Skip to main content
Log in

Propter quid demonstrations: Roger Bacon on geometrical causes in natural philosophy

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In Posterior Analytics 1.13, Aristotle introduced a distinction between two kinds of demonstrations: of the fact (quia), and of the reasoned fact (propter quid). Both demonstrations take a syllogistic form, in which the middle term links either two facts (in the case of quia demonstrations) or a proximate cause and a fact (in the case of propter quid demonstrations). While Aristotle stated that all the terms of one demonstration must be taken from within the same subject matter, he admitted some exceptions in which the fact and the reasoned fact are instantiated by terms from different sciences, as when mathematics provides the reason and another science the empirical fact. This was the methodological foundation of the “mixed sciences”, a subject of varying interpretations in the thirteenth century. Roger Bacon (C. 1220–1292), adhering to Robert Grosseteste’s (C. 1168–1563) commentary on Posterior Analytics, presented a unique interpretation of this exception. He replaced propositional demonstrations with geometrical considerations and diagrams, thus producing geometrical arguments for theorems in natural philosophy. I focus on Bacon’s propter quid arguments, as applied in three case studies: (1) the heat caused by a body moving to its natural place; (2) the motion of the scale; (3) and the contraction of water. Based on an analysis of these demonstrations, I argue that Bacon’s interpretation of propter quid demonstration reflects his application of a scientific methodology that imbues geometrical objects with causal power over material bodies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more on this topic, see, among others, Bolton (1991), Lennox (2010), and Owen (1966).

  2. Thomas Aquinas was not aware of this fact when he commented on the Posterior Analytics, since the Latin version of the Physics he used corrupted the key Physics II 2 passage, rendering it ‘the sciences which are more physical than mathematical.’ See Aquinas’ commentary on Physics, Book II, Lecture 3. For related discussions, See; Di Liscia (2009), p. 294; Distelzweig (2013), p. 90.

  3. Sandoz refers to On the Heavens 290b1 for a claim about the permanence of celestial bodies, and to On the Soul II. 7–8 for a description of light and sound as incorporeal forms distinguished from sight and hearing.

  4. This could explain why in On the Heavens Aristotle seems to breach his metabasis prohibition, undertaking a natural investigation of heaven, a breach indicated by Distelzweig (2013).

  5. Note that the thirteenth-century interpretation—just like any other interpretation—does not necessarily conform with Aristotle’s original intention. Hussey (2002), Lear (1982), and Lennox (1986) argue that in Aristotle’s philosophy of mathematics, real mathematical properties are present within material terrestrial substances (but do not exhaust their essences). They deduce from this analysis a possible use of mathematical middle terms in natural philosophy. Lear, for example, argues that there is “evidence that he [Aristotle] thought that even in the sublunary world physical objects could perfectly instantiate geometrical properties” (1982, p. 177), and Lennox states that “There seems to be nothing in Galileo’s appeal in his new science to mathematical demonstration that Aristotle would not wholeheartedly endorse” (1986, p. 51). This, however, was not the accepted thirteenth-century interpretation.

  6. See McEvoy’s (1983, pp. 636–643), and Southern’s (1986, pp. 131–3) argument for a slightly earlier date (1220–1225). Lewis (2003) suggests that the work was written in the 1220s but with some additions from the 1230s.

  7. van Dyke (2009) argues that this attempt was successful.

  8. The broadening of the domain of optics in the Latin world owes its origin to Robert Kilwardby’s De ortu scientiarum. Kilwardby (C. 1215–1279) read Alhazan’s De aspectibus and defined the subject of optics as the “way of seeing” (modus videndi), and its end as the knowledge of the rules of vision and the perfection of our vision through such knowledge. He observed that although it is subalternate to geometry, perspectiva is more truly a natural science (De ortu scientiarum, pp. 36–50).

  9. “Et necesse est omnia sciri per hanc scientiam, quia omnes actiones rerum fiunt secundum specierum et virtutum multiplicationem ab agentibus hujus mundi in materias patientes; et leges hujusmodi multiplicationum non sciuntur nisi a perspectiva, nec alibi sunt traditae”.

  10. “res mathematica et naturalis non differant nisi penes consideracionem et non secundum esse et secundum rem ut Aristoteles dicit et demonstratum est in Methaphisicis, manifestum est quod id accidit mathematice et naturaliter secundum esse in rebus.”.

  11. The diagram is taken from Vat. Lat. 4086, fol. 33r. This is a fourteenth-century manuscript, closely resembling (but not a copy of) Cotton Jul. D. v, which is the oldest manuscript of the Opus majus, held by the British Museum and partly destroyed by fire (Little, 1914, p. 379).

  12. Jardine and Jardine (2010, p. 394) address the question of the purpose of a diagram and its relation to the text: is it mainly illustrative, or is it meant to convey information about geometrical configurations not explicitly present in the text? This question deserves, indeed, a separate discussion. However, it seems to me that Bacon would have argued that his demonstrations could not work without these diagrams, for to be convinced, one must see with his own eyes the difference between the straight and the diagonal, the vertical components, and the two arcs cut by the same cord (see the next two demonstrations).

  13. Fisher and Unguru (1971, p. 360) note the tight link between mathematics and experience in Bacon. By drawing figures and counting, mathematics contains intrinsic certifying experiences. These ‘perceptible experiments’ make everything clear to the senses (rather than to reason) and preclude all possibility of doubting.

  14. As Saito (2012) notes, it is often the case that medieval diagrams are schematic, oversimplified, and inaccurate. To communicate general mathematical relations, this is enough.

  15. What we know about Jordanus de Nemore amounts to conjectures only. He taught in Paris (Hoyrup, 1988, p. 346), and was a capable mathematician, who composed treatises on algebra, arithmetic, geometry, and statics, all compiled before 1260. The works on statics ascribed to him exemplify a union of a philosophical Aristotelian approach with a more rigorous mathematical tradition of Euclid and Archimedes (Moody & Clagett, 1952, pp. 6–7). Some of the texts ascribed to him were likely written by members of his circle, which included, among others, Richard of Fournival (1201–?1260), Gerard of Brussels (fl. thirteenth century), and Campanus of Novara (C. 1220–1296). It has been suggested that Bacon and Jordanus may have met in the 1240s in Paris. On this suggestion, Bacon may have had close contact with Jordanus and his circle although he was not an actual member of this circle (Hoyrup, 1988, pp. 346–351). To be sure, Bacon provided several references to books associated with Jordanus, such as Liber philotegni, Liber de triangulis Jordani, and Liber Jordani de ponderibus, while expressing appreciation for his mathematical capabilities.

  16. For the concept of positional gravity, see among others, Brown (1978, pp. 191–192), and Moody and Clagett (1952, pp. 15–17).

  17. The diagram is taken from Vat. Lat. 4086, fol. 34r.

References

  • Aristotle, Metaphysics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), and W. D. Ross (Trans.), The Complete Works of Aristotle – The revised Oxford Translation (vol. 2, pp. 1552–1728). 1984, Princeton University Press.

  • Aristotle, Posterior Analytics. In J. Barnes (Ed. And trans.), The Complete Works of Aristotle – The revised Oxford Translation (vol. 1, pp. 114–166). 1984, Princeton University Press.

  • Bacon, R. Opus majus. In J. H. Bridges (Ed.), vol. 3. 1897–1900, Clarendon Press.

  • Bacon, R. Communia naturalium. In R. Steele (Ed.), Opera hactenus inedita Rogeri Baconi (fascs 2–4). 1905–1940, Oxford University Press.

  • Bacon, R. Opus tertium. In J. S. Brewer (Ed.), Fr. Rogeri Bacon – Opera quaedam hactenus inedita (vol. 1, pp. 3–310). 1965, Cambridge University Press.

  • Bacon, R. Opus majus IV. In P. W. Dennis (Trans.), Roger Bacon's mathematical thought: a translation of part IV of the Opus majus with Introduction and Commentary (unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation). 2011, Dallas.

  • Bolton, R. (1991). Aristotle’s method in natural science: Physics I. In L. Judson (Ed.), Aristotle’s Physics: A Collection of Essays (pp. 1–29). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. E. (1978). The Science of weights. In D. C. Lindberg (Ed.), Science in the Middle Ages (pp. 179–204). University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crombie, A. C. (1953). Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science, 1100–1700. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crombie, A. C. (1957). Augustine to Galileo. The History of Science A. D. 400–1650. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demange, D. (2021). “…cupiens mathematicam tractare infra radices metaphysice…”. Roger Bacon on mathematical abstraction. Revista Española de Filosofía Medieval, 28(1), 67–98.

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • De Nemore, J. Liber philotegni. In M. Clagett (Ed.), Archimedes in the Middle Ages, vol. 5. 1984, American Philosophical Society.

  • Di Liscia, D. A. (2009). Kepler’s a priori Copernicanism in his Mysterium Cosmographicum. In M. A. Granada and E. Mehl (Eds.), Nouveau ciel, Nouvelle terre. L’astronomie copernicienne dans l’Allemagne de la Réforme (1530–1630) (pp. 283–317). Les Belles Lettres.

  • Distelzweig, P. M. (2013). The Intersection of the mathematical and natural sciences: The subordinate sciences in Aristotle. Apeiron, 46(2), 85–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, N. W., & Unguru, S. (1971). Experimental science and mathematics in Roger Bacon’s thought. Traditio, 27, 353–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galli, F. (2021). Where does the last drop make the cup run over? Roger Bacon vs John Peckham, and Bartolomeo da Bologna on the properties of water and the capacity of vessels. Studi Medievali, 62(2), 641–662.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosseteste, R. Commentarius in posteriorum analyticorum libros. In P. Rossi (Ed.). 1981, Olschki.

  • Grosseteste, R. On lines, angels, and figures. In B. Ludwig (Ed.), Die philosophischen werke des Robert Grosseteste. Bischofs von Lincoln (pp. 51–58). 1912, Aschendorff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Høyrup, J. (1988). Jordanus de Nemore, 13th-century mathematical innovator: An essay on intellectual context, achievement, and failure. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 38, 307–363. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00357064

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hussey, E. (2002). Aristotle and mathematics. In L. Wolpert, C. J. Tuplin, & T. E. Rihll (Eds.), Science and Mathematics in Ancient Greek Culture (pp. 217–229). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jardine, B., & Jardine, N. (2010). Critical editing of early-modern astronomical diagrams. Journal for the History of Astronomy, 41(3), 393–414.

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Kilwardby, R. De ortu scientiarum. In A. Judy (Ed.). 1976, Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.

  • Laird, W. R. (1987). Robert Grosseteste on the subalternate sciences. Traditio, 43, 147–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lear, J. (1982). Aristotle’s philosophy of mathematics. The Philosophical Review, 91(2), 161–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J. G. (1986). Aristotle, Galileo, and ‘Mixed Sciences.’ In W. A. Wallace (Ed.), Reinterpreting Galileo (pp. 29–52). Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J. G. (2010). Aristotle’s natural science: The many and the one. Apeiron, 43(2–3), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, N. T. (2003). Robert Grosseteste’s notes on physics. In E. A. Mackie & G. Joseph (Eds.), Robert Grosseteste (pp. 103–134). University of Toronto Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lindberg, D. C. (1982). On the applicability of mathematics to nature: Roger Bacon and his predecessors. British Journal for the History of Science, 15, 2–24.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Lindberg, D. C. (1987). Roger Bacon and the origins of perspectiva in the West. In E. Grant & J. E. Murdoch (Eds.), Mathematics and its Applications to Science and Natural Philosophy in the Middle Ages (pp. 249–268). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Little, A. G. (1914). Appendix: Roger Bacon’s Works, with References to the MSS. With Printed Editions. In A. G. Little (Ed.), Roger Bacon—Essays (pp. 373–425). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Livesey, S. J. (1986). The Oxford calculators, quantification of qualities, and Aristotle’s prohibition of metabasis. Vivarium, 24, 50–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longeway, J. (2005). Medieval Theories of Demonstration. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 Edition). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/demonstration-medieval/.

  • Marshall, D. B. (2011). Investigations into the applicability of geometry (Ph.D. diss.). Harvard University.

  • McEvoy, J. (1983). The chronology of Robert Grosseteste’s writings on nature and natural philosophy. Speculum, 58(3), 614–655.

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • McKirahan, R. D. (1978). Aristotle’s subordinate sciences. The British Journal for the History of Science, 9, 197–220.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • McKirahan, R. D. (1992). Principles and proofs—Aristotle’s theory of demonstrative science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moody, E. A., and Clagett, M. (1952). The Medieval Science of Weights (Scientia de ponderibus)—Treatises Ascribed to Euclid, Archimedes, Thabit ibn Qurra, Jordanus de Nemore, and Blasius of Parma. University of Wisconsin Press.

  • Owen, G. E. L. (1966). The Platonism of Aristotle. Proceedings of the British Academy, 51, 125–150. reprinted in M. Nussbaum (Ed.). (1986). Logic, Science, and Dialectic: Collected Papers in Greek Philosophy. London, pp. 200–220.

  • Peckham, J. (1972). Tractatus de perspectiva. In D. C. Lindberg (Ed.). Franciscan Institute Publications.

  • Saito, K. (2012). Traditions of the diagram, tradition of the text: A case study. Synthese, 186(1), 7–20.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sandoz, R. (2018). Applying mathematics to empirical sciences: Flashback to a puzzling disciplinary interaction. Synthese, 195(2), 875–898.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Southern, R. W. (1986). Robert Grosseteste. The Growth of an English Mind. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Dyke, C. (2009). An Aristotelian theory of divine illumination: Robert Grosseteste’s commentary on the Posterior Analytics. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 17(4), 685–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, W. A. (1972). Causality and Scientific Explanation. Medieval and Early Classical Science (Vol. 1). University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisheipl, J. A. (1965). Classification of the sciences in medieval thought. Mediaeval studies, 27, 54–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisheipl, J. A. (1985). Nature and Motion in the Middle Ages. Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Daniel Di Liscia and Giora Hon for their valuable comments on this paper, and to Jeremiah Hackett for his help with finding the manuscripts. This reaserch was supported by the Israel Science Foundation (Grant No. 2773/21).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yael Kedar.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kedar, Y. Propter quid demonstrations: Roger Bacon on geometrical causes in natural philosophy. Synthese 203, 18 (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04433-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04433-7

Keywords

Navigation