Skip to main content
Log in

Navigating dissent by managing value judgments: the case of Lyme disease

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent philosophical literature has highlighted the complexities of handling dissent in science. On one hand, scientific dissent can be very harmful, as when “merchants of doubt” strategically appeal to dissent in order to undermine important environmental and public-health initiatives. On the other hand, scientific dissent can also be beneficial when it helps to promote scientific objectivity, progress, and public engagement. Some authors have responded to this tension by suggesting criteria for distinguishing normatively appropriate and inappropriate dissent, while other authors have suggested that it is more fruitful to alter the social context in which science operates in order to alleviate the negative effects of dissent over the long term. This paper proposes another approach that may be helpful for managing particularly challenging cases of scientific dissent. It argues that instances of scientific dissent often incorporate debates over value judgments, so many difficult cases of dissent can be navigated by: (1) identifying and highlighting those value judgments; and (2) managing those value judgments by drawing strategies from the extensive literature on values and science. The paper illustrates this approach by examining a case study of dissent over the treatment of long-term symptoms associated with Lyme disease.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout this paper, I will typically refer to “appropriate” and “inappropriate” dissent rather than using Biddle and Leuschner’s language of “epistemically detrimental” dissent. I think it is at least possible that dissent could be inappropriate for reasons other than being epistemically detrimental, and dissent could potentially be appropriate in some cases even if it is epistemically detrimental. See also de Melo-Martín and Intemann’s (2018) concept of “normatively inappropriate dissent.”

  2. See https://www.hhs.gov/ash/advisory-committees/tickbornedisease/index.html.

References

  • Alexandrova, A. (2018). Can the science of well-being be objective? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69, pp. 421–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Auwaerter, P. G., Bakken, J. S., Dattwyler, R. J., Dumler, J. S., Halperin, J. J., McSweegan, E., Nadelman, R. B., O’Connell, S., Shapiro, E. D., Sood, S. K., Steere, A. C., Weinstein, A., & Wormser, G. P. (2011a). Antiscience and ethical concerns associated with advocacy of Lyme disease. The Lancet Infectious Diseases, 11, pp. 713–719.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Auwaerter, P. G., Bakken, J. S., Dattwyler, R. J., Dumler, J. S., Halperin, J. J., McSweegan, E., Nadelman, R. B., O’Connell, S., Sood, S. K., Weinstein, A., & Wormser, G. P. (2011b). Scientific evidence and best patient care practices should guide the ethics of Lyme disease activism. Journal of Medical Ethics, 37, pp. 68–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berndtson, K. (2013). Review of evidence for immune evasion and persistent infection in Lyme disease. International Journal of General Medicine, 291–306.

  • Biddle, J., & Leuschner, A. (2015). Climate skepticism and the manufacture of doubt: Can dissent in science be epistemically detrimental? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 5, pp. 261–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boykoff, M., & Boykoff, J. (2004). Balance as bias: Global warming and the U.S. Prestige Press. Global Environmental Change, 14, pp. 125–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corburn, J. (2005). Street science: Community knowledge and environmental health justice. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Melo-Martín, I., & Intemann, K. (2014). Who’s afraid of dissent? Addressing concerns about undermining scientific consensus in public policy developments. Perspectives on Science, 22(4), pp. 593–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Melo-Martín, I., & Intemann, K. (2018). The fight against doubt: How to Bridge the gap between scientists and the public. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • DeLong, A. K., Blossom, B., Maloney, E. L., & Phillips, S. E. (2012). Antibiotic retreatment of Lyme disease in patients with persistent symptoms: A biostatistical review of randomized, placebo-controlled, clinical trials. Contemporary Clinical Trials, 33, pp. 1132–1142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiMarco, M., & Khalifa, K. (2019). Inquiry tickets: values, pursuit, and underdetermination. Philosophy of Science, 86, pp. 1016–1028.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2005). Inserting the Public into Science. In S. Maasen & P. Weingart (Eds.), Democratization of expertise? Exploring novel forms of scientific advice in political decision-making (pp. 153–169). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2008). The role of values in expert reasoning. Public Affairs Quarterly, 22, pp. 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2014). The moral terrain of science. Erkenntnis, 79, pp. 961–979.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dumes, A. A. (2020). Divided bodies: Lyme disease, contested illness, and evidence-based medicine. Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. (2011). Is a little pollution good for you? Incorporating societal values in environmental research. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. (2017). A tapestry of values: An introduction to values in science. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. C. (2019). Science journalism, value judgments, and the open science movement. Frontiers in Communication, 4, 71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. (2022a). A taxonomy of transparency in science. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 52, pp. 342–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K. (2022b). Values in Science. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K., & McKaughan, D. J. (2014). Nonepistemic values and the multiple goals of science. Philosophy of Science, 81, pp. 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K., & Resnik, D. B. (2014). Science, policy, and the transparency of values. Environmental Health Perspectives, 122, pp. 647–650.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, K., & Willmes, D. (2013). Cognitive attitudes and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), pp. 807–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fallon, B. A., & Sotsky, J. (2017). Conquering Lyme disease: Science bridges the great divide. Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fallon, B. A., Keilp, J. G., Corbera, K. M., et al. (2008). A randomized, placebo-controlled trial of repeated iv antibiotic therapy for Lyme encephalopathy. Neurology, 70, pp. 992–1003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernández Pinto, M., & Hicks, D. J. (2019). Legitimizing values in regulatory science. Environmental Health Perspectives, 127, p. 035001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Firestein, S. (2012). Ignorance: How It drives science. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleming, N. (2020). Coronavirus misinformation, and how scientists can help to fight it. Nature, 583, pp. 155–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franco, P. L. (2017). Assertion, nonepistemic values, and scientific practice. Philosophy of Science, 84, pp. 160–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godler, Y., Reich, Z., & Miller, B. (2020). Social epistemology as a new paradigm for journalism and media studies. New Media and Society, 22, pp. 213–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldenberg, M. (2021). Vaccine hesitancy: Public trust, expertise, and the war on science. University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, M., & Elliott, K. (2022). Science as experience: A deweyan model of science communication. Perspectives on Science, 30, pp. 621–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harker, D. (2015). Creating scientific controversies: Uncertainty and bias in science and society. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harvard, S., & Werker, G. (2021). Health economists on involving patients in modeling: Potential benefits, harms, and variables of interest. PharmacoEconomics, 39, pp. 823–833.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harvard, S., & Winsberg, E. (2022). The epistemic risk in representation. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 32(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, D. J. (2017). Scientific controversies as proxy politics. Issues in Science and Technology, 33, p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holman, B., & Elliott, K. C. (2018). The promise and perils of industry-funded science. Philosophy Compass, 13, p. e12544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holman, B., & Wilholt, T. (2022). The new demarcation problem. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 91, pp. 211–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horel, S. and Foucart, S. (2020). Endocrine disruptors in Europe: Nineteen “Experts” are polluting the debate. Environmental Health News, June 23. Retrieved August 23, 2023 from https://www.ehn.org/european-parliament-endocrine-disruptors-2646227143.html

  • ILADS. (2020). Controversies and challenges in treating Lyme and other tick-borne diseases. https://www.ilads.org/research-literature/controversies-challenges/. Accessed 19 Oct 2023.

  • Intemann, K. (2015). Distinguishing between legitimate and illegitimate values in climate modeling. European Journal for Philosophy of Science., 5, pp. 217–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • John, S. (2019). Science, truth, and dictatorship: Wishful thinking or wishful speaking? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 78, pp. 64–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, L., & Stricker, R. B. (2009). Attorney general forces infectious diseases society of America to Redo Lyme guidelines due to flawed development process. Journal of Medical Ethics, 35, pp. 283–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klempner, M. S., Hu, L. T., Evans, J., Schmid, C. H., Johnson, G. M., Trevino, R. P., Norton, D., Levy, L., Wall, D., McCall, J., & Kosinski, M. (2001). Two controlled trials of antibiotic treatment in patients with persistent symptoms and a history of Lyme disease. New England Journal of Medicine, 345(2), 85–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kourany, J. (2018). Adding to the tapestry. Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology, 10, p. 9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krupp, L. B., Hyman, L. G., Grimson, R., et al. (2003). Study and treatment of post Lyme disease (STOP-LD): A randomized double masked clinical trial. Neurology, 60, pp. 1923–1930.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1977). Objectivity, value judgement, and theory choice. In T. Kuhn (Ed.), The essential tension (pp. 320–329). University of Chicago Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lacey, H. (2017). Distinguishing between cognitive and social values. In K. Elliott & D. Steel (Eds.), Current Controversies in Values and Science (pp. 15–30). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lantos, P. M. (2011). Chronic Lyme disease: The controversies and the science. Expert Review of Anti-Infective Therapy, 9, pp. 787–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lantos, P. M., Rumbaugh, J., Bockenstedt, L. K., Falck-Ytter, Y. T., Aguero-Rosenfeld, M. E., Auwaerter, P. G., Baldwin, K., Bannuru, R. R., Belani, K. K., Bowie, W. R., Branda, J. A., et al. (2021). Clinical practice guidelines by the Infectious Diseases Society of America (IDSA), American Academy of Neurology (AAN), and American College of Rheumatology (ACR): 2020 guidelines for the prevention, diagnosis, and treatment of lyme disease. Arthritis & Rheumatology, 73, pp. 12–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Bihan, S., & Amadi, I. (2017). On epistemically detrimental dissent: contingent enabling factors versus stable difference-makers. Philosophy of Science, 84, pp. 1020–1030.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leuschner, A., & Fernández Pinto, M. (2021). How dissent on gender bias in academia affects science and society: Learning from the case of climate change denial. Philosophy of Science, 88, pp. 573–593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leuschner, A., & Fernández Pinto, M. (2022). Exploring the limits of dissent: The case of shooting bias. Synthese, 200, pp. 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2002). The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, D. (2016). Ontological choices and the value-free ideal. Erkenntnis, 81, pp. 1253–1272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lusk, G., & Elliott, K. (2022). Non-epistemic values and scientific assessment: an adequacy-for-purpose view. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 12, p. 35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maloney, E. L. (2016). Controversies in persistent (chronic) Lyme disease. Journal of Infusion Nursing, 39, pp. 369–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGarity, T., & Wagner, W. (2008). Bending science: How special interests corrupt public health research. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIlroy-Young, B., Öberg, G., & Leopold, A. (2021). The manufacturing of consensus: The struggle for epistemic authority in chemical risk evaluation. Environmental Science and Policy, 122, pp. 25–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKaughan, D. J., & Elliott, K. C. (2015). Introduction: Cognitive attitudes and values in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 53, pp. 57–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaels, D. (2008). Doubt Is Their Product: How Industry’s Assault on Science Threatens Your Health. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, B. (2013). When is consensus knowledge based? Distinguishing shared knowledge from mere agreement. Synthese, 190, pp. 1293–1316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, B. (2014). Catching the WAVE: The weight-adjusting account of values and evidence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 47, pp. 69–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, B. (2021). When is scientific dissent epistemically inappropriate? Philosophy of Science, 88, pp. 918–928.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, B., & Pinto, M. (2022). Epistemic equality: Distributive epistemic justice in the context of justification. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 32, pp. 173–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • NIH (National Institutes of Health). (2018). Lyme disease antibiotic treatment research. Retrieved October 1, 2022 from https://www.niaid.nih.gov/diseases-conditions/lyme-disease-antibiotic-treatment-research

  • O’Connor, C., & Weatherall, J. (2019). The Misinformation Age. Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N. (2019). Why Trust Science? Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oreskes, N., & Conway, E. (2010). Merchants of Doubt: How a Handful of Scientists Obscured the Truth on Issues from Tobacco Smoke to Global Warming. Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orman, N. (2021). AAAS Voices: Countering Science Misinformation. Retrieved February 19, 2023. https://www.aaas.org/news/misinformation?utm_campaign=Gadi&utm_source=AAAS&utm_medium=Twitter

  • Ottinger, G., & Cohen, B. (2011). Technoscience and environmental justice: Expert cultures in a grassroots movement. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pfeiffer, M. B. (2018). Lyme: The first epidemic of climate change. Island Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1963). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proctor, R. (2011). Golden holocaust: Origins of the cigarette catastrophe and the case for abolition. University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D. B., & Elliott, K. C. (2019). Value-entanglement and the integrity of scientific research. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 75, pp. 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolin, K. (2017). Scientific dissent and a fair distribution of epistemic responsibility. Public Affairs Quarterly, 31, pp. 209–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, S. A. (2021). Democratic values: A better foundation for public trust in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axz023

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanek, G., Wormser, G. P., Gray, J., & Strle, F. (2012). Lyme borreliosis. The Lancet, 379(9814), 461–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanev, R. (2017). Inductive Risk and Values in Composite Outcome Measures. In K. C. Elliott & T. Richards (Eds.), Exploring inductive risk: Case studies of values in science (pp. 171–191). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thacker, P. (2021). The covid-19 lab leak hypothesis: Did the media fall victim to a misinformation campaign? BMJ, 374, p. 1656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2010). Causation and biology: Stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 25, pp. 287–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • World Health Organization. (2021). Fighting misinformation about COVID-19, one click at a time. Retrieved February 19, 2023 from https://www.who.int/news-room/feature-stories/detail/fighting-misinformation-in-the-time-of-covid-19-one-click-at-a-time

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am very grateful for excellent suggestions I received on this paper from two anonymous reviewers for this journal. I also received helpful feedback from audiences at the workshop on Values in Science and Political Philosophy at Claremont McKenna College, the workshop on Engaging Ethics and Epistemology of Science at Leibniz Universität Hannover, the workshop on The Legacy of the Value-Free Ideal of Science at Uppsala University, and a reading group based at the Université de Montréal and the University of Calgary. Finally, I thank Philippe Stamenkovic and Adam Tamas Tuboly for their invitation to contribute to this collection of articles.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kevin C. Elliott.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has received compensation for a lecture on ethics for the Chlorine Institute, an industry trade association focused on safety and sustainability in the chlor-alkali industry. The author acknowledges that this could possibly affect his judgment about how to handle dissent in science, specifically in cases where industry is involved.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Elliott, K.C. Navigating dissent by managing value judgments: the case of Lyme disease. Synthese 202, 134 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04368-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04368-z

Keywords

Navigation