Skip to main content
Log in

Two epistemological challenges regarding hypothetical modeling

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Sometimes, scientific models are either intended to or plausibly interpreted as representing nonactual but possible targets. Call this “hypothetical modeling”. This paper raises two epistemological challenges concerning hypothetical modeling. To begin with, I observe that given common philosophical assumptions about the scope of objective possibility, hypothetical models are fallible with respect to what is objectively possible. There is thus a need to distinguish between accurate and inaccurate hypothetical modeling. The first epistemological challenge is that no account for the epistemology of hypothetical models seems to cohere with the most characteristic function of scientific modeling in general, i.e., surrogative representation. The second epistemological challenge is a version of “reliability challenges” familiar from other areas. There is a challenge to explain how hypothetical models could be a reliable guide to what is possible, given that they are not and cannot be compared against their nonactual targets and updated accordingly. I close with some brief remarks on possible solutions to these challenges.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a dissenting view, see Verreault-Julien (forthcoming).

  2. Sometimes, discussions of hypothetical modeling include exploratory models, which I intend to ignore here – my focus is only on the uses of hypothetical models which appear to be focused on objective possibilities rather than epistemic possibilities. (See Grüne-Yanoff and Sjölin Wirling forthcoming for some excellent discussion.) Likewise, philosophers sometimes refer to hypothetical models as providing “how-possibly” explanations. But these discussions often assume or contest certain background assumptions regarding the nature of scientific explanation. Again, I wish to sidestep these issues and focus only on the kinds of modeling practices that are either aimed at or plausibly interpreted as representing objective possibilities.

  3. Of course, some of these idealizations might “seem” less impossible than others. For instance, the behavior of frictionless planes, while nonactual, is quite easily epistemically accessible. We can simply extend the curve of an observed surface as its friction decreases to the hypothetical limit where there is no friction. However, the fact that these idealizations are epistemically accessible should not make us think that they are any less impossible: friction results from intermolecular electromagnetism, so, for there to be no friction, there would need to be different fundamental forces than there actually are – hence the idealization is still nomologically impossible. Thanks to a referee for pressing me on this point.

  4. For those worried about my use of “imagination” as a rough-and-ready source of evidence regarding modality here, I am happy to concede that imagination is an unreliable source of evidence about what is possible: in fact, this only strengthens my overall concerns. See Sect. 4 below.

  5. It is worth noting that van Riel (2015) is overall quite sympathetic to these worries.

  6. Many thanks to a referee for this framing.

  7. Thanks to an anonymous referee for pressing me on this point.

  8. See Hirvonen et al., (2021, p. 13831) for an observation-only example regarding Alexander Fleming’s eventual development of penicillin.

  9. Thanks to Till Grüne-Yanoff for pushing me to clarify this point. See also Grüne-Yanoff 2013, p857 for an example of the confirmatory value of simulation from historical anthropology.

  10. See also Sjölin Wirling (2021, p. 475, fn5), Sjölin Wirling and Grüne-Yanoff (2021, §6). Although, as Fischer (2017, §2.4) notes, depending on which sorts of things count as theories, there might be more of a way to integrate these kinds of cases with the theory-based epistemology of modality. Maybe the Arrow-Debreu model by itself constitutes a theory. However, it is worth noting that when it comes to scientific theories, Fischer endorses the semantic view of theories, according to which theories are collections of models. And under the semantic view, it still looks like at least at the initial time of publication, the Arrow-Debreu model conflicted with the established theory, and didn’t itself constitute a theory (since presumably a single model does not constitute a theory). Still, there may be more to say here.

  11. This is not to say that the only factors that help decide whether some model is credible or imaginable are those that are intrinsic to the model. Consistency with existing theory or empirical knowledge can help explain why it is that something seems credible or imaginable (e.g., Kung 2010). Thanks to Till Grüne-Yanoff for this point.

  12. See Korman (2019) for an excellent survey of this literature. Another example besides the one mentioned here is “evolutionary debunking” in moral epistemology. If non-naturalist moral realism is correct, then even if all of our ordinary moral beliefs are true, they face a reliability challenge (see Vavova, 2015 for an overview of this extensive literature). For the explanation for why we come to have our moral beliefs would presumably be due to selection factors over the long course of human evolutionary history, which is to say, the non-natural moral properties would not enter at all into the explanation for why we have the moral beliefs we do. And if so, there needs to be an explanation for how those beliefs could manage to coincide so miraculously with the moral facts. Absent such an explanation, one naturally worries that those moral beliefs are unjustified even if they are true.

  13. Importantly, this opens the path to a possible response—more on this later, in the concluding section of the paper.

  14. I am not the first person to observe that a reliability challenge arises for knowledge of modality. The “integration challenge” (Peacocke 1999) in modal epistemology often presented as a version of a reliability challenge as well; for discussion of both integration and reliability challenges, see Thomasson (2018), Wang (2018), and Sjölin Wirling (2021), among many others.

  15. And if there are such cases, the “surrogacy challenge” raised in the previous sections will also be easy to answer.

  16. Thanks to Grüne-Yanoff and Verreault-Julien (2021, p. 119) for bringing these references to my attention.

References

  • Bokulich, A. (2011). How scientific models can explain. Synthese, 180(1), 33–45. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9565-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke-Doane, J. (2022). Mathematics and metaphilosophy. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2002). Varieties of necessity. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and possibility. pp. 253–281.

  • Fischer, B. (2016). A theory-based epistemology of modality. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46(2), 228–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, B. (2017). Modal justification via theories. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. & Nguyen, J. (2017). Models and representation. In L. Magnani & T. Bertolotti (eds.), Springer handbook of model-based science. pp. 49–102.

  • Frisch, M. (2015). Users, structures, and representation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(2), 285–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelfert, A. (2019). Probing possibilities: toy models, minimal models, and exploratory models. In M. Fontaine, C. Barés-Gómez, F. Salguero-Lamillar, L. Magnani & Á. Nepomuceno-Fernández (eds.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology. Springer.

  • Giere, R. N. (2004). How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 742–752.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2010). An agent-based conception of models and scientific representation. Synthese, 172(2), 269–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2009). Learning from minimal economic models. Erkenntnis, 70(1), 81–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2013). Appraising models nonrepresentationally. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 850–861. https://doi.org/10.1086/673893

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T., & Verreault-Julien, P. (2021). How-possibly explanations in economics: Anything goes? Journal of Economic Methodology, 28(1), 114–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D. W. (2016). Derivational robustness, credible substitute systems and mathematical economic models: The case of stability analysis in Walrasian general equilibrium theory. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 6(1), 31–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirvonen, I., Koskinen, R., & Pättiniemi, I. (2021). Modal inferences in science: A tale of two epistemologies. Synthese, 199(5–6), 13823–13843.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. (1997). Models and representation. Philosophy of Science, 64(4), 336.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacquart, M. (2020). Observations, simulations, and reasoning in astrophysics. Philosophy of Science, 87(5), 1209–1220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jhun, J. S. (2018). What’s the point of ceteris paribus? or, how to understand supply and demand curves. Philosophy of Science, 85(2), 271–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T. and Loettgers, A. (2022). (Un)Easily possible synthetic biology. Philosophy of Science.

  • Korman, D. Z. (2019). Debunking arguments. Compass, 14(12), 89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kung, P. (2016). You really do imagine it: Against error theories of imagination. Noûs, 50(1), 90–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2015). Modeling without models. Philosophical Studies, 172(3), 781–798.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki, U. (2009). Missing the world: Models as isolations and credible surrogate systems. Erkenntnis, 70(1), 29–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massimi, M. (2019). Two kinds of exploratory models. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 869–881.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith, J., & Price, G. R. (1973). The logic of animal conflict. Nature, 246(5427), 15–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLoone, B. (2020). Calculus and counterpossibles in science. Synthese, 198(12), 12153–12174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nguyen, J. (2020). It’s not a game: Accurate representation with toy models. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71(3), 1013–1041.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, W. S. (2017). Computer simulation measurement and data assimilation. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68(1), 273–304. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axv037

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potochnik, A. (2009). Optimality modeling in a suboptimal world. Biology and Philosophy, 24(2), 183–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rami, K. (2017). Synthetic biology and the search for alternative genetic systems: Taking how-possibly models seriously. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 7(3), 493–506.

  • Reutlinger, A., Hangleiter, D., & Hartmann, S. (2018). Understanding (with) toy models. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69(4), 1069–1099.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rice, C. (2015). Moving beyond causes: Optimality models and scientific explanation. Noûs, 49(3), 589–615.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rice, C. C. (2012). Optimality explanations: A plea for an alternative approach. Biology and Philosophy, 27(5), 685–703.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohwer, Y., & Rice, C. (2013). Hypothetical pattern idealization and explanatory models. Philosophy of Science, 80(3), 334–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2003). Reductive theories of modality. In M. J. Loux & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), The oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 180–208). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sjölin-Wirling, Y. (2021). Is credibility a guide to possibility? A challenge for toy models in science. Analysis, 81(3), 470–478.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sjölin-Wirling, Y., & Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2021). The epistemology of modal modeling. Philosophy Compass, 16(10), 12775.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sjölin Wirling, Y & Grüne-Yanoff, T. (forthcoming). Epistemic and objective possibility in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.

  • Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71(5), 767–779.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2015). Deflationary representation inference and practice. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A ,49, 36–47. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsa.2014.11.001

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: The status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7(1), 1–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2009). Credible worlds, capacities and mechanisms. Erkenntnis, 70(1), 3–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szabo Gendler, T. & Hawthorne, J. (eds.) (2002). Conceivability and possibility. Oxford University Press.

  • Tan, P. (2019). Counterpossible non-vacuity in scientific practice. Journal of Philosophy, 116(1), 32–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. L. (2018). How can we come to know metaphysical modal truths? Synthese, 198(Suppl 8), 2077–2106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaidya, A. J., & Wallner, M. (2021). The epistemology of modality and the problem of modal epistemic friction. Synthese, 198(Suppl 8), 1909–1935.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Riel, R. (2015). The content of model-based information. Synthese, 192(12), 3839–3858.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vavova, K. (2015). Evolutionary debunking of moral realism. Philosophy Compass, 10(2), 104–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verreault-Julien, P. (2017). Non-causal understanding with economic models: The case of general equilibrium. Journal of Economic Methodology, 24(3), 297–317.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verreault-Julien, Philippe (forthcoming). Representing non-actual targets? Philosophy of Science:1–10.

  • Wang, J. (2018). The epistemological objection to modal primitivism. Synthese, 198(Suppl 8), 1887–1898.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2016). Modal science. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46(4–5), 453–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J., & Hitchcock, C. (2003). Explanatory generalizations, part I: A counterfactual account. Noûs, 37(1), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

A predecessor of this paper was presented at Till Grüne-Yanoff and Ylwa Sjölin Wirling’s workshop “Modal Modeling in the Sciences,” as well as at the University of Birmingham and Fordham University. Thanks to audiences at all these venues for comments on the paper, including Otavio Bueno, Mike Hicks, Brian McLoone, and others. Thanks also to Jonathan Barker, Harjit Bhogal, and Jenn Wang for discussion of this paper. And finally, special thanks to two referees, Philippe Verreault-Julien, and to both Till Grüne-Yanoff and Ylwa Sjölin Wirling for their detailed comments on this paper, and for organizing a great workshop.

Funding

This research was not supported by any external funding.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Tan.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I have no conflicts of interest to report.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Tan, P. Two epistemological challenges regarding hypothetical modeling. Synthese 200, 448 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03928-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-022-03928-z

Keywords

Navigation