Truth pluralists say that there are many ways to be true. Cotnoir (2013a) has suggested a “uniquely pluralist response to the liar”. The basic idea is to maintain that, if a sentence says of itself that it is not true in a certain way, then that sentence is not apt to be true in that way, but is instead apt to be true in a different way. This is consistent with the basic tenets of truth pluralism, but it is an open question whether or not it is amenable to any actual pluralist theory.

The primary goal of this paper is to argue that Cotnoir’s proposal is amenable to form-based pluralism, rather than domain-based pluralism. Where domain-based pluralists say that sentences in different domains are apt to be true in different ways, form-based pluralists say that sentences of different logical forms are apt to be true in different ways. In Sect. 1, I argue (contra Cotnoir) that there are several serious obstacles in the way of domain-based pluralists who wish to endorse Cotnoir’s proposal. In Sect. 2, I argue that form-based pluralists (of at least one variety) can overcome these obstacles. My goal is not to defend this kind of pluralism or this pluralist response to the liar. Rather, it is to make progress towards such a solution, by showing how the form-based pluralist can overcome the difficulties facing domain-based pluralists. My conclusion is thus a conditional one: if we are to avoid the liar paradox in this way, then form-based pluralists are much better equipped to do so than domain-based pluralists.

The secondary goal is to argue that most, if not all, substantivists about truth should find form-based pluralism independently attractive. This is on two grounds. First, most if not all such theorists should agree that the relevant variety of form-based truth pluralism is extensionally adequate (Sect. 2.1). Second, most if not all such theorists independently stand to benefit from endorsing form-based pluralism (Sect. 2.2). A form-based pluralist solution to the liar is therefore no merely technical curiosity, but something in which substantivists about truth have a vested interest: insofar as the theory is independently attractive to substantivists, it would be a major boon to such theorists if form-based pluralism also provides a solution to the liar.

1 Cotnoir’s proposal

1.1 Pluralism: moderate and strong

Truth pluralism, as we’ll understand it here, is the view that there are many ways to be true; and, in particular, that claims of certain different kinds are apt to be true in different ways. That is, while claims of one kind (type-1 claims) are apt to be true in one way, claims of another kind (type-2 claims) are apt to be true in a different way.Footnote 1 We get different versions of the view depending inter alia on: (i) what different ways of being true there are; (ii) which different kinds of claim are apt to be true in different ways; and (iii) how we understand the relationship between truth as such and the different ways of being true. (i) and (ii) will be important later, but let’s start by thinking a little about (iii).

On (iii), pluralists divide into two families.Footnote 2 “Moderate” pluralists recognise the existence of a generic truth property, truth as such, for which all claims are apt. In this sense, they are monists about truth. However, possession of this generic property is grounded in, or realised by, or manifested by, or determined by, or in some other important metaphysical sense dependent on different properties for claims of different kinds. In this sense, they are also pluralists about truth. In a slogan, truth is “one and many” (Lynch, 2009). “Strong” pluralists, by contrast, do not recognise the existence of a generic truth property for which all claims are apt. The property of being true reduces to, or is constituted by, or is to be identified with different properties for claims of different kinds; and there is no further alethic property that these different claims have in common. In a slogan, truth is none and many. (It will be useful to have a way of talking that is neutral between moderate and strong pluralism, so let’s stipulate that “in virtue of” talk can be read in either a moderate or strong way. So we say both kinds of pluralist think that claims of different kinds are apt to be true in virtue of possessing different properties.)

I think it’s fair to say that, since these views have been distinguished, strong pluralists have been on the defensive. Moderate pluralists have advanced a battery of arguments for postulating a generic truth property, arguing that strong pluralists struggle to accommodate the truth of “mixed compounds” (logically complex claims composed of claims that are apt to be true in different ways), the validity of “mixed inferences” (arguments composed of claims that are apt to be true in different ways), the normative role of truth, or the expressive role of the truth predicate as a device for generalisation and endorsement.Footnote 3 Those sympathetic with strong pluralism have largely been preoccupied with trying to meet these challenges (or questioning whether moderate pluralists are any better off). The positive case for strong pluralism over moderate is usually limited to the idea that strong pluralism is more parsimonious (Ferrari et al., 2021, pp. 645–650): both strong and moderate pluralists postulate different ways of being true, but moderate pluralists also postulate a generic truth property. On this way of seeing things, moderate pluralists are guilty of little more than an unnecessary indulgence.

A salient exception comes from Cotnoir (2013a).Footnote 4 Cotnoir argues that strong pluralists are entitled to a “uniquely pluralist response to the liar” (Cotnoir, 2013a, p. 346). This is a bold conjecture, which needs to be taken seriously if we are to properly evaluate the credentials of the view. The liar paradox is among the most difficult and tenacious problems facing theories of truth. If strong pluralists have a solution, that’s a significant reason to favour strong pluralism as a theory of truth. (Whether it outweighs the putative shortcomings of the view, and whether this response is preferable to those responses available to its opponents, are of course further questions; but we need to know whether we can put this on the “pro” side of the scale before we can hope to see which way it tips.) Moreover, Cotnoir’s conjecture provides a bridge between two literatures that have historically been problematically isolated: that on the metaphysics of truth and that on the alethic paradoxes.

1.2 Strong pluralism and the liar

How does the “uniquely pluralist” response to the liar go? Suppose we accept all instances of schema (T):

(T) ‘p’ is true iff p

where ‘p’ is a schematic marker to be replaced with a declarative sentence and single-quotes are a device for turning a sentence into a singular term denoting that sentence.Footnote 5 We run into problems the moment we encounter a sentence that says of itself that it is not true, e.g., Liar = ‘Liar is not true’. By (T), Liar is true iff Liar is not true; contradiction quickly follows. We face the uncomfortable choice of somehow resisting this reasoning, learning to live with contradiction, or finding a principled way of restricting which instances of schema (T) we accept.

Truth pluralists, however, think that different claims are apt to be true in different ways. The pluralist can therefore maintain that each of these different ways of being true validates schema (T), but only for certain claims. That is, the pluralist can accept all instances of schema (TP):

(TP) If ‘p’ is apt to be true in virtue of being F, then ‘p’ is F iff p.

Now, providing that there is no generic way of being true, this creates an opportunity that Cotnoir exploits. Cotnoir’s proposal has two major components. The first, which will be our focus, is to maintain:

(Shiftiness) If a sentence S says of itself that it is not true in a certain way, then

S is not apt to be true in that way, but is instead apt to be true in a different way.Footnote 6

Shiftiness allows us to avoid contradiction because it is perfectly consistent to maintain that a sentence is not true in one way iff it is true in a different way (assuming that these different ways of being true are suitably independent). For example, suppose that the different ways of being true are T1, T2, etc. Then take LiarT1 = ‘LiarT1 is not T1’. By Shiftiness, it follows that LiarT1 is not apt to be true in virtue of being T1, but instead apt to be true in some other way; say, in virtue of being T2. By (TP), LiarT1 is T2 iff LiarT1 is not T1. As long as being T1 is neither necessary nor sufficient for being T2, there is no contradiction.Footnote 7

Shiftiness is not compatible with moderate pluralism, since such pluralists postulate a generic truth property for which all sentences are apt. A sentence that says of itself that it is not true in that way must be apt to be true in that way, if it is apt to be true at all. The moderate pluralist therefore faces the same uncomfortable choice everyone else faces when it comes to this generic truth property. It is precisely by denying the existence of any such generic truth property that strong pluralism is compatible with Shiftiness. Strong pluralists can therefore avoid the liar paradox in a way that moderate pluralists cannot. If this is right, then the moderate pluralist’s postulation of a generic truth property is no mere unnecessary indulgence, but outright lands them in contradiction.

(Note that, if the strong pluralist strategy fails, and a liar sentence concerning some local truth property leads to contradiction, this is as much a problem for the moderate pluralist as it is for the strong pluralist! It is just that it is not an additional problem for the moderate pluralist, given that she already has to deal with the problem when it comes to the generic truth property.)

As Cotnoir (2013a, pp. 347–348) discusses, the structure of his proposal is reminiscent of Tarski’s (1935/1956, 1944) hierarchical proposal. But I think Cotnoir’s is much more interesting, for reasons that Cotnoir does not mention. For Tarski, a truth predicate is a truth predicate for a language and Tarski chooses to focus on languages that are not “semantically closed”—that is, roughly, languages that do not contain their own truth predicates. It is easy to see that Shiftiness is true of sentences of those languages: since these languages do not contain their own truth predicates, any sentence (including a liar sentence) that uses such a truth predicate is not a sentence of the language to which the relevant truth predicate applies. But it does not follow that Shiftiness holds in general. On the contrary, Tarski clearly held that natural languages like English are semantically closed, and consequently give rise to the liar paradox. Tarski’s view seems to be that the concept of truth is simply incoherent; and the decision to focus on languages that are not semantically closed is intended as a directive for avoiding contradiction while employing this incoherent concept (Ray, 2018, pp. 702–706). Cotnoir’s proposal, while structurally similar, does not involve merely choosing to focus on languages in which the problem does not arise! Instead, Cotnoir’s proposal employs pluralist resources that are supposed to be motivated entirely independently of the liar.

1.3 Domain-based pluralism and the liar

Now, while Cotnoir’s proposal is consistent with the basic tenets of truth pluralism, we should still ask whether or not it is a proposal that any actual truth pluralist can accept. At the outset, we noted that we get different versions of the view depending on: (i) what different ways of being true there are, and (ii) which different kinds of claim are apt to be true in different ways. Shiftiness makes a claim about the way in which certain sentences—namely, liar sentences, sentences that say of themselves that they are not true in one way or another—are apt to be true. So, to see whether any pluralist can accept Shiftiness, we should ask what they have said about (ii).

On this, Cotnoir follows the mainstream in appealing to the notion of a domain of discourse.Footnote 8 The intuitive idea is reasonably clear. We are used to distinguishing ethical claims (‘Stealing is wrong’), mathematical claims (‘7 is prime’), aesthetic claims (‘That song rocks’), and so on, both from each other and from mundane descriptive claims like ‘The dog is hairy’. These claims belong to different domains of discourse: the ethical, the mathematical, the aesthetic, and so on. Philosophers often have different views about different domains. One could be a realist about things like dogs, for example, while being an expressivist about ethics, an error theorist about mathematics, and a subjectivist about aesthetics. According to what we will call domain-based pluralism, the way in which a particular claim is apt to be true is determined by the domain of discourse it is a part of.Footnote 9 For example, ethical claims may be apt to be true in a different way to mathematical claims, which are true in a different way to ordinary descriptive claims, and so on.

When Cotnoir argues that strong pluralists can avoid the liar, he is squarely focused on domain-based pluralism. He introduces truth pluralism thus:

“Pluralists endorse many truth predicates T1, …, Tn. Usually, each predicate is a truth predicate for a certain ‘domain of discourse’. […]

What does it mean to be a truth predicate for a domain? […] One such minimal constraint is the T-scheme:

(TS)⊢ Ti (⌜α⌝) ↔ α for all sentences α of domaini.” (Cotnoir, 2013a, p. 340)

And his proposal for avoiding the liar deploys the notion of a domain. Consider LiarT1 = ‘LiarT1 is not T1’. Cotnoir (2013a, p. 342) argues that deriving a contradiction from this sentence “depends crucially on the assumption that [LiarT1] is actually in domain1. But the pluralist, of course, is free to reject that [LiarT1] is in domain1.”Footnote 10 What about LiarT2 = ‘LiarT2 is not T2’? “Here again, the pluralist is free to reject that [LiarT2] is in domain2, but rather in, say, domain3. This process can continue…”.

(Let’s address a presentational awkwardness. In the above, Cotnoir’s discussion, his formulation of (TS), and his subscripting convention for truth predicates and domains may suggest that each truth predicate is a truth predicate for exactly one domain: ‘T1’ for domain1; ‘T2’ for domain2; etc. Later, however, he is explicit that “domains may share the same truth predicate.” (2013a, p. 347) This is the conventional picture—a domain-based pluralist may think that, say, moral claims and aesthetic claims are true in the same way—but it complicates Cotnoir’s proposal. If two domains, say domain1 and domain2, share a truth predicate, say ‘T1’, then it is not enough to avoid contradiction to deny that LiarT1 is in domain1. The pluralist needs to deny that LiarT1 is in domain1 or any other domain that shares the same truth predicate. Let’s take this amendment as read. With this in place, and modulo some presentational differences, what Cotnoir articulates is Shiftiness as implemented by a domain-based pluralist.)

However, domain-based pluralists are ill-equipped to endorse Shiftiness. To see this, note first that Shiftiness requires that there are infinitely many ways to be true, and in particular that there are infinitely many different liar sentences that are apt to be true in different ways. Suppose, for reductio, that there are just two ways to be true, T1 and T2, and consider two liar sentences: LiarT1 = ‘LiarT1 is not T1’ and LiarT2 = ‘LiarT2 is not T2’. It follows from Shiftiness that LiarT1 is apt to be true in virtue of being T2, while LiarT2 is apt to be true in virtue of being T1. By (TP): LiarT1 is T2 iff LiarT1 is not T1; and LiarT2 is T1 iff LiarT2 is not T2. So far, so consistent. But now consider a sentence that says of itself that it lacks both of these properties, which we can formulate, for example, by disjunction: LiarT1&T2 = ‘It is not the case that (LiarT1&T2 is T1 or LiarT1&T2 is T2)’. It follows from Shiftiness that LiarT1&T2 is not apt to be true in virtue of being T1 or in virtue of being T2; but since these are ex hypothesi the only two ways to be true, it must be apt to be true in one of these two ways, assuming it is apt to be true at all.Footnote 11 A contradiction. To maintain Shiftiness, we must postulate a third way of being true—call it T3—and say that LiarT1&T2 is apt to be true in virtue of being T3. But then we can use disjunction to formulate another sentence that says of itself that it does not possess any of these three properties: LiarT1&T2&T3 = ‘It is not the case that (LiarT1&T2&T3 is T1 or LiarT1&T2&T3 is T2 or LiarT1&T2&T3 is T3)’. To maintain Shiftiness, we will need to postulate a fourth way of being true. And so on ad infinitum.

A brief aside. Even if there are infinitely many ways to be true, if we accept infinitary disjunction, then there will still be a sentence that says of itself that it is not true in any of these infinitely many different ways: Liarω = ‘It is not the case that (Liarω is T1 or Liarω is T2 or …)’, where the ellipsis abbreviates an infinite disjunction of atomic sentences that ascribe each of the infinite different ways of being true to Liarω.Footnote 12 Cotnoir therefore proposes that the pluralist rejects infinitary disjunction, which he argues “we already have pluralism-independent (but paradox-motivated) reasons to reject.” (Cotnoir, 2013a, p. 339) This is the second major component of Cotnoir’s proposal, and it is the component that Cotnoir is primarily concerned to defend, apparently taking Shiftiness to be unproblematic. As such, I am going to grant, for the sake of argument, that we have good reason to reject infinitary disjunction.Footnote 13 My discussion focuses on Shiftiness instead.

Returning to our main thread: Shiftiness requires that there are infinitely many ways to be true. For the domain-based pluralist, the way in which a particular sentence is apt to be true is determined by its domain. So, Shiftiness requires that there are infinitely many domains of discourse. A first worry is that it is not at all obvious that there are infinitely many domains of discourse. In a related setting, Cook (2011, p. 628) suggests that “[t]here seem to be no good reasons for thinking that there are only finitely many distinct discourses”; but Wright (2017, p. 356) argues to the contrary that “our presumption should be in favour of […] a large but countably finite class”.

However, even granting that there are infinitely many domains of discourse, distinct domains can share a truth property, so there may still only be finitely many truth properties. Do we have any reason to think that there are in fact infinitely many? Here, we might profitably ask what pluralists have said about (i): what different ways of being true there are. Many domain-based pluralists are clear about what kinds of truth properties there are. According to “correspondence pluralists,” for example, the many ways of being true are all different ways of corresponding to reality.Footnote 14 Others maintain that, while corresponding to reality is one way of being true, other claims are true in some “anti-realist” or “non-representational” sense.Footnote 15 Yet others maintain that some claims are only true in a deflationary sense, while others are (also?) true in a more robust or substantive sense.Footnote 16 Beall (2013) has even suggested a kind of “deflated truth pluralism.” Pluralists are less often explicit about exactly how many local truth properties they endorse, but a quick perusal of the literature will verify that they only usually countenance a few such properties, almost always in single figures. (For example, in their book-length defences of the view, Edwards (2018b) and Lynch (2009) each only explicitly commits to two.) And the most detailed arguments given for domain-based pluralism do not suggest that the local truth properties will proliferate to any great extent, since they draw on binary distinctions between, e.g., mind-independent and mind-dependent entities, abstract and concrete entities, natural and non-natural entities, objective and projected entities, or sparse and abundant properties (Gamester, 2020). Even if a domain-based pluralist endorsed a thousand—or a hundred billion!—truth properties, this would be nowhere near enough for Shiftiness; but as things stand we have no reason to think they will endorse more than a handful. It is hard to imagine what these infinitely many domain-specific truth properties would look like.

However, even granting that there are infinitely many domains of discourse and infinitely many ways of being true, Shiftiness requires that infinitely many different liar sentences are apt to be true in different ways, which for the domain-based pluralist means that infinitely many different liar sentences must fall into different domains. But there is no reason to think that any different liar sentences will fall into different domains, and some reason to think they will not. Domain-based pluralists have rarely been clear about how they intend to individuate domains, but the general idea seems to be that they are individuated by their subject matter: the kind of thing they are about.Footnote 17 Thus those sentences about mathematical entities constitute the mathematical domain; those sentences about ethical entities constitute the ethical domain; and so on. While different liar sentences will concern different truth properties, they are nonetheless all about the same type of thing—namely, truth properties—and thus would seem to all fall into the same domain. (Just as ‘Torture is wrong’ and ‘Charity is right’ concern different properties, but nonetheless concern the same type of property—namely, ethical properties—and thus fall into the same domain.)

Finally, even granting that there are infinitely many domains and infinitely many ways of being true and that infinitely many liar sentences fall into different domains, all it takes is for one liar sentence to fall into the wrong domain and contradiction follows: if LiarT1 is in domain1;Footnote 18 or LiarT2 is in domain2; or LiarT3 is in domain3; and so on ad infinitum. As we saw above, Cotnoir says that the domain-based pluralist is “free to reject” that LiarT1 is in domain1. But it is not up to the pluralist to decide what domain a sentence falls into. So, for all that has been said, we have no reason to think that Shiftiness is true of any particular liar sentence, let alone that it is true of all of them. And remember there are infinitely many! It is hard to imagine what assurance the domain-based pluralist might be able to give us that Shiftiness holds across the board.

All this suggests that domain-based pluralists are ill-equipped to endorse Shiftiness and so to avoid the liar in the way Cotnoir suggests: they typically endorse very few—certainly finitely many—truth properties; their liar sentences are unlikely to fall into different domains, and so (by their lights) are unlikely to be apt to be true in different ways; and, even setting all this aside, we have no reason to think Shiftiness would be true of any particular liar sentence, let alone all of them.

2 Form-based pluralism

Domain-based pluralists maintain that the way in which a particular sentence is apt to be true is determined by its domain of discourse. Form-based pluralists, by contrast, maintain that the way in which a particular sentence is apt to be true is determined by its logical form.Footnote 19 Having argued that domain-based pluralists face serious difficulties when it comes to endorsing Shiftiness, I now turn to arguing that form-based pluralists, of at least one variety, are able to overcome these difficulties.

Suppose that the atomic sentences ‘snow is white’ and ‘grass is green’ are each apt to be true in virtue of corresponding to a fact. And suppose that a conjunction is true iff its conjuncts are true. It follows that ‘snow is white and grass is green’ is true iff ‘snow is white’ corresponds to a fact and ‘grass is green’ corresponds to a fact. And suppose, finally, that ‘snow is white’ and ‘grass is green’ each corresponds to a fact. So, the conjunction is true. Now we can ask: is it true in the same way as its conjuncts? That is, does the conjunction itself also correspond to a fact? As I think of it, the central intuition driving form-based pluralism is that this is surplus to requirements. It is enough that the conjunction conjoins two sentences each of which corresponds to a fact; it does not need to correspond to a fact itself. But if the conjunction is not apt to be true in virtue of corresponding to a fact, then it is not apt to be true in the same way as its atomic components, and so must be apt to be true in a different way (very roughly, in virtue of combining, in the right kind of way, sentences that are true). Thus a logically complex sentence is, in virtue of being logically complex, apt to be true in a different way to its atomic components. This is form-based pluralism. Analogous reasoning applies to sentences of other logical complexity, whatever property (or properties) we say their atomic components are apt for.

Of course, there may be advantages to saying that complex sentences are true in the same way as their atomic components that outweigh this intuitive case. But in fact we will see that, for most if not all substantivists about truth, this commitment is independently problematic (Sect. 2.2). Form-based pluralism should therefore be independently attractive to substantivists about truth. And of course maintaining that all sentences are apt to be true in the same way, regardless of logical complexity, blocks Shiftiness, and so commits you to finding some other way of dealing with the liar paradox. It would therefore be a major boon for substantivists if form-based pluralism also provided a solution to the liar via Shiftiness.

How might form-based pluralism be amenable to Shiftiness? When thinking about the logical form of a sentence, it’s useful to think about two things. First, the logical connectives it uses and in particular its main connective: the latter determines whether the sentence is a negation, a disjunction, a conjunction, a conditional, etc. Second, its order of complexity: letting atomic sentences be 0th-order, the order of complexity of a logically complex sentence is one greater than its highest-order component. Thus a first-order negation is the negation of an atomic sentence; conjoining a first-order negation to an atomic sentence gets us a second-order conjunction; etc. Since any declarative sentence can be embedded in a negation, disjunction, conjunction, etc., there is no upper limit on how high the order of complexity of a sentence may be (so long as it remains finite, given our prohibition on infinitary compounds). So, assuming that a sentence’s logical form is determined, in part, by its order of complexity, there are infinitely many logical forms that a sentence may have.

This suggests a two-step strategy for endorsing Shiftiness. First, maintain that sentences of different orders of complexity are apt to be true in different ways.Footnote 20 Second, maintain that any sentence that says of itself that it is not true in the way in which sentences of a certain order of complexity are apt to be true is of a different order of complexity to those sentences. In what follows, we take these steps in turn.

2.1 Introducing the view

Our first step is to maintain that sentences of different orders of complexity are apt to be true in different ways. Is it possible to spell this out in a plausible way? Yes. Most theorists accept that a conjunction is true iff its conjuncts are true; that a disjunction is true iff at least one of its disjuncts is true; that a negation is true iff its negand is not true; and so on. As I’ll now show, it follows from these recursive principles that, for sentences of any given logical form, there is a property that is co-extensive with truth for all and only the sentences of that logical form. The pluralist can therefore endorse these properties as her truth properties, and anyone who accepts the principles will be committed to the extensional adequacy of this theory.

To fix ideas, let’s focus on a simple language, consisting of: singular terms ‘a’, ‘b’, etc.; one-place predicates ‘F’, ‘G’, etc.; negation ‘ ~ ’; and conjunction ‘&’. In this language, all atomic sentences (or “atoms”) are of the form ‘Fa’. For brevity, let’s say that a sentence of the form ‘Fa’ is TA iff there exists some x such that ‘a’ denotes x and ‘F’ is true of x. We can then say:

  1. (i)

    An atom φ is true iff φ is TA.

  2. (ii)

    ⌜ ~ φ⌝ is true iff φ is not true.

  3. (iii)

    ⌜φ & ψ⌝ is true iff φ is true and ψ is true.

The rough idea is then as follows. Any sentence is made up of logically atomic sentences combined in a certain kind of way using logical connectives. From (i)–(iii), it follows that whether or not a sentence is true is determined by how it combines its atomic constituents (that is, its logical form) and how TA is distributed among its atomic constituents. In the limit case, a sentence might just be an atomic sentence that is TA. Or it could negate an atomic sentence that is not TA. Or it could conjoin an atomic sentence that is TA with another atomic sentence that is TA. Or it could conjoin the negation of an atomic sentence that is not TA with an atomic sentence that is TA. Or it could conjoin the conjunction of the negation of an atomic sentence that is not TA and an atomic sentence that is TA with the negation of an atomic sentence that is not TA. And so on. For any given logical form, all and only the true sentences of that form will combine a set of atomic sentences with the relevant distribution of TA in the way that sentences of that form combine them. Thus, the property of combining a set of atomic sentences with that distribution of TA in that way will be co-extensive with truth for all and only the sentences of the given logical form. For instance, according to (i)–(iii), each of the properties listed in Table 1 will be co-extensive with truth for sentences of the given logical form (where ‘p’, ‘q’, etc. represent atomic constituents).

Table 1 Table listing the properties that are co-extensive with truth for sentences of the given logical forms (where ‘p’, ‘q’, and ‘r’ represent the logically atomic constituents of said sentences)

Now, co-extensiveness is not sufficient for metaphysical dependence, of any of the kinds endorsed by moderate pluralists, let alone reduction or identity, as per strong pluralism. So, commitment to (i)–(iii) does not hereby commit you to form-based pluralism in either its moderate or strong guises. But it does commit you to the extensional adequacy of any variety of form-based pluralism that maintains that sentences of the relevant logical forms are apt to be true in virtue of possessing the relevant properties. It is this kind of form-based pluralism that we will be interested in for the rest of this paper. For present purposes, we will work with the intuitive characterisation of the view just given; I provide a precise characterisation in the Appendix.

Now, the above discussion is obviously focused on an incredibly simple language. But the key observation—that, for any given logical form, there is a property that is necessarily co-extensive with truth for all and only the sentences of that form—will hold as long as we endorse recursive connections between the truth of a logically complex sentence and the truth of its components, like (ii) and (iii). In particular, while I worked with a particular conception of what it is for an atomic sentence to be true that was only suitable for sentences of a particular form, which I labelled ‘TA’, we could work with any other conception instead.

For example, suppose that you are a monist about truth, and in particular that you think that truth always consists in corresponding to a fact. It follows a fortiori that an atomic sentence is true iff it corresponds to a fact. It then follows from (ii) that a first-order negation is true iff it negates an atomic sentence that does not correspond to a fact; from (iii) that a first-order conjunction is true iff it conjoins two atomic sentences, each of which corresponds to a fact; from (ii) and (iii) that the negation of a first-order conjunction is true iff it negates the conjunction of two atomic sentences x and y such that it’s not the case that x corresponds to a fact and y corresponds to a fact; and so on. These are the properties listed in the table above, if we interpret ‘is TA’ as standing for corresponds to a fact. Analogous reasoning would run given any other monistic conception of truth.

Alternatively, suppose you are a pluralist about truth, and in particular that you think that sentences in domain1 are true in virtue of being T1 and sentences in domain2 are true in virtue of being T2 (and all atomic sentences are either in domain1 or domain2). It follows that an atomic sentence φ is true iff (φ is in domain1 and φ is T1) or (φ is in domain2 and φ is T2). It then follows from (ii) that a first-order negation is true iff it negates an atomic sentence x such that it is not the case that ((x is in domain1 and x is T1) or (x is in domain2 or x is T2)); from (iii) that a first-order conjunction is true iff it conjoins two atomic sentences x and y such that ((x is in domain1 and x is T1) or (x is in domain2 and x is T2)) and ((y is in domain1 and y is T1) or (y is in domain2 and y is T2)); and so on. These are the properties listed in the table, if we interpret ‘TA’ disjunctively, as standing for a disjunction of the domain-specific truth properties restricted to the relevant domains. Analogous reasoning would run given any other (non-form-based) pluralistic conception of truth.

Our characterisation of form-based pluralism can therefore afford to be schematic in two respects: first, on how we should interpret ‘TA’; second, on exactly which recursive principles like (ii) and (iii) we endorse. You can fill in those details however you like. Whatever it in fact is that the truth of a logically atomic sentence consists in, including those not of the simple “singular-term-plus-predicate” form—that is, however we should in fact interpret ‘TA’—if we endorse some recursive principles like (ii) and (iii) for logically complex sentences, then it follows that, for any given logical form, there is a property that is co-extensive with truth for all and only the sentences of that form. I therefore take this observation, and thus the extensional adequacy of the relevant kinds of form-based pluralism, to be largely uncontroversial; or, at least, no more controversial than recursive principles like (ii) and (iii). In this sense, form-based pluralism is a highly non-revisionary theory of truth.

The controversial element of form-based pluralism will be the claim that truth is grounded in or reduces to these properties for sentences of different logical forms. Even then, I’m unsure to what extent moderate form-based pluralism will be controversial. For example, the relationship between the truth of a conjunction and the truth of its conjuncts is often thought to be a paradigm case of grounding. But it is primarily strong form-based pluralism that we are interested in, and the reduction claim is obviously much more controversial. The question we’re interested in here is thus whether this controversial claim might come with a substantial pay-off with respect to the liar paradox. (Note that, insofar as strong form-based pluralism is extensionally adequate, if Shiftiness turns out not to hold, and the view is hereby inconsistent, then this is a problem for everyone! It is just not an additional problem for non-strong-form-based-pluralists, who already have to find some other way to deal with the liar paradox.)

2.2 Independent benefits of form-based pluralism

Not only is form-based pluralism extensionally non-revisionary, but most if not all substantive theories of truth stand to benefit from it, independently of the liar paradox. First, realist theories of truth characteristically postulate “truth-makers”: entities that make sentences true. As a placeholder, let’s suppose that truth-makers are facts.Footnote 21 For example, ‘this cup is blue’ is made true by the fact that this cup is blue. Now, if each true sentence requires its own truth-maker, then in addition to atomic facts like the fact that this cup is blue, it looks like we will need to postulate negative facts like the fact that this cup is not a hippo and disjunctive facts like the fact that this cup is either blue or a hippo, to account for the truth of logically complex sentences. Such logically complex facts strike many as unacceptably mysterious and promiscuous (after all, any true sentence entails infinitely many true disjunctions). Bertrand Russell (1918/2010, p. 42) claims to have “nearly produced a riot” by arguing for negative facts in a lecture at Harvard in 1914. To avoid postulating negative facts, philosophers have postulated exotic entities like totality facts (Armstrong, 2004) or even denied that there are any negative truths (Mumford, 2007). Even Barker and Jago (2012, p. 126), while defending the existence of negative facts, deny that there are any disjunctive facts, and so “do not think that there is a fact corresponding to every true sentence.” But there is no need to postulate logically complex facts if we restrict the truth-making claim to atomic sentences and embrace form-based pluralism (David, 1994, pp. 119–124). If a first-order negation is true in virtue of negating an atomic sentence that does not have a truth-maker, then it need not itself be made true by a (negative) fact. Similarly, if a first-order disjunction is true in virtue of disjoining an atom x and an atom y such that either x or y has a truth-maker, then it need not be made true by a (disjunctive) fact itself. This was the idea embraced, to a greater or lesser extent, by the logical atomists; indeed, this insight has been referred to as “[t]he glory of logical atomism” (Mulligan et al., 1984, p. 289).Footnote 22

Second, anti-realist theories of truth—such as coherentist, pragmatist, and epistemic conceptions of truth—characteristically entail that all truths are knowable (Künne, 2003, pp. 20–32, 375–452). This notoriously runs into “Fitch’s Paradox,” which demonstrates that, given very plausible assumptions, the claim that all truths are knowable entails the absurd claim that all truths are known (Brogaard & Salerno, 2019). Suppose that all truths are knowable. And suppose, for reductio, that there is an unknown truth p, that is, that the following conjunction is true: p and it is not known that p. Since this conjunction is true, it must be knowable. But, plausibly, this conjunction cannot be known. Plausibly, if you know a conjunction, you know both its conjuncts. So, if you know this conjunction, you would both know that p and know that it is not known that p. But if you know the first conjunct, it’s not possible to know the second: if you know that p, then it’s not the case that it is not known that p; so, you can’t know that it is not known that p (since knowledge is factive). But if this conjunction cannot be known, then ex hypothesi it cannot be true. By reductio, then, there are no unknown truths.

However, Michael Bench-Capon has argued in unpublished work that this worry disappears if we restrict our anti-realist theory of truth, by denying that a conjunction needs to be true in the same way as its conjuncts.Footnote 23 Let’s suppose that our anti-realist theory of truth—as a placeholder, call it provability—applies to both ‘p’ and ‘it is not known that p’.Footnote 24 By assumption, then, ‘p’ and ‘it is not known that p’ are each true, and so provable (and so knowable). But it does not follow that they are jointly provable (and so jointly knowable). In general, that it is possible that p and possible that q does not entail that it is possible that p and q: there may be possible p-worlds and possible q-worlds, but no overlap between the two. And that is the case here: ‘p’ and ‘it is not known that p’ are both provable, but the possible worlds in which it is proven that p obviously do not overlap with the possible worlds in which it is proven that it is not known that p—this, indeed, is the lesson of Fitch’s Paradox, since if either conjunct were proven it would be known, meaning the other cannot be known, and so cannot be proven. So, the conjunction ‘p and it is not known that p’ is not provable. But if we say that the conjunction is apt to be true, not in virtue of being provable, but in virtue of conjoining a sentence that is provable with another sentence that is provable, then it can nonetheless be true. As such, there’s no contradiction in assuming that there is an unknown atomic claim, even if all atomic claims are knowable.

Finally, suppose one is a (non-form-based) pluralist about truth: type-1 claims are apt to be true in virtue of being T1 while type-2 claims are apt to be true in virtue of being T2. Suppose that ‘Fido is hairy’ is type-1 and ‘Fido is evil’ is type-2, and both are true. So ‘Fido is hairy and evil’ is true. But in virtue of what is this conjunction true? We cannot say that the conjunction is true in the same way as its conjuncts, as there may not be any local truth property shared by both its conjuncts. This is the “problem of mixed conjunctions,” one version of the broader “problem of mixed compounds”.Footnote 25 Again, this problem disappears if we restrict this pluralism to atomic claims and embrace form-based pluralism, since then we deny that the conjunction is true in the same way as either of its conjuncts. Instead, ‘Fido is hairy and evil’ is true in virtue of conjoining a type-1 atom that is T1 with a type-2 atom that is T2. Similar reasoning applies to other logical compounds. This is why several domain-based pluralists are also form-based pluralists.Footnote 26

Form-based pluralism thus provides solutions to long-standing problems for realist, anti-realist, and pluralist theories of truth. And most, perhaps all, substantivist theories of truth fall into one of these three families. Since form-based pluralism is already extensionally adequate, this should make the view independently attractive to (most, if not all)Footnote 27 substantivists about truth. Of course, I have not argued that adopting form-based pluralism is the best, let alone the only, possible response to the above worries (though I am inclined to think that it is). It may be possible to find an alternative solution. But the large literature on these problems, along with the fact that many already endorse the form-based pluralist solution, suggests that finding a viable alternative is no mean feat. Since substantivists independently stand to benefit from form-based pluralism, they have a vested interest in also being able to hereby avoid the liar paradox.

2.3 Form-based pluralism and the liar

Form-based pluralists are much better equipped to endorse Cotnoir’s proposed solution to the liar than domain-based pluralists. Our first worry for domain-based pluralists was that it is not obvious that there are infinitely main domains of discourse. But it is obvious that there are infinitely many logical forms (where logical form is individuated in terms of order of complexity as well as main connective). Our second worry was that domain-based pluralists typically only endorse a handful of different ways in which a claim can be true. But form-based pluralists, of the kind articulated above, endorse infinitely many different ways in which a claim can be true. (And this proposal is, I have stressed, extensionally non-revisionary.)

Our third worry was that it is not obvious that any liar sentences will fall into different domains. But it is obvious that certain liar sentences will have different logical forms. Consider the following liar sentences, which concern the first three properties implicit in (i)–(iii) above:

(LiarA):

It is not the case that LiarA is an atom that is TA.

(LiarB):

It is not the case that LiarB negates a sentence x such that x is an atom that is not TA.

(LiarC):

It is not the case that LiarC conjoins a sentence x and a sentence y such that x is an atom that is TA and y is an atom that is TA.

These sentences are clearly of different logical forms.

Our fourth worry was that we have been given no reason to think that Shiftiness is true of any particular liar sentence in the domain-based pluralist setting. But Shiftiness clearly is true of at least some of the form-based pluralist’s liar sentences. Consider, again, LiarA. This sentence says of itself that it does not have the property in virtue of which only atomic sentences are true. And LiarA is not an atomic sentence. So, Shiftiness is true of LiarA. Similar reasoning applies to LiarB and LiarC: LiarB concerns the property in virtue of which only first-order negations are true, and LiarB is not a first-order negation; LiarC concerns the property in virtue of which only first-order conjunctions are true, and LiarC is not a first-order conjunction. So, Shiftiness is true of LiarB and LiarC too.

This is progress! We are now much closer to being able to endorse Cotnoir’s “uniquely pluralist” response to the liar. The question we are left with is whether we have any reason to think that this pattern will generalise, such that Shiftiness holds across the board.

As I say, I will not attempt a full defence of the strong form-based pluralist response to the liar here. But I think we do have some reason to think that this pattern will generalise. Recall that, for the form-based pluralist, a sentence is true in virtue of (i) how it combines its atomic constituents, and (ii) how TA is distributed among its atomic constituents. Canonically, the characterisation of how TA needs to be distributed among its atomic constituents will mirror the logical form of the sentence itself. A first-order negation, for example, negates an atom that is not TA. A first-order conjunction conjoins two atoms, x and y, such that x is TA and y is TA. A sentence of the form ‘p ∨ (q & ~ r)’ is true iff ‘p’ is TA or (‘q’ is TA andr’ is not TA). This follows from the “disquotational” nature of the recursive clauses. So, a sentence that ascribes one of these truth properties will be at least as complex as the sentences that are apt to be true in that way. So, a sentence that says of itself that it is not true in some way will be more complex than the sentences that are apt to be true in that way.Footnote 28 If this is true in general, then Shiftiness is true, and the strong form-based pluralist can avoid the liar.

One worry for this line of argument arises from the following two-step procedure. First, we define a new predicate thus:

T~1::

For any x, x is T~1 iffdef x negates a sentence y such that y is an atom that is not TA.

Second, we use this new predicate to formulate a liar sentence:

(LiarT~1):

LiarT~1 is not T~1.

Like LiarB, this sentence says of itself that it does not have the property in virtue of which first-order negations are apt to be true. But unlike LiarB, this sentence is—on the surface, at least—a first-order negation. If so, then Shiftiness is not true of LiarT~1, and contradiction surely follows.

In response, it is worth noting that the two-step structure of this problem can be exploited to pose problems for most if not all substantive theories of truth. In particular, it can be used to reinstate the problems to which we saw form-based pluralism provides a solution in the previous subsection. There, we noted that the following logically complex claims pose problems for substantivists:

  1. (1)

    This cup is not a hippo.

  2. (2)

    This cup is either blue or a hippo.

  3. (3)

    p and it is not known that p.

  4. (4)

    This dog is hairy and evil.

(1) and (2) pose problems for realist theories; (3) for anti-realist theories; and (4) for pluralist theories. We saw that, by embracing form-based pluralism, the substantivist can deny that these logically complex claims are true in the same way as their atomic components, and thus solve the problems to which these problems give rise.

However, now suppose that we define four new predicates thus:

Noppo::

For any x, x is noppo iffdef x is not a hippo.

Blorpo::

For any x, x is blorpo iffdef x is either blue or a hippo.

Noknowtrue::

p’ is noknowtrue iffdef p and it is not known that p.

Haivil::

For any x, x is haivil iffdef x is hairy and x is evil.

We can then use these new predicates to formulate the following superficially atomic sentences:

  1. (1*)

    This cup is noppo.

  2. (2*)

    This cup is blorpo.

  3. (3*)

    p’ is noknowtrue.

  4. (4*)

    This dog is haivil.

(1*)–(4*) are equivalent to (1)–(4). But since they are atomic, the form-based pluralist solutions to the problems posed by (1)–(4) do not apply to (1*)–(4*). The problems posed by (1)–(4) are thus reinstated: the realist, it seems, needs to postulate mysterious and promiscuous facts to explain the truth of (1*) and (2*); the anti-realist is committed to saying that (3*) is knowable if true, which reinstates Fitch’s Paradox; and it is unclear in what way (4*) will be true by the pluralist’s lights. Substantivists will therefore be forced to find an alternative solution to these long-standing problems. Insofar as it is not clear that there is a viable alternative, as noted at the end of the previous subsection, this is a problem.

Substantivists about truth therefore have a vested interest in responding to problems established via this kind of two-step structure quite independently of the liar paradox. This provides a kind of “companions in guilt” response to the problem posed by LiarT~1. If we assume that substantivism about truth is otherwise viable, then (pending some other solution to the problems posed by (1)–(4), of course) this involves the assumption that substantivists are able to respond to the two-step structure when it is used to pose problems via (1*)–(4*). Presumably, then, the form-based pluralist can avail themselves of this response when the two-step structure is used to pose problems via LiarT~1.

To illustrate, one plausible response to the problems posed by (1*)–(4*) is to maintain that the surface form of these apparently atomic sentences masks their underlying logical form. By stipulation, ‘this cup is noppo’ just means that this cup is not a hippo; so, it is plausible that the underlying logical form of this sentence is a negation. Parallel reasoning applies to (2*)–(4*). If so, then (1*)–(4*) do not pose any problems distinct from (1)–(4) to which, we have seen, form-based pluralism provides a solution. By the same token, it is plausible that the underlying logical form of LiarT~1 is the same as LiarB, namely:

(LiarT~1):

It is not the case that LiarT~1 negates a sentence x such that x is an atom that is not TA.

If so, then despite its surface form, LiarT~1 is not a first-order negation, and so does not constitute a counterexample to Shiftiness.

Perhaps this response is unsatisfactory. But the point is that, unless substantivists have some such response to the problems established via this two-step structure, then they are independently in trouble. And if they do have such a response, such as the one floated above, then the form-based pluralist can avail themselves of this response too.

As I say, this does not constitute anything like a full defence of the form-based pluralist response to the liar. My goal in this paper has been more modest: to make progress towards such a solution by demonstrating how form-based pluralism is able to overcome the difficulties faced by domain-based pluralism. Having shown this, I conclude that, if we are to embrace the “uniquely pluralist response to the liar” suggested by Cotnoir, then form-based pluralism is the way to do it. Nor is this form-based solution to the liar a mere technical curiosity, since form-based pluralism should be independently attractive to substantivists about truth: it is extensionally adequate and provides solutions to a variety of long-standing problems facing substantivist theories of truth. I thus conclude that substantivists about truth have a vested interest in this solution to the liar.