \(y \succ x\)), then the second case is possible only when \(L = L^{\prime }\).

  3. Alternatively, choice probability may be left undefined in this case.

  4. Setting \(F(1) = 1\) is appealing on normative grounds. From a descriptive perspective, it may be desirable to set \(F (1)< 1\). This allows model (10) to account for rare violations of stochastic dominance that are observed in the data. See Loomes et al. (2002) for a more detailed discussion.

  5. Note that Fishburn (1978) model with a power function coincides with Blavatskyy (2011a) model with a function \(\varphi (v)= v ^{\mu }\) for all \(v \ge 0\).

  6. See also graphical representation in MacCrimmon and Smith (1986) and Butler and Loomes (2007).

  7. This special case may be considered as nearly conventional economic theory based on a revealed preference relation: \(L^{\prime }\succsim L\) when \(P (L, L^{\prime })=0\), \(L\succsim L^{\prime }\) when \(P (L,L^{\prime })=1\), and \(L \sim L^{\prime }\) when \(P (L, L^{\prime }) = 0.5\). This is “nearly conventional” because in standard economic theory a choice probability \(P (L, L^{\prime }\)) is not defined when \(L \sim L^{\prime }\).

  8. A popular class of QRE is logit QRE, which is based on model (6) with error term \(\xi \) drawn from the logistic distribution. This specification of strong utility is sometimes called Luce’s choice model (cf. Luce (1959).

References

  • Ballinger, P., & Wilcox, N. (1997). Decisions, error and heterogeneity. Economic Journal, 107, 1090–1105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P., & Pogrebna, G. (2010). Models of stochastic choice and decision theories: Why both are important for analyzing decisions. Journal of Applied Econometrics, 25(6), 963–986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2006). Violations of betweenness or random errors? Economics Letters, 91, 34–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2007). Stochastic expected utility theory. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 34, 259–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2008). Stochastic utility theorem. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 44, 1049–1056.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2009). Preference reversals and probabilistic choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 39(3), 237–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2011a). A model of probabilistic choice satisfying first-order stochastic dominance. Management Science, 57(3), 542–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2011b). Probabilistic risk aversion with an arbitrary outcome set. Economics Letters, 112(1), 34–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2012). An application of recent advances in decision theory to solving \(2\times 2\) simultaneous-move noncooperative games in the normal form (unpublished).

  • Buschena, D., & Zilberman, D. (2000). Generalized expected utility, heteroscedastic error, and path dependence in risky choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 20, 67–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. D., & Loomes, G. C. (2007). Imprecision as an account of the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review, 97(1), 277–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. (1989). An experimental test of several generalized utility theories. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 2, 61–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbone, E., & Hey, J. (1995). A comparison of the estimates of EU and non-EU preference functionals using data from pairwise choice and complete ranking experiments. Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 20, 111–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falmagne, J.-C. (1985). Elements of psychophysical theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fechner, G. (1860). Elements of Psychophysics. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. (1978). A probabilistic expected utility theory of risky binary choices. International Economic Review, 19, 633–646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P. (1988). Nonlinear preference and utility theory. Brighton: Wheatsheaf Books Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gul, F., & Pesendorfer, W. (2006). Random expected utility. Econometrica, 71(1), 121–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harless, D., & Camerer, C. (1994). The predictive utility of generalized expected utility theories. Econometrica, 62, 1251–1289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J., & Orme, C. (1994). Investigating generalisations of expected utility theory using experimental data. Econometrica, 62, 1291–1326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J. (1995). Experimental investigations of errors in decision making under risk. European Economic Review, 39, 633–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J. (2001). Does repetition improve consistency? Experimental Economics, 4, 5–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J. (2005). Why we should not be silent about noise. Experimental Economics, 8, 325–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1995). Incorporating a stochastic element into decision theories. European Economic Review, 39, 641–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1998). Testing different stochastic specifications of risky choice. Economica, 65, 581–598.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., Moffatt, P., & Sugden, R. (2002). A microeconomic test of alternative stochastic theories of risky choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 24, 103–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G. (2005). Modelling the stochastic component of behaviour in experiments: Some issues for the interpretation of data. Experimental Economics, 8, 301–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. D. (1959). Individual choice behavior. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCrimmon, K., & Smith, M. (1986). Imprecise equivalences: Preference reversals in money and probability. University of British Columbia working paper 1211.

  • Machina, M. (1982). Expected utility’ analysis without the independence axiom. Econometrica, 50, 277–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R., & Palfrey, T. (1995). Quantal response equilibria for normal form games. Games and Economic Behavior, 10, 6–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1981). Risk perception and risk aversion among Australian farmers. Australian Journal of Agricultural Recourse Economics, 25, 160–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieskamp, J., Busemeyer, J., & Mellers, B. (2006). Extending the bounds of rationality: Evidence and theories of preferential choice. Journal of Economic Literature, XLIV, 631–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seidl, C. (2002). Preference reversal. Journal of Economic Surveys, 16, 621–655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, U., & Hey, J. (2004). Are preference reversals errors? An experimental investigation. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 29, 207–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, U., & Neugebauer, T. (2007). Testing expected utility in the presence of errors. Economic Journal, 117, 470–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (1989). Probability and juxtaposition effects: An experimental investigation of the common ratio effect. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 2, 159–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., Slovic, P., & Kahneman, D. (1990). The causes of preference reversal. American Economic Review, 80, 204–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vuong, Q. (1989). Likelihood ratio tests for model selection and non-nested hypotheses. Econometrica, 57, 307–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilcox, N. (2008). Stochastic models for binary discrete choice under risk: A critical primer and econometric comparison. In J. C. Cox & G. W. Harrison (Eds.), Research in experimental economics (Vol. 12, pp. 197–292). Bingley: Emerald.

  • Wilcox, N. (2011). Stochastically more risk averse: A contextual theory of stochastic discrete choice under risk. Journal of Econometrics, 162, 89–104 .

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, G. (1994). An empirical test of ordinal independence. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 9, 39–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yaari, M. E. (1969). Some remarks on measures of risk aversion and on their uses. Journal of Economic Theory, 1, 315–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pavlo R. Blavatskyy.

Appendix

Appendix

1.1 Proof of Proposition 3

Consider an arbitrary outcome \(x \in X\) and a lottery \(L \in \mathcal{{L}}\). We shall prove that if conditions of proposition 3 hold.

If outcome \(x\) is less preferred than the worst possible outcome in lottery \(L\), then model (10) implies that and . Since , it must be the case that . Similarly, if outcome \(x\) is more preferred than the best possible outcome in lottery \(L\), then we have . What remains is to consider the case when outcome \(x\) lies between the worst and the best possible outcome in lottery \(L\).

If inequality (22) holds for all \(x, y, z \in X\) such that \(z \succsim x \succsim y\) then

(24)

If inequality (24) holds then the following inequality holds as well:

(25)

Since for all \(v \in [-1,1]\) and it is a non-decreasing function, we can rewrite inequality (25) as

(26)

According to formula (10), the left-hand side of (26) is equal to and the right-hand side of (26) is equal to . Thus, . \(\square \)

1.2 Matlab R2009a programing code used in Sect. 3 to estimate model (10) with functional form (11)

% this program searches for the maximum likelihood estimates of model (10) with functional form (11) and rank-dependent utility (expected utility is a special case when we set parameter gamma \(=\) 1)

figure a

% the program calls a user-defined function RDU_RC presented below. The function uses an input \(100\times 8\) array L1 of lottery probabilities. Probability of the lowest, two middle and the highest outcome in the left lottery is given in vectors L1(:,1), L1(:,2), L1(:,3) and L1(:,4) correspondingly. Probability of the lowest, two middle and the highest outcome in the right lottery is given in vectors L1(:,5), L1(:,6), L1(:,7) and L1(:,8) correspondingly. The function also uses an input \(100\times 53\) array A of probabilities with which each subject chooses the right lottery in each decision problem.

figure b

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Blavatskyy, P.R. Stronger utility. Theory Decis 76, 265–286 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-013-9366-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-013-9366-3

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation