Skip to main content
Log in

Conjoined cases

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Incorporating normality ascriptions into counterfactual theories of causation was supposed to handle isomorphs. It doesn’t—conjoining isomorphs can produce cases that such ascriptions cannot resolve.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For simplicity, I limit the account to atomic effects, whereas Halpern (2016, pp. 25, 81) allows for non-atomic effects.

  2. Some authors see the role of intuitions as much less central for the project of defining causation (Beckers & Vennekens, 2018; Clarke, 2023; Glymour et al., 2010; Woodward, 2021); they, of course, may as well welcome a solution that sacrifices one of the intuitions, if this sacrifice is made for good reasons.

  3. On yet another one (Beckers and Vennekens, 2018), causal models are extended with event timing; causal claims depend on both the casual structure of the case and the timing of the events involved. I’ll leave engaging with that proposal for another occasion; I’ll just flag that this strategy is similar to the one from normality in that on both, causal claims hold in virtue on some properties of events beyond the counterfactual structure.

  4. In Sect. 5, I present two theories that use the normality of events but not solutions, Harinen’s (2017) and Gallow’s (2021).

  5. \(\approx \) is the symmetric part of \(\succcurlyeq \).

  6. This also seems to match how the folk make normality ascriptions (Bear & Knobe, 2017; Hitchcock & Knobe, 2009; Wysocki, 2020).

  7. Halpern and Hitchcock (2015) call witnesses (ab)normal and events (a)typical. I use a single term for both.

  8. Act-nrm also mistakenly denies that \(N{=}0\) rather than \(N{=}1\) causes \(T{=}1\) rather than \(T{=}0\); this problem has been already pointed out by Rosenberg and Glymour (2018). However, the current counterexample doesn’t piggyback on that previous problem. Say, you could use \({\mathfrak {M}}_{S{=}\text {-}1 \wedge G{=}0 \wedge N{=}0}\) as a witness to vindicate that \(N{=}0\) rather than \(N{=}1\) causes \(T{=}1\) rather than \(T{=}0\). Because \({\mathfrak {M}}_{S{=}\text {-}1 \wedge G{=}0 \wedge N{=}0}\) shares the solution with \({\mathfrak {M}}_{S{=}\text {-}1 \wedge G{=}0}\), they are equally normal, and the latter could be used as a witness to contradict .

  9. I am indebted to Sander Beckers for suggesting this move.

  10. In and \(\vec {T}'{=}\vec {t}\), I abused the notation; read the expressions as if the assignment on the right side were trimmed to the values of the variables on the left side.

  11. The theory still can handle The Patriarch in their current formulation, but not [6], a non-contrastive version of The Patriarch.

  12. The most convincing reason I see for this requirement is that an intervention cannot bring about a state of affairs that cannot exist, and interventions can bring about any combination of values of different variables.

  13. Gallow (2021), Ross and Woodward (2021), and Hitchcock (2007, p. 527) probably would concur.

  14. The difference between my strategy and his is that, unlike Clarke, I am ready to admit that if the final case elicits unambiguous intuitions inconsistent with the original case, I may have a reason to treat the changes as altering causal relations.

  15. The cases may but needn’t be each other’s isomorphs.

  16. However, Samland and Waldmann (2015, 2016) propose that the influence of normality arises from people interpreting the question of causation with the one of normative responsibility. I am partially partial to this proposal.

References

  • Alicke, M. D., Mandel, D. R., Hilton, D. J., Gerstenberg, T., & Lagnado, D. A. (2015). Causal conceptions in social explanation and moral evaluation: A historical tour. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 10(6), 790–812.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bear, A., & Knobe, J. (2017). Normality: Part descriptive, part prescriptive. Cognition, 167, 25–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beckers, S., & Vennekens, J. (2018). A principled approach to defining actual causation. Synthese, 195(2), 835–862.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blanchard, T., & Schaffer, J. (2017). Cause without default. Making a Difference, 175–214.

  • Clarke, C. (2023). Why your causal intuitions are corrupt: Intermediate and enabling variables. Erkenntnis, 1–29.

  • Clarke, R., Shepherd, J., Stigall, J., Waller, R. R., & Zarpentine, C. (2015). Causation, norms, and omissions: A study of causal judgments. Philosophical Psychology, 28(2), 279–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fenton-Glynn, L. (2017). A proposed probabilistic extension of the halpern and pearl definition of ‘actual cause’. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Gallow, J. D. (2021). A model-invariant theory of causation. Philosophical Review, 130(1), 45–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerstenberg, T., & Icard, T. (2020). Expectations affect physical causation judgments. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 149(3), 599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C., Danks, D., Glymour, B., Eberhardt, F., Ramsey, J., Scheines, R., Spirtes, P., Teng, C. M., & Zhang, J. (2010). Actual causation: a stone soup essay. Synthese, 175, 169–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C., & Wimberly, F. (2007). Actual causes and thought experiments. Causation and Explanation, 4, 43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2007). Structural equations and causation. Philosophical Studies, 132, 109–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J. Y. (2016). Actual Causality. MIT Press.

  • Halpern, J. Y., & Hitchcock, C. (2010). Actual causation and the art of modeling. In Probability causality and heuristics: A tribute to Judea Pearl (pp. 383–406). College Publications.

  • Halpern, J. Y., & Hitchcock, C. (2015). Graded causation and defaults. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Halpern, J. Y., & Pearl, J. (2005). Causes and explanations: A structural-model approach. Part II: Explanations. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Harinen, T. (2017). Normal causes for normal effects: Reinvigorating the correspondence hypothesis about judgments of actual causation. Erkenntnis, 82(6), 1299–1320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henne, P., O’Neill, K., Bello, P., Khemlani, S., & De Brigard, F. (2021). Norms affect prospective causal judgments. Cognitive Science, 45(1), e12931.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henne, P., Pinillos, Á., & De Brigard, F. (2017). Cause by omission and norm: Not watering plants. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95(2), 270–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hiddleston, E. (2005). A causal theory of counterfactuals. Noûs, 39(4), 632–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2001). The intransitivity of causation revealed in equations and graphs. The Journal of Philosophy, 98(6), 273–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2007). Prevention, preemption, and the principle of sufficient reason. Philosophical Review, 116(4), 495–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C., & Knobe, J. (2009). Cause and norm. The Journal of Philosophy, 106(11), 587–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Fraser, B. (2008). Causal judgment and moral judgment: Two experiments. Moral Psychology, 2, 441–447.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kominsky, J. F., & Phillips, J. (2019). Immoral professors and malfunctioning tools: Counterfactual relevance accounts explain the effect of norm violations on causal selection. Cognitive Science, 43(11), e12792.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maslen, C. (2004). Causes, contrasts, and the nontransitivity of causation. In N. Hall, L. A. Paul, & J. Collins (Eds.), Causation and Counterfactuals (pp. 341–357). MIT Press.

  • Maudlin, T. (2004). Causation, counterfactuals, and the third factor. In J. Collins, E. J. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals. MIT Press.

  • McDonald, J. (2023). Essential structure for apt causal models. Australasian Journal of Philosophy (forthcoming).

  • McGrath, S. (2005). Causation by omission: A dilemma. Philosophical Studies, 123(1–2), 125–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (2004). Causal models, token causation, and processes. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 820–832.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (2017). The problem of counterfactual isomorphs. In Making a difference: Essays on the philosophy of causation (pp. 153–174).

  • Northcott, R. (2008). Causation and contrast classes. Philosophical Studies, 139, 111–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A., Hall, N., & Hall, E. J. (2013). Causation: A user’s guide. Oxford University Press.

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning and inference. Cambridge University Press.

  • Rosenberg, I., & Glymour, C. (2018). Review of joseph halpern, actual causality.

  • Ross, L. N., & Woodward, J. F. (2021). Irreversible (one-hit) and reversible (sustaining) causation. Philosophy of Science, 1–10.

  • Samland, J., & Waldmann, M. (2015). Highlighting the causal meaning of causal test questions in contexts of norm violations. In Proceedings of the 37th annual conference of the cognitive science society, pp. 2092–2097.

  • Samland, J., & Waldmann, M. (2016). How prescriptive norms influence causal inferences. Cognition, 156, 164–176.

  • Schaffer, J. (2005). Contrastive causation. Philosophical Review, 114(3), 327–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spirtes, P., Glymour, C. N., & Scheines, R. (2000). Causation, Prediction, and Search. Mit Press.

  • Thomson, J. J. (2003). Causation: Omissions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(1), 81–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weslake, B. (2015). A partial theory of actual causation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Wolff, J. E. (2016). Using defaults to understand token causation. Journal of Philosophy, 113(1), 5–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press.

  • Woodward, J. (2021). Causation with a human face: Normative theory and descriptive psychology. Oxford University Press.

  • Wysocki, T. (2020). Normality: A two-faced concept. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 11(4), 689–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper benefited greatly from the feedback of friends and foes alike: Colin Allen (and the feedback group he organized), Dmitri Gallow, JP Gamboa, Eric Hiddleston, Caitlin Mace, Katie Morrow, Jim Woodward, and the audiences at the 2021 PSA and the 2022 Central APA. Above all, I am grateful to the reviewers for their thorough suggestions. One of the reviewers, who later turned out to be Sander Beckers, proposed how to amend my cases so they work against any normality ordering of solutions, not only standard ones. Amending the cases made the argument much stronger, as it now targets any present or future theory that relies on ordering solutions according to their normality. I wish every author a reviewer like Sander. This work was supported by the Chateaubriand Fellowship of the Office for Science & Technology of the Embassy of France in the United States and a Reinhart Koselleck project (WA 621/25-1), funded by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tomasz Wysocki.

Ethics declarations

Conflicts of Interest

None declared.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wysocki, T. Conjoined cases. Synthese 201, 197 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04101-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-023-04101-w

Keywords

Navigation