Skip to main content
Log in

Know-how and why self-regulation will not go away

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the 1940s, Gilbert Ryle argued that knowing how to do something is not just a matter of being well-regulated but also a matter of self-regulation. Ryle appears to have thought that know-how requires self-regulation in both a backward-looking and forward-looking sense, but both ideas run counter to ordinary intuitions about know-how. The basic idea behind self-regulation, undertaking trials and adjusting to feedback, is captured by the “law of effect.” Daniel Dennett has argued that the “law of effect will not go away”. After updating Dennett’s “Tower of Generate-and-Test” through a broad survey of the empirical literature on learning, I identify a Rylean intuition about intelligence and argue that self-regulation in a forward-looking sense is necessary for know-how.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This distinguishes my project from that of Bäckström and Gustafsson, who seek to describe the role self-regulation plays in Ryle’s view (2017). Ryle was not himself interested in laying out necessary (or jointly sufficient) conditions for know-how. His goal was to identify the “logical space” or, more famously, “category” in which talk of know-how belongs. Talk of know-how belongs in a logical space where questions “about learning are applicable—where such questions make sense” (Bäckström & Gustafsson, 2017, 47).

  2. I draw on both Dennett (1975) and Dennett (1995, 373–380) in what follows.

  3. I intend “mere regulation” to track something different from Ryle’s “well-regulated” (see fn. 5). It’s also worth noting that not all biologists use this terminology as I do (e.g. Bich et al., 2016). In this essay, I focus on self-regulation which involves changing one’s default response through learning. A more encompassing account would also incorporate, for example, the more minimal forms of self-regulation described by Peter Railton (2014), which arguably also factor into non-representational or enactivist models of cognition (Van Gelder, 1995; Di Paolo et al., 2017) and views of extended cognition (Clark, 1998).

  4. It’s worth bearing in mind that Dennett considers creatures at successive levels of the Tower of Generate-and-Test to also be members of lower levels. Skinnerian creatures are also Darwinian creatures, subject to the forces of natural selection. I use the qualification “merely” to indicate creatures at their metaphorical ceiling (e.g. before I noted that birds and wasps aren’t merely Darwinian creatures because they are, at least, also Skinnerian).

  5. I suspect this sort of phenomenon is another reason why Ryle associated habit with inflexibility without qualification. He had fairly fixed habits within stable performance circumstances in mind (and this seems to track what he has in mind with the phrase “well-regulated”).

  6. There has also been a push to integrate reinforcement learning frameworks with research on the famous hippocampal map implicated in navigational tasks (see Stachenfeld et al., 2017), and attempts to unify these research programs have been accompanied by a deeper probing into what constitutes a cognitive map (Behrens et al., 2018). Notice that there are currently at least three senses of “cognitive map” at play in the Tolman-inspired literature (Tolman, 1948). In the neuro-computational literature on reinforcement learning, a cognitive map is broadly defined as a “representational template that enables an animal, through mental search, to find the best possible action at a particular state” (Dolan & Dayan, 2013, 313). In research on animal navigation, however, the term “cognitive map” refers either to the hippocampal map or, more generically, to any allocentric model encoding spatial relations between landmarks and goals within an open-field task environment (Geva-Sagiv, 2015; Wehner, 2020). Each of these senses of cognitive map has its roots in Tolman, but they are in principle distinct (see also, Behrens et al., 2018). Failing to keep these distinctions in mind may lead to confusion when approaching partially overlapping research programs. When researchers ask whether hymenopterans, especially desert ants and honeybees, navigate using a cognitive map similar to the famous hippocampal map found in rodents, the sense of cognitive map meaning allocentric model is typically at issue (Wehner, 2020). Research into hymenopteran navigation also focuses on a different kind of flexible choice. Suppose that a displaced ant recognizes a familiar landmark associated with a previously stored home-vector. If it has a cognitive map, it should be able to compute a direct route home based on its current spatial relationship to the landmark and the landmark-home vector stored in memory. In the literature on ant and bee navigation, the capacity to take novel shortcuts of this kind is taken to be the key issue for determining whether hymenopterans possess a cognitive map (Menzel et al., 2005; Cheeseman et al., 2014a). The persistent efforts to explain hymenopteran navigation in terms of egocentric path integration and route-following systems may serve as a potent counterpoint to models that explain “map-like behavior” in terms of more sophisticated representational capacities (Cheung et al., 2014; Hoinville & Wehner, 2018; but see, Cheeseman et al., 2014b; Webb, 2019).

  7. One current limitation of the human origins literature worth noting here is that it tends to assume the common-sense categories of folk psychology and gives little attention to resources from cognitive science which might undermine those categories. In particular, the literature canvassed in this section has not been sufficiently integrated with the neuro-computational frameworks canvassed in the last two sections. Tomasello, for example, distinguishes the flexible behavior of apes from the inflexible behavior of other animals (Tomasello, 2014, 7–9), but he appears to be operating with the common-sense psychological distinction between habit and goal-directed behavior rather than a well-developed research program (Heyes, 2018; Sterelny, 2020, 780).

  8. One might wonder whether the intuition that the second organism lacks know-how would hold if it has the relevant mind tools and brings them to bear cogently on the problem. This would mean that they can produce a propositionally structured model of the task environment and evaluate it by deploying normative language, but that they nevertheless fail to alter their default response within a trial or across multiple trials. This might sound, at first pass, like an incoherent state of affairs. If they understand the situation as I described it and learn that yellow berries are now poisonous, why wouldn’t they try something new? There are conceivable circumstances in which they won’t. One would be a case where an organism with human capacities nevertheless behaves instinctually—an informationally encapsulated module takes over. In other cases, it could be due to a failure of practical rationality or due to weakness of will.

  9. It might, for example, pick out learning opportunities that are appropriate to the learner’s current abilities. Educational theory would be an important resource in fleshing this idea out, though I suspect, for considerations like Hawley’s, that any such metric should allow for somewhat vague boundaries.

References

  • Annas, J. (2001). Moral knowledge as practical knowledge. Social Philosophy and Policy, 18(02), 236–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bäckström, S., & Gustafsson, M. (2017). Skill, drill, and intelligent performance: Ryle and intellectualism. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, 5(5), 41–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balleine, B. W., Daw, N. D., & O’Doherty, J. P. (2009). Multiple forms of value learning and the function of dopamine. In P. W. Glimcher, C. F. Camerer, E. Fehr, & R. A. Poldrack (Eds.), Neuroeconomics (pp. 367–387). Academic Press.

  • Behrens, T. E., Muller, T. H., Whittington, J. C., Mark, S., Baram, A. B., Stachenfeld, K. L., & Kurth-Nelson, Z. (2018). What is a cognitive map? Organizing knowledge for flexible behavior. Neuron, 100(2), 490–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J., & Moffett, M. (2011). The state of play. In J. Bengson, & M. A. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 3–55). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bich, L., Mossio, M., Ruiz-Mirazo, K., & Moreno, A. (2016). Biological regulation: Controlling the system from within. Biology & Philosophy, 31(2), 237–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blumberg, M. S. (2017). Development evolving: The origins and meanings of instinct. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 8(1–2), e1371.

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cath, Y. (2019). Knowing how. Analysis, 79(3), 487–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheeseman, J. F., Millar, C. D., Greggers, U., Lehmann, K., Pawley, M. D., Gallistel, C. R., & Menzel, R. (2014a). Way-finding in displaced clock-shifted bees proves bees use a cognitive map. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 111(24), 8949–8954.

  • Cheeseman, J. F., Millar, C. D., Greggers, U., Lehmann, K., Pawley, M. D., Gallistel, C. R., & Menzel, R. (2014b). Reply to Cheung et al.: The cognitive map hypothesis remains the best interpretation of the data in honeybee navigation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 111(42), E4398–E4398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheung, A., Collett, M., Collett, T. S., Dewar, A., Dyer, F., Graham, P., & Webb, B. (2014). Still no convincing evidence for cognitive map use by honeybees. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 111(42), E4396-E4397.

  • Christensen, W., Sutton, J., & McIlwain, D. J. (2016). Cognition in skilled action: Meshed control and the varieties of skill experience. Mind & Language, 31(1), 37–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1998). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. MIT press.

  • Clark, A. (2006). Language, embodiment, and the cognitive niche. Trends in cognitive sciences, 10(8), 370–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2009). Natural pedagogy. Trends in cognitive sciences, 13(4), 148–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2011). Natural pedagogy as evolutionary adaptation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 366(1567), 1149–1157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F., & Morris, A. (2015). Habitual control of goal selection in humans. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 112(45), 13817–13822.

  • Daw, N. D. (2018). Are we of two minds? Nature neuroscience, 21(11), 1497–1499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daw, N. D., Niv, Y., & Dayan, P. (2005). Uncertainty-based competition between prefrontal and dorsolateral striatal systems for behavioral control. Nature neuroscience, 8(12), 1704–1711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1975). Why the law of effect will not go away. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour, 5, 169–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. Simon and Schuster.

  • Dennett, D. (2000). Making Tools for Thinking. In Metarepresentations., edited by D. Sperber, 17–29. Oxford University Press.

  • Dewsbury, D. A. (1978). What is (was?) The fixed action pattern? Animal Behaviour, 26(1), 310–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., Buhrmann, T., & Barandiaran, X. (2017). Sensorimotor life: An enactive proposal. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, A. (1998). Omission learning after instrumental pretraining. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology: Section B, 51(3), 271–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, A., Nicholas, D. J., & Adams, C. D. (1983). The effect of the instrumental training contingency on susceptibility to reinforcer devaluation. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 35(1), 35–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dolan, R. J., & Dayan, P. (2013). Goals and habits in the brain. Neuron, 80(2), 312–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elzinga, B. (2018). Self-regulation and knowledge how. Episteme, 15(1), 119–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elzinga, B. (2021). Intellectualizing know how. Synthese, 198(2), 1741–1760. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02160-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elzinga, B. (2022). Knowing how to know that. Erkenntnis, 87, 1987–2001. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00286-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, M. P., Schoenbaum, G., & Gershman, S. J. (2018). Rethinking dopamine as generalized prediction error. Proceedings of the Royal Society B, 285(1891), 20181645.

  • Gershman, S. J., & Daw, N. D. (2017). Reinforcement learning and episodic memory in humans and animals: An integrative framework. Annual review of psychology, 68, 101–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geva-Sagiv, M., Las, L., Yovel, Y., & Ulanovsky, N. (2015). Spatial cognition in bats and rats: From sensory acquisition to multiscale maps and navigation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 16(2), 94–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (2002). Authentic intentionality. In M. Scheutz (Ed.), Computationalism: New directions (pp. 159–174). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2003). Success and knowledge-how. American philosophical quarterly, 40(1), 19–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (2018). Cognitive gadgets: The cultural evolution of thinking. Harvard University Press.

  • Hoinville, T., & Wehner, R. (2018). Optimal multiguidance integration in insect navigation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 115(11), 2824–2829.

  • Keijzer, F. (2013). The Sphex story: How the cognitive sciences kept repeating an old and questionable anecdote. Philosophical Psychology, 26(4), 502–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kremer, M. (2016). A capacity to get things right: Gilbert Ryle on knowledge. European Journal of Philosophy, 25(1), 25–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lake, B. M., Ullman, T. D., Tenenbaum, J. B., & Gershman, S. J. (2017). Building machines that learn and think like people. Behavioral and brain sciences, 40, E253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langdon, A. J., Sharpe, M. J., Schoenbaum, G., & Niv, Y. (2018). Model-based predictions for dopamine. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 49, 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liscum, E., & Stowe-Evans, E. L. (2000). Phototropism: A “Simple” physiological response modulated by multiple interacting photosensory‐response pathways. Photochemistry and photobiology, 72(3), 273–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Löwenstein, D. (2017). Know-how as competence: A rylean responsibilist account. Vittorio Klostermann.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, R., Greggers, U., Smith, A., Berger, S., Brandt, R., Brunke, S., & Schüttler, E. (2005). Honey bees navigate according to a map-like spatial memory. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 102(8), 3040–3045.

  • Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2017). The enigma of reason. Harvard University Press.

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, Thought and other Biological categories. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Momennejad, I., Russek, E. M., Cheong, J. H., Botvinick, M. M., Daw, N. D., & Gershman, S. J. (2017). The successor representation in human reinforcement learning. Nature Human Behaviour, 1(9), 680–692.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, M., & Tomaselli, K. (2010). Overimitation in Kalahari Bushman children and the origins of human cultural cognition. Psychological science, 21(5), 729–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Doherty, J. P., Cockburn, J., & Pauli, W. M. (2017). Learning, reward, and decision making. Annual review of psychology, 68, 73–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pavese, C. (2022). Knowledge How. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2022 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2022/entries/knowledge-how/.

  • Railton, P. (2014). Reliance, trust, and belief. Inquiry : A Journal Of Medical Care Organization, Provision And Financing, 57(1), 122–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2008). Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. University of Chicago press.

  • Russek, E. M., Momennejad, I., Botvinick, M. M., Gershman, S. J., & Daw, N. D. (2017). Predictive representations can link model-based reinforcement learning to model-free mechanisms.PLoS computational biology, 13(9), e1005768.

  • Ryle, G. (2002). Ryle’s last letter to Daniel Dennett. The Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 7, 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (2009a). The concept of mind. 60th anniversary edition. Routledge. (Original work published in 1949).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (2009b). Collected essays, 1929–1968 (Vol. 2). Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schleidt, W. M. (1974). How “fixed” is the fixed action pattern? Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie, 36(1-5), 184–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schultz, W., Dayan, P., & Montague, P. R. (1997). A neural substrate of prediction and reward. Science, 275(5306), 1593–1599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, M. E., Railton, P., Baumeister, R. F., & Sripada, C. (2013). Navigating into the future or driven by the past. Perspectives on psychological science, 8(2), 119–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharpe, M. J., Chang, C. Y., Liu, M. A., Batchelor, H. M., Mueller, L. E., Jones, J. L., & Schoenbaum, G. (2017). Dopamine transients are sufficient and necessary for acquisition of model-based associations. Nature Neuroscience, 20(5), 735–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J. (2021). The shape of agency: Control, action, skill, knowledge. Oxford University Press.

  • Skyrms, B. (2004). The stag hunt and the evolution of social structure. Cambridge University Press.

  • Stachenfeld, K. L., Botvinick, M. M., & Gershman, S. J. (2017). The hippocampus as a predictive map. Nature neuroscience, 20(11), 1643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice. MIT press.

  • Sterelny, K. (2020). Afterword: Tough questions; hard problems; incremental progress. Topics in Cognitive Science, 12(2), 766–783.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2021). The Pleistocene Social Contract: Culture and Cooperation in Human Evolution. Oxford University Press.

  • Sutton, R. S., & Barto, A. G. (2018). Reinforcement learning: An introduction. MIT press.

  • Tinebergen, N. (1952). The curious behavior of sticklebacks. Scientific American, 6, 22–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tolman, E. C. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological review, 55(4), 189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2014). A natural history of human thinking. Harvard University Press.

  • Tomasello, M. (2016). Cultural learning redux. Child Development, 87(3), 643–653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., Kruger, A. C., & Ratner, H. H. (1993). Cultural learning. Behavioral and brain sciences, 16(3), 495–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webb, B. (2019). The internal maps of insects. Journal of Experimental Biology, 222(Suppl_1), jeb188094.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wehner, R. (2020). Desert Navigator: The Journey of the ant. Harvard University Press.

  • Wooldridge, D. E. (1963). The machinery of the brain. McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yarrow, K., Brown, P., & Krakauer, J. W. (2009). Inside the brain of an elite athlete: The neural processes that support high achievement in sports. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(8), 585–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. W. (2013). Mindshaping: A new framework for understanding human social cognition. MIT Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Bryce Huebner and Michael Kremer and the anonymous referees for their comments on the ideas developed in this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Benjamin Elzinga.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I have no other conflicts of interest to declare.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Elzinga, B. Know-how and why self-regulation will not go away. Synthese 201, 202 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04168-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04168-5

Keywords

Navigation