Skip to main content
Log in

An experimental study on the ontology of relations

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is an ongoing debate on the ontology of relations, which features four main competing approaches: directionalism, positionalism, anti-positionalism, and primitivism. This paper focuses on a particular version of positionalism, namely role positionalism, and proposes the results of an experimental philosophy research concerning aspects of it. We tested the intuitions of ordinary subjects regarding the inter-relational generality of the roles typically assumed for spatial and kinematic relations, namely source, destination, theme, location. According to a 2014 paper by Orilia, this generality is rather wide, as it encompasses relations of temporal order, causation, quantitative order, transaction, possession, and parthood. Our findings do not support this proposal, except for parthood, and, in a limited way, for temporal order. We also tested the intuitions of ordinary subjects regarding the contrast between the pro-converses option, according to which non-symmetric relations split into distinct converse relations, and the anti-converses option, according to which non-symmetric relations have no distinct converses. Although traditionally positionalism is associated to the latter option, in recent works by Orilia role positionalism is associated to the former option for at least some relations, while remaining anchored to the latter option for other relations. Our findings support this mixed line to some extent, but not quite in the way suggested by Orilia in such works.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On thematic roles, see, for example, Fillmore (1968), Jackendoff (1972, 1990), Gruber (1976), Palmer (1994).

  2. On experimental philosophy in general, see for example Knobe and Nichols (2008), Alexander (2012) and Knobe (2017). On experimental metaphysics, see Rose et al. (2017).

  3. See Russell (1903), Grossman (1983) and Dixon (forthcoming).

  4. As regards symmetric relations, they can be viewed as having no directions, or as having two opposite directions at once, and as capable of being exemplified by the same relata in multiple orders. For example, if John is next to Mary, next to is exemplified by John and Mary, in that order, since it has the direction from John to Mary, and also by Mary and John, in that other order, since it also has the direction from Mary to John (see Paolini Paoletti, 2023).

  5. See Russell (2016), Hochberg (1987), Gilmore (2013), Donnelly (2016, 2021) and Dixon (2018).

  6. See Fine (2000) and Leo (2013).

  7. See Gaskin and Hill (2012) and MacBride (2014).

  8. See the references provided in Sect. 1.

  9. We included the following Privacy Policy statement:

    Survey “The Ontology of Relations” – Privacy Policy.

    We inform you that the General Data Protection Regulation (EU Regulation 679/2016, from now on “GDPR”) assumes that the protection of physical persons—with respect to the treatment of personal data—is a fundamental right. Following the GDPR, personal data processing should comply with the principles of accuracy, lawfulness, transparency and protection of confidentiality and of personal rights. This Privacy Policy is introduced in fulfilment of the Article 13 of the GDPR. The legal grounds of personal data processing are based on the Article 1, clause 1E, of the GDPR.

    • 1. Data Controller.

      The Data Controller of the personal data you sent by filling the survey is the University of Macerata, based in Macerata, via Crescimbeni 30-32, and the Legal Representative is its “Magnifico Rettore”. You can get in contact with the Data Controller either at that address, or by sending a message to https://www.urp@unimc.it or to the PEC address https://www.ateneo@pec.unimc.it.

    • 2. Data Protection Officer.

      The Data Protection Officer is based at the Data Controller and is appointed in compliance with the Article 37 of the GDPR. You can get in contact with the Data Protection Officer by sending a message to https://www.dpo@unimc.it.

    • 3. Nature and Purpose of Processing.

      Personal data will be processed for research purposes only and will not be shared—not even under pseudonymization. Only the results of the statistical analysis of personal data will be shared and made public. Moreover, the Investigators will not be able to identify the respondents and they will not be able to associate the personal data collected with the identity of each respondent.

      4. Data Diffusion.

      In connection with the purposes described above and only within their scope, personal data will not be shared – as described above.

      5. Profiling.

      Personal data will not be subjected to automatized decision-making processes (including profiling).

      6. Data Retention Duration.

      Personal data will only be retained until the purposes of their processing will be reached—as described above.

      7. Data Recipients and Potential Data Transfer.

      Personal data collected for the purposes specified above will only used by the Principal Investigator of the research project for those purposes. Personal data will not be transferred to any extra-EU country.

    • 8. Data Subjects’ Rights (the right to be informed, of access, to rectification, to erasure, to restrict processing, to revoke consent, to object).

      All the subjects involved in personal data processing have the right to ask the University of Macerata (as the Data Controller and in compliance with the Articles 15, 16, 17, 18, 19 and 21 of the GDPR):

      • to access their own personal data and the information specified in the Article 15 of the GDPR;

      • to rectify inexact personal data and to integrate incomplete personal data;

      • to erase their personal data;

      • to restrict data processing in the cases specified in the Article 18 of the GDPR;

      • to object to their personal data processing;

      • to revoke their consent to non-mandatory personal data processing, without making illegitimate data processing performed before the revocation.

      These rights can be exercised by sending a message to the Data Protection Office to the e-mail address: https://www.dpo@unimc.it.

      All the subjects involved in personal data processing can also lodge a complaint with the Data Protection Authority in compliance with the Article 77 of the GDPR.

      By filling Part 5 of the survey “The Ontology of Relations”, you accept the terms and conditions of this Privacy Policy. You also give your consent to the use of the data only for the purposes and only in the ways specified in this Privacy Policy (EU Regulation 679/2016).

  10. It may be thought that we could have used additional screening questions regarding converses, based on the assumption that, for at least some relations, there is consensus on whether or not the relation in question has a distinct converse. As far as we know, no relation is such that there is consensus on this and thus we did not consider this option. We felt however that, although the screening questions focus mainly on roles, they somehow also provide, if answered successfully, some evidence of a competence about relationality that is relevant for a proper understanding of the questions regarding converses, which will be discussed in Sect. 6.

  11. The Population Standard Deviation measures the degree of variation among the individual results. It can be taken to reflect how much the participants converge on, or diverge from, the mean value.

References

  • Alexander, J. (2012). Experimental philosophy: An introduction. Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, S. (2018). Plural slot theory. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 11, 193–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, S. (forthcoming). Directionalism and relations of arbitrary symmetry. Dialectica.

  • Donnelly, M. (2016). Positionalism revisited. In A. Marmodoro & D. Yates (Eds.), The metaphysics of relations (pp. 80–99). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, M. (2021). Explaining the differential application of non-symmetric relations. Synthese, 199, 3587–3610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore, C. J. (1968). The case for case. In E. Bach & R. T. Harms (Eds.), Universals of linguistic theory (pp. 1–88). Holt, Rinehart & Winston.

  • Fine, K. (2000). Neutral relations. The Philosophical Review, 199, 1–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaskin, R., & Hill, D. J. (2012). On neutral relations. Dialectica, 66, 167–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilmore, C. (2013). Slots in universals. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 8, 187–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossman, R. (1983). The categorial structure of the world. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruber, J. S. (1976). Lexical structures in syntax and semantics. North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hochberg, H. (1987). Russell’s early analysis of relational predication and the asymmetry of the predication relation. Philosophia, 17, 439–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. S. (1972). Semantic interpretation in generative grammar. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. S. (1990). Semantic structures. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2017). Experimental philosophy. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved on January 23, 2023, from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/experimental-philosophy/

  • Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (Eds.). (2008). Experimental philosophy. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leo, J. (2013). Relational complexes. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42, 357–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacBride, F. (2014). How involved do you want to be in a non-symmetrical relationship? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacBride, F. (2020). Relations. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved on January 23, 2023, from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/relations

  • Orilia, F. (2008). The problem of order in relational states of affairs: A Leibnizian view. In R. Egidi & G. Bonino (Eds.), Fostering the ontological turn. Gustav Bergmann (1906–1987) (pp. 161–185). de Gruyter.

  • Orilia, F. (2011). Relational order and onto-thematic roles. Metaphysica, 12, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orilia, F. (2014). Positions, ordering relations and O-roles. Dialectica, 68, 283–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orilia, F. (2019). Relations, O-roles and applied ontology. Philosophical Inquiries, 7, 115–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orilia, F. (2020) Van Inwagen’s approach to relations and the theory of o-roles. In M. Szatkowski (Ed.), Quo vadis metaphysics? Essays in honor of Peter Van Inwagen (pp. 279–296). De Gruyter.

  • Orilia, F. (forthcoming) Converse relations and the sparse-abundant distinction. Dialectica.

  • Palmer, F. R. (1994). Grammatical roles and relations. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Paolini Paoletti, M. (2016). Non-symmetrical relations, O-roles, and modes. Acta Analytica, 31, 373–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paolini Paoletti, M. (2023). Relationism and the problem of order. Acta Analytica, 38, 245–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, D., Beebee, J. R., & Schaffer, J. (Eds.). (2017). Experimental metaphysics. Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1903). The principles of mathematics. Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (2016). Theory of knowledge: The 1913 manuscript. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by the Italian Ministry of Education, University and Research through the PRIN 2017 project “The Manifest Image and the Scientific Image” prot. 2017ZNWW7F_004, and our research was approved by the Ethical Committee of the University of Macerata, on July, 8, 2021. We wish to thank two anonymous referees for their useful comments. We also wish to thank Ivana Bianchi, Roberto Burro, Vincenzo Mauro and Stefano Perri for their advice on statistical matters.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michele Paolini Paoletti.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Orilia, F., Paolini Paoletti, M. An experimental study on the ontology of relations. Synthese 203, 75 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-024-04485-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-024-04485-3

Keywords

Navigation