Skip to main content
Log in

Compact spaces and privileged times; what the video game asteroids can teach us about the present

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The A-Theory of time has long struggled with the results of special relativity. One proposed solution is to stipulate the existence of a physically or metaphysically privileged frame which defines the global present for all observers. Recently this proposal has cropped up in literature on spatially closed universes (SCUs) which seem to naturally instantiate such structures. This paper examines the privileged frame proposal through the lens of SCUs, arguing that even in these space-times which seem overwhelmingly friendly to A-theoretic accounts the theory face insurmountable challenges.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are a number of different ways this can be cashed out, ranging from theories which hold that all past, present and future events exist but only present objects are ‘metaphysically real’ (Moving Spotlight), that the present converts a non-existing future into an existing past (Growing Block), or that only the present exists (Presentism). On all accounts it is critical that the present be metaphysically distinct from the past and future such that it possesses the property of being ‘now’. (Emery et al., 2020).

  2. None of these are necessary properties of such universes. Time could also be circular, for example, or space curved. For this paper, however, I follow the topologies used by previous authors including Weeks (2001), Peters (1983), and Luminet (2009)

  3. It should be noted here that the sudden discontinuity in x-coordinates is an artifact of the metric we are using, and is no more significant than the fact that people standing on the line of zero longitude on our own planet seem to be able to step from 0 to 360.

  4. I am hesitant to use this language as it implies there is something special about the points of identification within the universe. Recall, however, that this is a remnant of the metric being used, and the location of the discontinuity is a matter of convenience and choice rather than a real break in the world.

  5. It is worth noting that even though we have a system with significant restrictions on the Cauchy surfaces available, there are still multiple viable Cauchy surfaces for Alice’s frame. ‘Wavy’ surfaces, for example, are still valid solutions provided they never have an angle greater than 45 from the xc direction.

  6. This is in contrast with theories like cosmic time which, in some cases, attempt to define a universal present by methods like the statistical averaging of galactic motion, or the mean motion of the cosmic background radiation (Bourne, 2004; Swinburne, 2007).

  7. Many thanks to a reviewer who pointed out that in the presence of generic curvature radar synchronisation often does remain useful as demonstrated by Perlick (2008).

  8. It is worth noting that there does exist some literature within physics on our ability to determine large-scale topological features using local properties, but most of it focus on orientability (Bielińska & Read, 2023) or mapping the cosmic background radiation (Gomero, Mota, & Reboucas, 2016).

  9. This objection has also been raised for cosmic time, which suffers similar weaknesses (Read & Qureshi-Hurst, 2021).

  10. There are other types of cosmic time which get used in the literature. See Smeenk (2013) for a good overview. Here I am using Swinburne’s (2007) one, however, because it is simple, easy to intuit, and clearly demonstrates the property I am trying to highlight.

References

  • Anderson, R., Vetharaniam, I., & Stedman, G. E. (1998). Conventionality of synchronisation, gauge dependence and test theories of relativity. Physics Reports, 295(3–4), 93–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arfaei, H., & Kamani, D. (1999). Mixed branes interaction in compact space-time. Nuclear Physics B, 561(1–2), 57–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bielińska, M., & Read, J. (2023). Testing spacetime orientability. Foundations of Physics, 53(1), 8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourne, C. (2004). Becoming inflated. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55(1), 107–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2008). ’Finding “Real” time in quantum mechanics. In W. L. Craig & Q. Smith (Eds.), Einstein, relativity and absolute simultaneity (pp. 50–72). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2017). What makes time special? Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cornish, N. J., Spergel, D. N., Starkman, G. D., & Komatsu, E. (2004). Constraining the topology of the universe. Physical Review Letters, 92(20), 201302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, W. L. (2013). Time and the metaphysics of relativity (Vol. 84). Springer

  • Di Valentino, E., Melchiorri, A., & Silk, J. (2019). Planck evidence for a closed universe and a possible crisis for cosmology. Nature Astronomy, 1–8.

  • Emery, N., Markosian, N., & Sullivan, M. (2020). Time. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2020 ed.). Meta- physics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2020/entries/time/.

  • Friedman, M. (1986). Foundations of space-time theories: Relativistic physics and philosophy of science. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. (1949). An example of a new type of cosmological solutions of Einstein’s field equations of gravitation. Reviews of Modern Physics, 21(3), 447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gomero, G. I., Mota, B., & Reboucas, M. J. (2016). Limits of the circles-in-the-sky searches in the determination of cosmic topology of nearly flat universes. Physical Review D, 94(4), 043501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A. (1969). Simultaneity by slow clock transport in the special theory of relativity. Philosophy of Science, 36(1), 5–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Havas, P. (1987). Simultaneity, conventialism, general covariance, and the special theory of relativity. General Relativity and Gravitation, 19, 435–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ingram, D., & Tallant, J. (2018). Presentism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2018 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/presentism/

  • Ismael, J. (2016). From physical time to human time. Cosmological and psychological time (pp. 107–124). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jammer, M. (2006). Concepts of simultaneity: From antiquity to einstein and beyond. JHU Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Landau, L. D., & Lifshitz, E. M. (1951). Classical theory of fields. Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee. (2019). Simultaneity in closed flat spacetime. Unpublished Draft .

  • Luminet, J.-P. (2009). Time, topology and the twin paradox. arXiv preprint arXiv:0910.5847 .

  • Malament, D. (1977). Causal theories of time and the conventionality of simultaneity. Noûs, 11, 293–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. (2013). Presentism, eternalism, and the growing block. Philosophia Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, J. (1992). Philosophy of space and time. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perlick, V. (2008). On the radar method in general-relativistic spacetimes. Astrophysics and Space Science Library, 349, 131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, P. (1983). Periodic boundary conditions in special relativity. American Journal of Physics, 51(9), 791–795.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1972). The notion of the present. The study of time (pp. 320–323). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Time and physical geometry. The Journal of Philosophy, 64(8), 240–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Read, J., & Qureshi-Hurst, E. (2021). Getting tense about relativity. Synthese, 198(9), 8103–8125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rebouças, M. J. (2009). Constraints on dark energy and cosmic topology. International Journal of Modern Physics A, 24(9), 1625–1630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1951). Philosophical significance of relativity. Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, 289–311.

  • Rizzi, G., Ruggiero, M. L., & Serafini, A. (2004). Synchronization gauges and the principles of special relativity. Foundations of Physics, 34(12), 1835–1887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savitt, S. F. (2000). There’s no time like the present (in minkowski spacetime). Philosophy of Science, 67, 563-S574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smeenk, C. (2013). Time in cosmology. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2007). Cosmic simultaneity. Einstein, relativity and absolute simultaneity, 244.

  • Torrengo, G. (2017). Feeling the passing of time. The Journal of Philosophy, 114(4), 165–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weeks, J. R. (2001). The twin paradox in a closed universe. The American Mathematical Monthly, 108(7), 585–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yourgrau, P. (1991). The disappearance of time: Kurt gödel and the idealistic tradition in philosophy. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Craig Callender for his help in refining this paper, and to the anonymous reviewer who gave such helpful and detailed feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ann C. Thresher.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of Interest

There are no potential conflicts of interest in this paper, nor did any research involve human or animal participants. I further certify that I have no affiliation with, or involvement in any organi- sation or entity with any financial interest or non-financial interest in the subject matter or materials discussed in this manuscript.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Thresher, A.C. Compact spaces and privileged times; what the video game asteroids can teach us about the present. Synthese 202, 161 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04325-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04325-w

Keywords

Navigation